AMERICAN SCIENCE SERIES— AD VANCED COURSE THE PRINCIPLES OF PSYCHOLOGY WILLIAM JAMES PROFESSOR OF PSYCHOLOGY IN HARVARD UNIVERSITY IN TWO VOLUMES VOL. II NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1905 Ul V * £-» Copyright, 1P90 BY HENRY HOLT & CO. HOBERT DRTIMMOND, ELECTROTYPER AND PRINTER, NEW YORE CONTENTS. CHAPTER XVII. PAOK SENSATION, . . . . ' . . . . .1 Its distinction from perception, 1. Its cognitive function — acquaintance with qualities, 3. No pure sensations after the first days of life, 7. The 'relativity of knowledge/ 9. The law of contrast, 13. The psychological and the physiological theories of it, 17. Bering's experiments, 20. The ' eccentric projection ' of sensations, 31. CHAPTER XVIII. IMAGINATION, 44 Our images are usually vague, 45. Vague images not neces sarily general notions, 48. Individuals differ in imagination ; Gallon's researches, 50, The 'visile' type, 58. The 'audile' type, 60. The 'motile' type, 61. Tactile images. 65. The neural process of imagination, 68. Its relations to that of sensation, 72. CHAPTER XIX. THE PERCEPTION OF ( THINGS/ 76 Perception and sensation, 76. Perception is of definite and probable things, 82. Illusions, 85 ;— of the first type, 86 ;— of the second type, 95. The neural process in perception, 103. 'Apperception,' 107. Is perception an unconscious inference? 111. Hallucinations, 114. The neural process in hallucination, 122. Binet's theory, 129. ' Perception-time/ 131. CHAPTER XX. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE, 134 The feeling of crude extensity, 134. The perception of spatial order, 145. Space-' relations,' 148. The meaning of localization, 153. 'Local signs.' 155. The construction of ' real ' space, 166. The subdivision of the original sense-spaces, 167. The sensation iii iv CONTENTS. PAGS of motion over surfaces, 171. The measurement of the sense- spaces by each other, 177. Their summation, 181. Feelings of movement in joints, 189. Feelings of muscular contraction, 197. Summary so far, 202. How the blind perceive space, 203. Visual space, 211. Helmholtz and Reid on the test of a sensation, 216. The theory of identical points, 222. The theory of projection, 228. Ambiguity of retinal impressions, 231 ; — of eye-movements, 234. The choice of the visual reality, 237. Sensations which we ignore, 240. Sensations which seem suppressed, 243. Dis cussion of Wundt's and Helmholtz's reasons for denying that retinal sensations are of extension, 248. Summary, 268. His torical remarks, 270. CHAPTER XXL THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY, 283 Belief and its opposites, 283. The various orders of reality, 287. ' Practical ' realities, 293. The sense of our own bodily existence is the nucleus of all reality, 297. The paramount reality of sensations, 299. The influence of emotion and active impulse on belief, 307. Belief in theories, 311. Doubt, 318. Relations of belief and will, 320. CHAPTER XXII. REASONING, 323 ' Recepts,' 327. In reasoning, we pick out essential qualities, 329. What is meant by a mode of conceiving, 332. What is involved in the existence of general propositions, 337. The two factors of reasoning, 340. Sagacity, 343. The part played by association by similarity, 345. The intellectual contrast between brute and man : association by similarity the fundamental human distinction, 348. Different orders of human genius, 360. CHAPTER XXIII. THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT, 373 The diffusive wave, 373. Every sensation produces reflex effects on the whole organism, 374. CHAPTER XXIV. INSTINCT, 383 Its definition, 383 Instincts not always blind or invariable, 389. Two principles of non -uniformity in instincts : 1) Their inhibition by habits, 394 ; 2) Their transitoriness, 398. Man has CONTENTS. V PAGE more instincts than any other mammal, 403. Reflex impulses, 404. Imitation, 408. Emulation, 409. Pugnacity, 409. Sym pathy, 410. The hunting instinct, 411. Fear, 415. Acquisitive ness, 422. Constructiveness, 426. Play, 427. Curiosity, 429. Sociability and shyness, 430. Secretiveness, 432. Cleanliness, 434. Shame, 435. Love, 437. Maternal love, 439. CHAPTEK XXV. THE EMOTIONS, 442 Instinctive reaction and emotional expression shade imper ceptibly into each other, 442. The expression of grief, 443 ; of fear, 446 ; of hatred, 449. Emotion is a consequence, not the cause, of the bodily expression, 449. Difficulty of testing this view, 454. Objections to it discussed, 456. The subtler emotions, 468. No special brain-centres for emotion, 472. Emotional dif ferences between individuals, 474. The genesis of the various emotions, 477. CHAPTER XXVI. WILL, . . 486 Voluntary movements : they presuppose a memory of invol untary movements, 487. Kinaesthetic impressions, 488. No need to assume feelings of innervation, 503. The ' mental cue ' for a movement may be an image of its visual or auditory effects as well as an image of the way it feels, 518. Ideo motor action, 522. Action after deliberation, 528. Five types of decision, 531. The feeling of effort, 535. Unhealthiness of will : 1) The ex plosive type, 537 ; 2) The obstructed type, 546. Pleasure and pain are not the only springs of action, 549. All consciousness is impulsive, 551. What we will depends on what idea dominates in our mind, 559. The idea's outward effects follow from the cerebral machinery, 560. Effort of attention to a naturally repugnant idea is the essential feature of willing, 562. The free-will controversy, 571. Psychology, as a science, can safely postulate determinism, even if free-will be true, 576. The edu cation of the Will, 579. Hypothetical brain-schemes, 582. CHAPTER XXVII. HYPNOTISM, , 594-616 Modes of operating and susceptibility, 594. Theories about the hypnotic state, 596. The symptoms of the trance, 601. vi CONTENTS. CHAPTER XXVIIL PAOK NECESSARY TRUTHS AND THE EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE, . 617 Programme of the chapter, 617. Elementary feelings are innate, 618. The question refers to their combinations, 619. What is meant by 'experience,' 620. Spencer on ancestral ex perience, 620. Two ways in which new cerebral structure arises : the 'back-door' and the 'front-door' way, 625. The genesis of the elementary mental categories, 631. The genesis of the natural sciences, 633. Scientific conceptions arise as accidental variations, 636. The genesis of the pure sciences, 641. Series of evenly increasing terms, 644. The principle of mediate compari son, 645. That of skipped intermediaries, 646. Classification, 646. Predication, 647. Formal logic, 648. Mathematical propositions, 652. Arithmetic, 653. Geometry, 656. Our doc trine is the same as Locke's, 661. Relations of ideas v. couplings of things, 663. The natural sciences are inward ideal schemes with which the order of nature proves congruent, 666. Meta physical principles are properly only postulates, 669. ^Esthetic and moral principles are quite incongruent with the order of nature, 672. Summary of what precedes, 675. The origin of instincts, 678. Insufficiency of proof for the transmission to the next generation of acquired habits, 681. Weismann's views, 683. Conclusion, 688. PSYCHOLOGY. CHAPTER XVII. SENSATION. AFTEB inner perception, outer perception ! The next three chapters will treat of the processes by which we cog nize at all times the present world of space and the mate rial things which it contains. And first, of the process called Sensation. SENSATION AND PEKCEPTION DISTINGUISHED. The ivords Sensation and Perception do not carry very definitely discriminated meanings in popular speech, and in Psychology also their meanings run into each other. Both of them name processes in which we cognize an objective world; both (under normal conditions) need the stimula tion of incoming nerves ere they can occur ; Perception always involves Sensation as a portion of itself ; and Sensa tion in turn never takes place in adult life without Percep tion also being there. They are therefore names for dif ferent cognitive functions, not for different sorts of mental fact. The nearer the object cognized comes to being a simple quality like 'hot,' 'cold,' 'red,' 'noise,' 'pain,' ap prehended irrelatively to other things, the more the state of mind approaches pure sensation. The fuller of relations the object is, on the contrary ; the more it is something classed, located, measured, compared, assigned to a func tion, etc., etc.; the more unreservedly do we call the state of mind a perception, and the relatively smaller is the part in it which sensation plays. Sensation, then, so long as we take the analytic point of 2 PSYCHOLOGY. view differs from Perception only in the extreme simplicity of its Meet or content* Its function is that of mere acquaintance with a fact. Perception's function, on the other hand, is knowledge about t a fact; and this knowledge admits of numberless degrees of complication. But in both sensa tion and perception we perceive the fact as an immediately present outward reality, and this makes them differ from •thought' and 'conception,' whose objects do not appeal- present in this immediate physical way. From the physio- * Some persons will say that we never have a really simple object or content My definition of sensation does not require the simplicity to be absolutely but only relatively, extreme. It is worth while in passing, fowever^o warn the reader against a couple of inferences that are often made One is that because we gradually learn to analyze so many quali ties we ouzht to conclude that there are no really indecomposable feelings i the mind The other is that because the processes that produce our sen sations are multiple, the sensations regarded as subjective facts must also Te compound. To take an example, to a child the taste of lemonade comes at first as a simple quality. He later learns both that many stimuli and manv nerves are involved in the exhibition of this taste to his mind, and he also learns to perceive separately the sourness, the coolness, the sweet the lemon aroma, etc., and the several degrees of strength of each and all of these things.-the experience falling into a large number of aspects, each of which is abstracted, classed, named, etc., and all of which appear to be the elementary sensations into which the original 'lemonade flavor is decomposed. It is argued from this that the latter never was tne simple thing which it seemed. I have already criticised this sort of reasoning in Chapter VI (see pp. 170 ff.). The mind of the child enjoying the simple lemonade flavor and that of the same child grown up and analyzing it are in two entirely different conditions. Subjectively considered, the two states of mind are two altogether distinct sorts of fact. The later mental state says ^this is the same flavor (or fluid) which that earlier state per ceived as simple/but that does not make the two states themselves identical. Tt is nothing but a case of learning more and more about the same topics of discourse or things. -Many of these topics, however, must be confessed to resist all analysis, the various colors for example. He who sees blue and yellow 'in 'a certain green means merely that when green is confront. with these other colors he sees relations of similarity. He who sees abstract •color ' in it means merely that he sees a similarity between it and all the other objects known as colors. (Similarity itself cannot ultimately be ac counted for by an identical abstract element buried in all the similars, as has been already shown, p. 492 ff .) He who sees abstract paleness, inten sity, purity, in the green means other similarities still. These are all out ward determinations of that special green, knowledges about it, zufalligeAn- tichten, as Herbart would say, not elements of its composition. Compare the article by Meinong in the Vierteljahrschrift filr wiss. Phil., xn. 324. f See above, p. 221. SENSATION. 3 logical point of view both sensations and perceptions differ from 1 thoughts ' (in the narrower sense of the word) in the fact that nerve-currents coming in from tJie periphery are involved in their production. In perception these nerve-currents arouse volumi nous associative or reproductive processes in the cortex; but ivhen sensation occurs alone, or with a minimum of perception, the ac companying reproductive processes are at a minimum too. I shall in this chapter discuss some general questions more especially relative to Sensation. In a later chapter perception will take its turn. I shall entirely pass by the classification and natural history of our special * sensa tions,' such matters finding their proper place, and being sufficiently well treated, in all the physiological books.* THE COGNITIVE FUNCTION OF SENSATION. A pure sensation is an abstraction; and when we adults talk of our ' sensations ' we mean one of two things : either certain objects, namely simple qualities or attributes like hard, hot, pain; or else those of our thoughts in which acquaintance with these objects is least combined with knowledge about the relations of them to other things. As we can only think or talk about the relations of objects with which we have acquaintance already, we are forced to postulate a function in our thought whereby we first become aware of the bare immediate natures by which our several objects are distinguished. This function is sensation. And just as logicians always point out the distinction between substantive terms of discourse and relations found to obtain between them, so psychologists, as a rule, are ready to admit this function, of the vision of the terms or matters meant, as something distinct from the knowledge about them and of their relations inter se. Thought with the former function is sensational, with the latter, intellec tual. Our earliest thoughts are almost exclusively sensa tional. They merely give us a set of thats, or its, of subjects * Those who wish a fuller treatment than Martin's Human Body affords may be recommended to Bernstein's * Five Senses of Man, 'in the Interna tional Scientific Series, or to Ladd's or Wundt's Physiological Psychology. The completest compendium is L. Hermann's Handbuch der Physiologic, vol. m. 4 PSYCHOLOGY. of discourse, with their relations not brought out. The first time we see light, in Condillac's phrase we are it rather rather than see it. But all our later optical knowledge is about what this experience gives. And though we were struck blind from that first moment, our scholarship in the subject would lack no essential feature so long as our mem ory remained. In training-institutions for the blind they teach the pupils as much about light as in ordinary schools Keflection, refraction, the spectrum, the ether-theory, etc., are all studied. But the best taught born-blind pupil of such an establishment yet lacks a knowledge which the least instructed seeing baby has. They can never show him what light is in its ' first intention ' ; and the loss of that sensible knowledge no book-learning can replace. All this is so obvious that we usually find sensation * postulated ' as an element of experience, even by those philosophers who are least inclined to make much of its importance, or to pay respect to the knowledge which it brings.* * " The sensations which we postulate as the signs or occasions of our perceptions" (A. Seth: Scottish Philosophy, p. 89). "Their existence is supposed only because, without them, it would be impossible to account for the complex phenomena which are directly present in consciousness " (J. Dewey: Psychology, p. 34). Even as great an enemy of Sensation as. T. H. Green has to allow it a sort of hypothetical existence under protest. " Perception presupposes feeling " (Contemp. Review, vol. xxxi. p. 747)» Cf. also such passages as those in his Prolegomena to Ethics, §§ 48, 49. — Physiologically, the sensory and the reproductive or associative processes, may wax and wane independently of each other. Where the part directly due to stimulation of the sense-organ preponderates, the thought has a sensational character, and differs from other thoughts in the sensational direction. Those thoughts which lie farthest in that direction we call sen sations, for practical convenience, just as we call conceptions those which lie nearer the opposite extreme. But we no more have conceptions pure than we have pure sensations. Our most rarefied intellectual states involve some bodily sensibility, just as our dullest feelings have some intellectual scope. Common-sense and common psychology express this by saying that the mental state is composed of distinct fractional parts, one of which is sensation, the other conception. We, however, who believe t!very mental state to be an integral thing (p. 276) cannot talk thus, but must speak of the degree of sensational or intellectual character, or function, oJ the mental state. Professor Bering puts, as usual, his finger better upon the truth than anyone else. Writing of visual perception, he says: "It is inadmissible in the present state of our knowledge to assert that first and last the same retinal picture arouses exactly the same pure sensation. SENSATION. 0 But the trouble is that most, if not all, of those who admit it, admit it as a fractional part of the thought, in the old-fashioned atomistic sense which we have so often criti cised. Take the pain called toothache for example. Again and again we feel it and greet it as the same real item in the universe. We must therefore, it is supposed, have a distinct pocket for it in our mind into which it and nothing else will fit. This pocket, when filled, is the sensation of toothache ; and must be either filled or half-filled whenever and under whatever form toothache is present to our thought, and whether much or little of the rest of the mind be filled at the same time. Thereupon of course comes up the paradox and mystery : If the knowledge of toothache be pent up in this separate mental pocket, how can it be known cum olio or brought into one view with anything else ? This pocket knows nothing else ; no other part of the mind knows toothache. The knowing of tooth ache cum olio must be a miracle. And the miracle must have an Agent. And the Agent must be a Subject or Ego ' out of time,' — and all the rest of it, as we saw in Chapter X. And then begins the well-worn round of recrimination between the sensationalists and the spiritualists, from which we are saved by our determination from the outset to accept the psychological point of view, and to admit knowledge whether of simple toothaches or of philosophic systems as an ultimate fact. There are realities and there are ' states of mind,' and the latter know the former ; and it is just as wonderful for a state of mind to be a ' sensation ' and know a simple pain as for it to be a thought and know a system but that this sensation, in consequence of practice and experience, is differ ently interpreted the last time, and elaborated into a different perception from the first. For the only real data are, on the one hand, the physical picture on the retina, — and that is both times the same; and, on the other hand, the resultant state of consciousness (ausgeloste Empjindungscomplex) — and that is both times distinct. Of any third thing, namely, a pure sen sation thrust between the retinal and the mental pictures, we know nothing. We can then, if we wish to avoid all hypothesis, only say that the nervous appa ratus reacts upon the same stimulus differently the last time from the first, and that in consequence the consciousness is different too." (Hermann's Hdbch., ni. i. 567-8.) 6 PSYCHOLOGY. of related things.* But there is no reason to suppose that when different states of mind know different things about the same toothache, they do so by virtue of their all con taining faintly or vividly the original pain. Quite the re verse. The by -gone sensation of my gout was painful, as Keid somewhere says ; the thought of the same gout as by gone is pleasant, and in no respect resembles the earlier mental state. Sensations, then, first make us acquainted with innu merable things, and then are replaced by thoughts which know the same things in altogether other ways. And Locke's main doctrine remains eternally true, however hazy some of his language may have been, that " though there be a great number of considerations wherein things may be compared one with another, and so a multitude of relations ; yet they all terminate in, and are concerned about, those simple ideas f either of sensation or reflection, which I think to be the whole materials of all our knowledge. . . . The simple ideas we receive from sensation and reflection are the boundaries of our thoughts ; beyond which, the mind whatever efforts it would make, is not able to advance one jot ; nor can it make any discoveries when it would pry into the nature and hidden causes of those ideas." | The nature and hidden causes of ideas will never be unravelled till the nexus between the brain and conscious ness is cleared up. All we can say now is that sensations me first things in the way of consciousness. Before con ceptions can come, sensations must have come ; but before sensations come, no psychic fact need have existed, a nerve- current is enough. If the nerve-current be not given, nothing else will take its place. To quote the good Locke again : "It is not in the power of the most exalted wit or enlarged under standing, by any quickness or variety of thoughts, to invent or frame * Yet even writers like Prof. Bain will deny, in the most gratuitous way, that sensations know anything. "It is evident that the lowest or most restricted form of sensation does not contain an element of knowl edge. The mere state of mind called the sensation of scarlet is not knowl edge, although a necessary preparation for it. " ' Is not knowledge about scarlet ' is all that Professor Bain can rightfully say. f By simple ideas of sensation Locke merely means sensations. j Essay c. H. U., bk. n. ch. xxm. § 29 ; ch. xxv. § 9. SENSATION. 7 one new simple idea [i.e. sensation] in the mind. ... I would have any one try to fancy any taste which had never affected his palate, or frame the idea of a scent he had never smelt ; and when he can do this, I will also conclude that a blind man hath ideas of colors, and a deaf man true distinct notions of sounds." * The brain is so made that all currents in it run one way. Consciousness of some sort goes with all the currents, but it is only when new currents are entering that it has the sensational tang. And it is only then that consciousness directly encounters (to use a word of Mr. Bradley 's) a real ity outside itself. The difference between such encounter and all concep tual knowledge is very great. A blind man may know all about the sky's blueness, and I may know all about your toothache, conceptually ; tracing their causes from primeval chaos, and their consequences to the crack of doom. But so long as he has not felt the blueness, nor I the toothache, our knowledge, wide as it is, of these realities, will be hollow and inadequate. Somebody must feel blueness, somebody must have toothache, to make human knowledge of these matters real. Conceptual systems which neither began nor left off in sensations would be like bridges without piers. Systems about fact must plunge themselves into sensation as bridges plunge their piers into the rock. Sensations are the stable rock, the terminus a quo and the terminus ad quern of thought. To find such termini is our aim with all our theories — to conceive first when and where a certain sensa tion may be had, and then to have it. Finding it stops dis cussion. Failure to find it kills the false conceit of knowledge. Only when you deduce a possible sensation for me from your theory, and give it to me when and where the theory requires, do I begin to be sure that your thought has anything to do with truth. Pure sensations can only be realized in the earliest days of life. They are all but impossible to adults with memories and stores of associations acquired. Prior to all impressions on sense-organs the brain is plunged in deep sleep and con sciousness is practically non-existent. Even the first weeks * Op. cit. bk. ii. ch. ii. § 2. 8 PSYCHOLOGY. after birth are passed in almost unbroken sleep by human infants. It takes a strong message from the sense-organs to break this slumber. In a new-born brain this gives rise to an absolutely pure sensation. But the experience leaves its ' unimaginable touch ' on the matter of the convolutions, and the next impression which a sense-organ transmits produces a cerebral reaction in which the awakened vestige of the last impression plays its part. Another sort of feel ing and a higher grade of cognition are the consequence ; and the complication goes on increasing till the end of life, no two successive impressions falling on ?,A identical brain, and no two successive thoughts being exactly the same. (See above, p. 230 ff.) The first sensation which an infant gets is for him thz Uni verse. And the Universe which he later comes to know is nothing but an amplification and an implication of that first simple germ which, by accretion on the one hand and in tussusception on the other, has grown so big and complex and articulate that its first estate is unrememberable. In his dumb awakening to the consciousness of something there, a mere this as yet (or something for which even the term this would perhaps be too discriminative, and the intellec tual acknowledgment of which would be better expressed by the bare interjection ' lo ! '), the infant encounters an ob ject in which (though it be given in a pure sensation) all the * categories of the understanding ' are contained. It has objectivity, unity, substantiality, causality, in the full sense in ivhich any later object or system of objects has these things. Here the young knower meets and greets his world ; and the miracle of knowledge bursts forth, as Voltaire says, as much in the infant's lowest sensation as in the highest achievement of a Newton's brain. The physiological con dition of this first sensible experience is probably nerve- currents coming in from many peripheral organs at once. Later, the one confused Fact which these currents cause to appear is perceived to be many facts, and to contain many qualities.* For as the currents vary, and the brain-paths * " So far is it from being true that we necessarily have as many feel ings in consciousness at one time as there are inlets to the sense then played upon, that it is a fundamental law of pure sensation that each momentary SENSATION. 9 are moulded by them, other thoughts with other * objects ' come, and the ' same thing ' which was apprehended as a present this soon figures as a past that, about which many unsuspected things have come to light. The principles of this development have been laid down already in Chapters XII and XIII, and nothing more need here be added to that account. "THE KELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE." To the reader who is tired of so much Erkenntnisstheorie I can only say that I am so myself, but that it is indispen sable, in the actual state of opinions about Sensation, to try to clear up just what the word means. Locke's pupils seek to do the impossible with sensations, and against them we must once again insist that sensations ' clustered together ' cannot build up our more intellectual states of mind. Plato's earlier pupils used to admit Sensation's existence, grudgingly, but they trampled it in the dust as something corporeal, non-cognitive, and vile.* His latest followers state of the organism yields but one feeling, however numerous may be its parts and its exposures. ... To this original Unity of consciousness it makes no difference that the tributaries to the single feeling are beyond the organ, ism instead of within it, in an outside object with several sensible proper ties, instead of in the living body with its several sensitive functions. . . . The unity therefore is not made by ' association ' of several components; but the plurality is formed by dissociation of unsuspected varieties within the unity ; the substantive thing being no product of synthesis, but the residuum of differentiation. " (J. Martineau : A Study of Religion (1888), p. 193-4.) Compare also F. H. Bradley, Logic, book i. chap. n. * Such passages as the following abound in anti -sensationalist literature: *' Sense is a kind of dull, confused, and stupid perception obtruded upon the soul from without, whereby it perceives the alterations and motions within its own body, and takes cognizance of individual bodies existing round about it, but does not clearly comprehend what they are nor pene trate into the nature of them, it being intended by nature, as Plotinus speaks, not so properly for knowledge as for the use of the body. For Ihe soul suf fering under that which it perceives by way of passion cannot master or Oonquer it, that is to say, know or understand it. For so Anaxagoras in Aris totle very fitly expresses the nature of knowledge and intellection under the notion of Conquering. Wherefore it is necessary, since the mind under stands all things, that it should be free from mixture and passion, for this find, as Anaxagoras speaks, that it may be able to master and conquer its objects, that is to say, to know and understand them. In like manner Plo tinus, in his book of Sense and Memory, makes to suffer and to be conquered nil one, as also to know and to conquer; for which reason he concludes that 10 PSYCHOLOGY. seem to seek to crowd it out of existence altogether. The only reals for the neo-Hegelian writers appear to be rela tions, relations without terms, or whose terms are only speciously such and really consist in knots, or gnarls of relations finer still in infinitum. "Exclude from what we have considered real all qualities consti tuted by relation, we find that none are left." "Abstract the many relations from the one thing and there is nothing. . . . Without the relations it would not exist at all." * "The single feeling is nothing that which suffers doth not know. . . . Sense that suffers from external objects lies as it were prostrate under them, and is overcome by them. . Sense therefore is a certain kind of drowsy and somnolent percep tion of that passive part of the soul which is as it were asleep in the body, and acts concretely with it. ... It is an energy arising from the body and a certain kind of drowsy or sleeping life of the soul blended together with it. The perceptions of which compound, or of the soul as it were half asleep and half awake, are confused, indistinct, turbid, and encumbered cogitations very different from the energies of the noetical part, . . . which are free, clear, serene, satisfactory, and awakened cogitations. That is to say, knowledges." Etc., etc., etc. (R. Cudworth: Treatise concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality, bk in. chap, n.) Similarly Male- branche: "THEODORE.— Oh, oh, Ariste! God knows pain, pleasure, warmth, and the rest. But he does not feel these things. He knows pain, since he knows what that modification of the soul is in which pain consists. He knows it because he alone causes it in us (as I shall presently prove), and he knows what he does. In a word, he knows it because his knowledge has no bounds. But he does not feel it, for if so he would be unhappy. To know pain, then, is not to feel it. ARISTE.— That is true. But to feel it is to know it, is it not ? THEODORE.— No indeed, since God does not feel it in the least, and yet he knows it perfectly. But in order not to quibble about terms, if you will have it that to feel pain is to know it, agree at least that it is not to know it clearly, that it is not to know it by light and by evidence— in a word, that it is not to know its nature; in other words and to speak exactly, it is not to know it at all. To feel pain, for example, is to feel ourselves unhappy without well knowing either what we are or what is this modality of our being which makes us unhappy. . . . Impose silence on your senses, your imagination, and your passions, and you will hear the pure voice of inner truth, the clear and evident replies of our common mas ter. Never confound the evidence which results from the comparison of ideas with the liveliness of the sensations which touch and thrill you. The livelier our sensations and feelings (sentiments) are, the more darkness do they shed. The more terrible or agreeable are our phantoms, and the more body and reality they appear to have, the more dangerous are they and fit to lead us astray." (Entretiens sur la Metaphysique, 3me Entretien, ad mil.} Malebranche's Theodore prudently does not try to explain how God's 'infinite felicity ' is compatible with his not feeling joy. * Green: Prolegomena, §§ 20, 28. SENSATION. 11 real." "On the recognition of relations as constituting the nature of vieas, rests the possibility of any tenable theory of their reality." Such quotations as these from the late T. H. Green* would be matters of curiosity rather than of importance, were it not that sensationalist writers themselves believe in a so-called 'Belativity of Knowledge,' which, if they only understood it, they would see to be identical with Professor Green's doctrine. They tell us that the relation of sensa tions to each other is something belonging to their essence, and that no one of them has an absolute content : "That, e.g., black can only be felt in contrast to white, or at least in distinction from a paler or a deeper black; similarly a tone or a sound only in alternation with others or with silence; and in like manner a smell, a taste, a touch, only, so to speak, in statu nascendi, whilst, when the stimulus continues, all sensation disappears. This all seems at first sight to be splendidly consistent both with itself and with the facts. But looked at more closely, it is seen that neither is the case." t * Introd. to Hume, §§ 146, 188. It is hard to tell just what this aposto lic human being but strenuously feeble writer means by relation. Some times it seems to stand for system of related fact. The ubiquity of the 4 psychologist's fallacy ' (see p. 196) in his pages, his incessant leaning on the confusion between the thing known %the thought that knows it, and the farther things known about that thing and about that thought by later and additional thoughts, make it impossible to clear up his meaning. Compare, however, with the utterances in the text such others as these: " The wak ing of Self-consciousness from the sleep of sense is an absolute new begin ning, and nothing can come within the ' crystal sphere ' of intelligence except as it is determined by intelligence. What sense is to sense is noth ing for thought. What sense is to thought, it is as determined by thought. There can, therefore, be no 'reality 'in sensation to which the world of thought can be referred." (Edward Caird's Philosophy of Kant, 1st ed. pp. 393-4.) "When," says Green again, "feeling a pa"in or pleasure of heat, I perceive it to be connected with the action of approaching the fire, am I not perceiving a relation of which one constituent, at any rate, is a simple sensation? TJie true answer is, No." "Perception, in its simplest form . . . —perception as the first sight or touch of an object in which nothing but what is seen or touched is recognized— neither is nor contains sensation" (Conterap. Rev., xxxi. pp. 746, 750.) "Mere sensation is in truth a phrase that represents no reality." " Mere feeling, then, as a mat. ter unformed by thought, has no place in the world of facts, in the cosmos of possible experience." (Prolegomena to Ethics, §§ 46, 50.)— I have ex pressed myself a little more fully on this subject in Mind, x. 27 ff. f Stumpf: Tonpsychologie, i. pp. 7, 8. Hobbes's phrase, sentire semper idem et non sentire ad idem recidunt, is generally treated as the original state ment of the relativity doctrine. J. S. Mill (Examn. of Hamilton, p. 6) 12 PSYCHOLOGY. The two leading facts from which the doctrine of uni versal relativity derives its wide-spread credit are these : 1) The psychological fact that so much of our actual knowledge is of the relations of things — even our simplest sensations in adult life are habitually referred to classes as we take them in ; and 2) The physiological fact that our senses and brain must have periods of change and repose, else we cease to feel and think. Neither of these facts proves anything about the presence or non-presence to our mind of absolute quali ties with which we become sensibly acquainted. Surely not the psychological fact ; for our inveterate love of relating and comparing things does not alter the intrin sic qualities or nature of the things compared, or undo their absolute givenness. And surely not the physio-., logical fact ; for the length of time during which we can feel or attend to a quality is altogether irrelevant to the! intrinsic constitution of the quality felt. The time, more over, is long enough in many instances, as sufferers from neuralgia know.* And the doctrine of relativity, not proved by these facts, is flatly disproved by other facts even more patent. So far are we from not knowing (in the words of Professor Bain) " any one thing by itself, but only the dif ference between it and another thing," that if this were true the whole edifice of our knowledge would collapse. If all we felt were the difference between the C and D, or c and d, on the musical scale, that being the same in the two pairs of notes, the pairs themselves would be the same, and lan guage could get along without substantives. But Professor Bain does not mean seriously what he says, and we need spend no more time on this vague and popular form of the doctrine, t The facts which seem to hover before the minds and Bain (Senses and Intellect, p. 321; Emotions and Will, pp. 550, 570-2; Logic, i. p. 2; Body and Mind, p. 81) are subscribers to this doctrine. Of. also J. Miirs Analysis, J. S. Mill's edition, n. 11, 12. * We can steadily hear a note for half an hour. The differences be tween the senses are marked. Smell and taste seem soon to get fatigued. f In the popular mind it is mixed up with that entirely different doc trine of the ' Relativity of Knowledge ' preached by Hamilton and Spencer. This doctrine says that our knowledge is relative to us, and is not of the SENSATION. 13 of its champions are those which are best described under the head of a physiological law. THE LAW OF CONTBAST. I will first enumerate the main facts which fall under this law, and then remark upon what seems to me their sig nificance for psychology.* [Nowhere are the phenomena of contrast better exhib ited, and their laws more open to accurate study, than in connection with the sense of sight. Here both kinds — simultaneous and successive — can easily be observed, for they are of constant occurrence. Ordinarily they remain unnoticed, in accordance with the general law of economy which causes us to select for conscious notice only such elements of our object as will serve us for aesthetic or prac tical utility, and to neglect the rest ; just as we ignore the double images, the mouches volantes, etc., which exist for everyone, but which are not discriminated without careful attention. But by attention we may easily discover the general facts involved in contrast. We find that in general the color and brightness of one object always apparently affect the color and brightness of any other object seen simultaneously with it or immediately after. In the first place, if we look for a moment at any surface and then turn our eyes elsewhere, the complementary color and opposite degree of brightness to that of the first surface tend to mingle them selves wilFTEe color and the brightness of the second. This is successive contrast. It finds its ex planation in the fatigue of the organ of sight, causing it to respond to any particular stimulus less and less readily the longer such stimulus continues to act. This is shown clearly in the very marked changes which occur in case of contin ued fixation of one particular point of any field. The field darkens slowly, becomes more and more indistinct, and finally, if one is practised enough in holding the eye per- object as the latter is in itself. It has nothing to do with the question which we have been discussing, of whether our objects of knowledge con tain absolute terms or consist altogether of relations. * What follows in brackets, as far as p. 27, is from the pen of my friend and pupil Mr. E. B. Delabarre. 14 PSYCHOLOGY. fectly steady, slight differences in shade and color may entirely disappear. If we now turn aside the eyes, a nega tive after-image of the field just fixated at once forms, and mingles its sensations with those which may happen to come from anything else looked at. This influence is dis tinctly evident only when the first surface has been ' fixated ' without movement of the eyes. It is, however, none the less present at all times, even when the eye wanders from point to point, causing each sensation to be modified more or less by that just previously experienced. On this ac count successive contrast is almost sure to be present in cases of simultaneous contrast, and to complicate the phenomena. A visual image is modified not only by other sensations just previously experienced, but also by all those experienced simul taneously with it, and especially by such as proceed from con tiguous portions of the retina. This is the phenomenon of simultaneous contrast. In this, as in successive contrast, both brightness and hue are involved. A bright object appears still brighter when its surroundings are darker than itself, and darker when they are brighter than itself. Two colors side by side are apparently changed by the admixture, with each, of the complement of the other. And lastly, a gray surface near a colored one is tinged with the complement of the latter. * The phenomena of simultaneous contrast in sight are so complicated by other attendant phenomena that it is diffi- * These phenomena have close analogues in the phenomena of contrast presented by the temperature-sense (see W. Preyer in Archiv f. d. ges. Phys., Bd. xxv. p. 79 ff.). Successive contrast here is shown in the fact that a warm sensation appears warmer if a cold one has just previously been experienced ; and a cold one colder, if the preceding one was warm. If a finger which has been plunged in hot water, and another which has been in cold water, be both immersed in lukewarm water, the same water appears cold to the former finger and warm to the latter. In simultaneous contrast, a sensation of warmth on any part of the skin tends to induce the sensation of cold in its immediate neighborhood ; and vwe versa. This may be seen if we press with the palm on two metal surfaces of about an inch and a half square and three-fourths inch apart ; the skin between them appears distinctly warmer. So also a small object of exactly the tempera ture of the palm appears warm if a cold object, and cold if a warm object, touch the skin near it, SENSATION. 15 cult to isolate them and observe them in their purity. Yet it is evidently of the greatest importance to do so, if one would conduct his investigations accurately. Neglect of this principle has led to many mistakes being made in accounting for the facts observed. As we have seen, if the eye is allowed to wander here and there about the field as it ordinarily does, successive contrast results and allowance must be made for its presence. It can be avoided only by carefully fixating with the well-rested eye a point of one field, and by then observing the changes which occur in this field when the contrasting field is placed by its side. Such a course will insure pure simultaneous contrast. But even thus it lasts in its purity for a moment only. It reaches its maximum of effect immediately after the intro duction of the contrasting field, and then, if the fixation is continued, it begins to weaken rapidly and soon disappears ; thus undergoing changes similar to those observed when any field whatever is fixated steadily and the retina becomes fatigued by unchanging stimuli. If one continues still further to fixate the same point, the color and brightness of one field tend to spread themselves over and mingle with the color and brightness of the neighboring fields, thus substituting ' simultaneous induction ' for simultaneous con trast. Not only must we recognize and eliminate the effects of successive contrast, of temporal changes due to fixation, and of simultaneous induction, in analyzing the phenomena of simultaneous contrast, but we must also take into account various other influences which modify its effects. Under favor able circumstances the contrast-effects are very striking, and did they always occur as strongly they could not fail to attract the attention. But they are not always clearly apparent, owing to various disturbing causes which form no exception to the laws of contrast, but which have a modi fying effect on its phenomena. When, for instance, the ground observed has many distinguishable features — a coarse grain, rough surface, intricate pattern, etc. — the con trast effect appears weaker. This does not imply that the effects of contrast are absent, but merely that the resulting sensations are overpowered by the many other stronger sen- It) PSYCHOLOGY. sations which entirely occupy the attention. On such a ground a faint negative after-image— undoubtedly due to retinal modifications— may become invisible ; and even weak objective differences in color may become imper ceptible. For example, a faint spot or grease-stain on woollen cloth, easily seen at a distance, when the fibres are not distinguishable, disappears when closer examination reveals the intricate nature of the surface. Another frequent cause of the apparent absence of con trast is the presence of narrow dark intermediate fields, such as are formed by bordering a field with black lines, or by the shaded contours of objects. When such fields interfere with the contrast, it is because black and white can absorb much color without themselves becoming clearly colored ; and because such lines separate other fields too far for them to distinctly influence one another. Even weak objective differences in color may be made imperceptible by such means. A third case where contrast does not clearly appear is where the color of the contrasting fields is too weak or too in tense, or where there is much difference in brightness between the two fields. In the latter case, as can easily be shown, it is the contrast of brightness which interferes with the color- contrast and makes it imperceptible. For this reason con trast shows best between fields of about equal brightness. But the intensity of the color must not be too great, for then its very darkness necessitates a dark contrasting field which is too absorbent of induced color to allow the contrast to appear strongly. The case is similar if the fields are too light. To obtain the best contrast-effects, therefore, the contrasting f fields should be near together, should not be separated by shadowsj or black lines, should be of homogeneous texture, and should be o/f about equal brightness and medium intensity of color. Such! conditions do not often occur naturally, the disturbing in fluences being present in case of almost all ordinary objects, thus making the effects of contrast far less evident. To eliminate these disturbances and to produce the conditions most favorable for the appearance of good contrast-effects, SENSATION. 17 various experiments have been devised, which will be ex plained in comparing the rival theories of explanation. ,\ There are two theories — the psychological and the physio logical — which attempt to explain the phenomena of con trast. Of these the psychological one was the first to gain prom inence. Its most able advocate has been Helmholtz. It explains contrast as a DECEPTION OF JUDGMENT. In ordinary life our sensations have interest for us only so far as they give us practical knowledge. Our chief concern is to recognize objects, and we have no occasion to estimate exactly their absolute brightness and color. Hence we gain no facility in so doing, but neglect the constant changes in their shade, and are very uncertain as to the exact degree of their brightness or tone of their color. When objects are near one another " we are inclined to consider those differences which are clearly and surely perceived as greater than those which appear uncertain in perception or which must be judged by aid of memory," * just as we see a medium- sized man taller than he really is when he stands beside a short man. Such deceptions are more easily possible in the judgment of small differences than of large ones ; also where there is but one element of difference instead of many. In a large number of cases of contrast, in all of which a whitish spot is surrounded on all sides by a colored surface — Meyer's experiment, the mirror experi ment, colored shadows, etc., soon to be described — the contrast is produced, according to Helmholtz, by the fact that " a colored illumination or a transparent colored cover ing appears to be spread out over the field, and obser vation does not show directly that it fails on the white spot."t We therefore believe that we see the latter through the former color. Now " Colors have their greatest importance for us in so far as they are properties of bodies and can serve as signs for the recognition of bodies. . . . We have become accustomed, in forming a judgment in regard to the colors of bodies, to eliminate the varying brightness and * Helmholtz, Physiolog. Optik, p. 392. t Loc. cit. p. 407. 18 PSYCHOLOGY. color of the illumination. We have sufficient opportunity to investigate the same colors of objects in full sunshine, in the blue light of the clear sky, in the weak white light of a cloudy day, in the reddish-yellow light of the sinking sun or of the candle. Moreover the colored reflections of surrounding objects are involved. Since we see the same colored objects under these varying illuminations, we learn to form a correct conception of the color of the object in spite of the difference in illumi nation, i.e. to judge how such an object would appear in white illumi nation ; and since only the constant color of the object interests us, we do not become conscious of the particular sensations on which our judgment rests. So also we are at no loss, when we see an object through a colored covering, to distinguish what belongs to the color of the covering and what to the object. In the experiments mentioned we do the same also where the covering over the object is not at all colored, because of the deception into which we fall, and in consequence of which we ascribe to the body a false color, the color complementary to the colored portion of the covering. " * We think that we see the complementary color through the colored covering, — for these two colors together would give the sensation of white which is actually experienced. If, however, in any way the white spot is recognized as an independent object, or if it is compared with another ob ject known to be white, our judgment is no longer deceived and the contrast does not appear. "As soon as the contrasting field is recognized as an independent body which lies above the colored ground, or even through an ade quate tracing of its outlines is seen to be a separate field, the contrast disappears. Since, then, the judgment of the spatial position, the material independence, of the object in question is decisive for the determination of its color, it follows that the contrast-color arises not through an act of sensation but through an act of judgment." f In short, the apparent change in color or brightness through contrast is due to no change in excitation of the organ, to no change in sensation ; but in consequence of a false judgment the unchanged sensation is wrongly inter preted, and thus leads to a changed perception of the bright ness or color. In opposition to this theory has been developed one h attempts to explain all cases of contrast as depend- * LOG. cit. p. 408. f Loc. cit. p. 406. SENSATION. 19 ing purely on physiological action of the terminal apparatus of vision. Hering is the most prominent supporter of this view. By great originality in devising experiments and by insist ing on rigid care in conducting them, he has been able to detect the faults in the psychological theory and to practi cally establish the validity of his own. Every visual sensa tion, he maintains, is correlated to a physical process in the nervous apparatus. Contrast is occasioned, not by a false idea resulting from unconscious conclusions, but by the fact that the excitation of any portion of the retina — and the consequent sensation — depends not only on its own illumination, but on that of the rest of the retina as well. " If this psycho-physical process is aroused, as usually happens, by light- rays impinging on the retina, its nature depends not only on the nature of these rays, but also on the constitution of the entire nervous apparatus which is connected with the organ of vision, and on the state in which it finds itself." * When a limited portion of the retina is aroused by ex ternal stimuli, the rest of the retina, and especially the immediately contiguous parts, tends to react also, and in such a way as to produce therefrom the sensation of the opposite degree of brightness and the complementary color to that of the directly-excited portion. When a gray spot is seen alone, and again when it appears colored through contrast, the objective light from the spot is in both cases the same. Helmholtz maintains that the neural process and the corresponding sensation also remain unchanged, but are differently interpreted ; Hering, that the neural process and the sensation are themselves changed, and that the * interpretation ' is the direct conscious correlate of the altered retinal conditions. According to the one, the con trast is psychological in its origin ; according to the other, it is purely physiological. In the cases cited above where the contrast-color is no longer apparent — on a ground with many distinguishable features, on a field whose borders are traced with black lines, etc., — the psychological theory, as we have seen, attributes this to the fact that under these circumstances we judge the smaller patch of color to be an * E. Hering, in Hermann's Handbuch d. Physiologic, in. 1, p. 565. 20 PSYCHOLOGY. independent object on the surface, and are no longer de ceived in judging it to be something over which the color of the ground is drawn. The physiological theory, on the other hand, maintains that the contrast-effect is still pro duced, but that the conditions are such that the slight changes in color and brightness which it occasions become imperceptible. The two theories, stated thus broadly, may seem equally plausible. Hering, however, has conclusively proved, by experiments with after-images, that the process on one part of the retina does modify that on neighboring portions, under conditions where deception of judgment' is impossi ble.* A careful examination of the facts of contrast will show that its phenomena must be due to this cause. In all the cases which one may investigate it will be seen that the up holders of the psychological theory have failed to conduct their experiments with sufficient care. They have not excluded successive contrast, have overlooked the changes due to * Hering : 'Zur Lehre vom Lichtsinne.' — Of these experiments the fol lowing (found on p. 24 ff.) may be cited as a typical one : "From dark gray paper cut two strips 3-4 cm. long and ^ cm. wide, and lay them on a background of which one half is white and the other half deep black, in such a way that one strip lies on each side of the border-line and parallel to it, and at least 1 cm. distant from it. Fixate £ to 1 minute a point on the border-line between the strips. One strip appears much brighter than the other. Close and cover the eyes, and the negative after-image appears. . . . The difference in brightness of the strips in the after-image is in gen eral much greater than it appeared in direct vision. . . . This difference in brightness of the strips by no means always increases and decreases with the difference in brightness of the two halves of the background. ... A phase occurs in which the difference in brightness of the two halves of the background entirely disappears, and yet botfr after-images of the strips are still very clear, one of them brighter and one darker than the back ground, which is equally bright on both halves. Here can no longer be any question of contrast-effect, because the conditio sine qua non of con trast, namely, the differing brightness of the ground, is no longer pres ent. This proves that the different brightness of the after-images of the strips must have its ground in a different state of excitation of the corre sponding portions of the retina, and from this follows further that botli these portions of the retina were differently stimulated during the original observation ; for the different after-effect demands here a different fore- effect. . In the original arrangement, the objectively similar strips appeared of different brightness, because both corresponding portions of the retina were truly differently excited." SENSATION. 21 steady fixation, and have failed to properly account for the various modifying influences which have been mentioned above. We can easily establish this if we examine the most striking experiments in simultaneous contrast. Of these one of the best known and most easily arranged is that known as Meyer's experiment. A scrap of gray paper is placed on a colored background, and both are covered by a sheet of transparent white paper. The gray spot then assumes a contrast-color, complementary to that of the background, which shines with a whitish tinge through the paper which covers it. Helmholtz explains the phenome non thus : " If the background is green, the covering-paper itself appears to be of a greenish color. If now the substance of the paper extends without apparent interruption over the gray which lies under it, we think that we see an object glimmering through the greenish paper, and such an object must in turn be rose-red, in order to give white light. If, how ever, the gray spot has its limits so fixed that it appears to be an inde pendent object, the continuity with the greenish portion of the surface fails, and we regard it as a gray object which lies on this surface." * The contrast-color may thus be made to disappear by tracing in black the outlines of the gray scrap, or by plac ing above the tissue paper another gray scrap of the same degree of brightness, and comparing together the two grays. On neither of them does the contrast-color now appear. Hering t shows clearly that this interpretation is incor rect, and that the disturbing factors are to be otherwise explained. In the first place, the experiment can be so arranged that we could not possibly be deceived into be lieving that we see the gray through a colored medium. Out of a sheet of gray paper cut strips 5 mm. wide in such a way that there will be alternately an empty space and a bar of gray, both of the same width, the bars being held to gether by the uncut edges of the gray sheet (thus presenting an appearance like a gridiron). Lay this on a colored back ground — e.g. green — cover both with transparent paper, and above all put a black frame which covers all the edges, leaving visible only the bars, which are now alternately * Helmholtz, Physiolog. Optik, p. 407. f In Archiv f. d. ges. Physiol., Bd. XLI. S. 1 ff. 22 PSYCHOLOGY. green and gray. The gray bars appear strongly colored by contrast, although, since they occupy as much space as the green bars, we are not deceived into believing that we see the former through a green medium. The same is true if we weave together into a basket pattern narrow strips of green and gray and cover them with the transparent paper. Why, then, if it is a true sensation due to physiological causes, and not an error of judgment, which causes the contrast, does the color disappear when the outlines of the gray scrap are traced, enabling us to recognize it as an independent object ? In the first place, it does not neces sarily do so, as will easily be seen if the experiment is tried. The contrast-color often remains distinctly visible in spite of the black outlines. In the second place, there are many adequate reasons why the effect should be modi fied. Simultaneous contrast is always strongest at the border-line of the two fields ; but a narrow black field now separates the two, and itself by contrast strengthens the whiteness of both original fields, which were already little saturated in color ; and on black and on white, contrast- colors show only under the most favorable circumstances. Even weak objective differences in color may be made to disappear by such tracing of outlines, as can be seen if we place on a gray background a scrap of faintly- colored paper, cover it with transparent paper and trace its out lines. Thus we see that it is not the recognition of the contrasting field as an independent object which interferes with its color, but rather a number of entirely explicable physiological disturbances. The same may be proved in the case of holding above the tissue paper a second gray scrap and comparing it with that underneath. To avoid the disturbances caused by using papers of different brightness, the second scrap should be made exactly like the first by covering the same gray with the same tissue paper, and carefully cutting a piece about 10 mm. square out of both together. To thoroughly guard against successive contrast, which so easily compli cates the phenomena, we must carefully prevent all previ ous excitation of the retina by colored light. This may be done by arranging thus : Place the sheet of tissue paper SENSATION. 23 on a glass pane, which rests on four supports ; under the paper put the first gray scrap. By means of a wire, fasten the second gray scrap 2 or 3 cm. above the glass plate. Both scraps appear exactly alike, except at the edges Gaze now at both scraps, with eyes not exactly accommo dated, so that they appear near one another, with a very narrow space between. Shove now a colored field (green) underneath the glass plate, and the contrast appears at once on both scraps. If it appears less clearly on the upper scrap, it is because of its bright and dark edges, its inequalities, its grain, etc. When the accommodation is exact, there is no essential change, although then on the upper scrap the bright edge on the side toward the light, and the dark edge on the shadow side, disturb somewhat. By continued fixation the contrast becomes weaker and finally yields to simultaneous induction, causing the scraps to become indistinguishable from the ground. Remove the green field and both scraps become green, by succes sive induction. If the eye moves about freely these last- named phenomena do not appear, but the contrast continues indefinitely and becomes stronger. When Helmholtz found that the contrast on the lower scrap disappeared, it was evidently because he then really held the eye fixed. This experiment may be disturbed by holding the upper scrap wrongly and by the differences in brightness of its edges, or by other inequalities, but not by that recognizing of it ' as an independent body lying above the colored ground,' on which the psychological explanation rests. In like manner the claims of the psychological explana tion can be shown to be inadequate in other cases of con trast. Of frequent use are revolving disks, which are especially efficient in showing good contrast-phenomena, because all inequalities of the ground disappear and leave a perfectly homogeneous surface. On a white disk are ar ranged colored sectors, which are interrupted midway by narrow black fields in such a way that when the disk is re volved the white becomes mixed with the color and the black, forming a colored disk of weak saturation on which appears a gray ring. The latter is colored by contrast with 24 PSYCHOLOGY. the field which surrounds it. Helmholtz explains the fact thus : " The difference of the compared colors appears greater than it really is either because this difference, when it is the only existing one and draws the attention to itself alone, makes a stronger impression than when it is one among many, or because the different colors of the sur face are conceived as alterations of the one ground-color of the surface such as might arise through shadows falling on it, through colored reflexes, or through mixture with colored paint or dust. In truth, to produce an objectively gray spot on a green surface, a reddish coloring would be necessary." * This explanation is easily proved false by painting the disk with narrow green and gray concentric rings, and giv ing each a different saturation. The contrast appears though there is no ground-color, and no longer a single dif ference, but many. The facts which Helmholtz brings for ward in support of his theory are also easily turned against him. He asserts that if the color of the ground is too in tense, or if the gray ring is bordered by black circles, the contrast becomes" weaker; that no contrast appears on a white scrap held over the colored field ; and that the gray ring when compared with such scrap loses its contrast-color either wholly or in part. Hering points out the inaccuracy of all these claims. Under favorable conditions it is impos sible to make the contrast disappear by means of black en closing lines, although they naturally form a disturbing element ; increase in the saturation of the field, if disturb ance through increasing brightness-contrast is to be avoid ed, demands a darker gray field, on which contrast-colors are less easily perceived ; and careful use of the white scrap leads to entirely different results. The contrast-color does appear upon it when it is first placed above the colored field; but if it is carefully fixated, the contrast-color di minishes very rapidly both on it and on the ring, from causes already explained. To secure accurate observation, all complication through successive contrast should be avoided thus : first arrange the white scrap, then interpose a gray screen between it and the disk, rest the eye, set the wheel in motion, fixate the scrap, and then have the screen re- * Helmholtz, loc. cit. p. 412. SENSATION. 25 moved. The contrast at once appears clearly, and its dis appearance through continued fixation can be accurately watched. Brief mention of a few other cases of contrast must suf fice. The so-called mirror experiment consists of placing at an angle of 45° a green (or otherwise colored) pane of glass, forming an angle with two white surfaces, one hori zontal and the other vertical. On each white surface is a black spot. The one on the horizontal surface is seen through the glass and appears dark green, the other is reflected from the surface of the glass to the eye, and appears by contrast red. The experiment may be so arranged that we are not aware of the presence of the green glass, but think that we are looking directly at a surface with green and red spots upon it ; in such a case there is no deception of judg ment caused by making allowance for the colored medium through which we think that we see the spot, and therefore the psychological explanation does not apply. On exclud ing successive contrast by fixation the contrast soon disap pears as in all similar experiments.* Colored shadows have long been thought to afford a con vincing proof of the fact that simultaneous contrast is psychological in its origin. They are formed whenever an opaque object is illuminated from two separate sides by lights of different colors. When the light from one source is white, its shadow is of the color of the other light, and the second shadow is of a color complementary to that of the field illuminated by both lights. If now we take a tube, blackened inside, and through it look at the colored shadow, none of the surrounding field being visible, and then have the colored light removed, the shadow still appears colored, although ' the circumstances which caused it have disap peared.' This is regarded by the psychologists as con clusive evidence that the color is due to deception of judg ment. It can, however, easily be shown that the persistence of the color seen through the tube is due to fatigue of the retina through the prevailing light, and that when the colored light is removed the color slowly disappears as the * See Hering : Archiv. f. d. ges. Physiol., Bd. XLI. S. 358 ff. 26 PSYCHOLOGY. equilibrium of the retina becomes gradually restored. When successive contrast is carefully guarded against, the simul taneous contrast, whether seen directly or through the tube, never lasts for an instant on removal of the colored field. The physiological explanation applies throughout to all the phenomena presented by colored shadows. * If we have a small field whose illumination remains con stant, surrounded by a large field of changing brightness, an increase or decrease in brightness of the latter results in a corresponding apparent decrease or increase respect ively in the brightness of the former, while the large field seems to be unchanged. Exner says : ' ' This illusion of sense shows that we are inclined to regard as con stant the dominant brightness in our field of vision, and hence to refer the changing difference between this and the brightness of a limited field to a change in brightness of the latter." The result, however, can be shown to depend not on illusion, but on actual retinal changes, which alter the sen sation experienced. The irritability of those portions of the retina lighted by the large field becomes much reduced in consequence of fatigue, so that the increase in brightness becomes much less apparent than it would be without this diminution in irritability. The small field, however, shows the change by a change in the contrast-effect induced upon it by the surrounding parts of the retina, t The above cases show clearly that" physiological processes, and not deception of judgment, are responsible for contrast of color. To say this, however, is not to maintain that our perception of a color is never in any degree modified by our judgment of what the particular colored thing before us may be. We have unquestionable illusions of color due to wrong inferences as to what object is before us. Thus Von Kries;|: speaks of wandering through evergreen forests cov ered with snow, and thinking that through the interstices of the boughs he saw the deep blue of pine-clad mountains, cov- *Hering: Archiv f. d. ges. Physiol., Bd. XL. S. 172 ff. ; Delabarre r American Jourual of Psychology, n. 636. f Hering : Archiv f . d. ges. Physiol., Bd. XLI. S. 91 ff. i D'e Gesichtsempfindungen u. ihre Analyse, p. 128. SENSATION. 27 ered with snow and lighted by brilliant sunshine ; whereas what he really saw was the white snow on trees near by, lying in shadow]. * Such a mistake as this is undoubtedly of psychological origin. It is a wrong classification of the appearances, due to the arousal of intricate processes of association amongst which is the suggestion of a different hue from that really before the eyes. In the ensuing chapters such illusions as this will be treated of in considerable detail. But it is a mistake to interpret the simpler cases of con trast in the light of such illusions as these. These illu sions can be rectified in an instant, and we then wonder how they could have been. They come from insufficient attention, or from the fact that the impression which we get is a sign of more than one possible object, and can be interpreted in either way. In none of these points do they resemble simple color-contrast, which unquestionably is a phenomenon of sensation immediately aroused. I have dwelt upon the facts of color-contrast at such great length because they form so good a text to comment on in my struggle against the view that sensations are im mutable psychic things which coexist with higher mental functions. Both sensationalists and intellectualists agree that such sensations exist. They fuse, say the pure sen sationalists, and make the higher mental function ; they are combined by activity of the Thinking Principle, say the intellectualists. I myself have contended that they do not exist in or alongside of the higher mental function when that exists. The things which arouse them exist ; and the ^ \ higher mental function also knows these same things. But just as its knowledge of the things supersedes and displaces their knowledge, so it supersedes and displaces them, when it comes, being as much as they are a direct result ant of whatever momentary brain-conditions may obtain. The psychological theory of contrast, on the other hand, holds the sensations still to exist in themselves unchanged before the mind, whilst the ' relating activity ' of the latter * Mr. Delabarre's contribution ends here. 28 PSYCHOLOGY. deals with them freely and settles to its own satisfaction what each shall be, in view of what the others also are. Wundt says expressly that the Law of Relativity is " not a law of sensation but a law of Apperception ;" and the word Apperception connotes with him a higher intellectual spon taneity.* This way of taking things belongs with the phi losophy that looks at the data of sense as something earth- born and servile, and the * relating of them together' as something spiritual and free. Lo ! the spirit can even change the intrinsic quality of the sensible facts themselves if by so doing it can relate them better to each other ! But (apart from the difficulty of seeing how changing the sen sations should relate them better) is it not manifest that the relations are part of the ' content ' of consciousness, part of the 'object,' just as much as the sensations are? Why ascribe the former exclusively to the knower and the latter to the known? The knower is in every case a unique pulse of thought corresponding to a unique reaction of the brain upon its conditions. All that the facts of contrast show us is that the same real thing may give us quite different sensations when the conditions alter, and that we must therefore be careful which one to select as the thing's truest representative. There are many other fads beside the phenomena of contrast which prove that ivhen two objects act together on us the sensation which either would give alone becomes a different sensation. A certain amount of skin dipped in hot water gives the perception of a certain heat. More skin immersed makes the heat much more intense, although of course the water's heat is the same. A certain extent as well as in tensity, in the quantity of the stimulus is requisite for any quality to be felt. Fick and Wunderli could not distin guish heat from touch when both were applied through a * Physiol. Psych., i. 351, 458-60. The full inanity of the law of rela tivity is best to be seen in Wundt's treatment, where the great ' allgemeinei' Oesetz der Beziehung,' invoked 10 account for Weber's law as well as for the phenomena of contrast and many other matters, can only be defined as a tendency to feel all things in relation to each other! Bless its little soul! But why does it change the things so, when it thus feels them in relation? SENSATION. 29 hole in a card, and so confined to a small part of the skin. Similarly there is a chromatic minimum of size in objects. The image they cast on the retina must needs have a cer tain extent, or it will give no sensation of color at all. In versely, more intensity in the outward impression may make the subjective object more extensive. This happens, as will be shown in Chapter XIX, when the illumination is .increased : The whole room expands and dwindles ac cording as we raise or lower the gas-jet. It is not easy to explain any of these results as illusions of judgment due to the inference of a wrong objective cause for the sen sation which we get. No more is this easy in the case of Weber's observation that a thaler laid on the skin of the forehead feels heavier when cold than when warm ; or of Szabadfoldi's observation that small wooden disks when heated to 122° Fahrenheit often feel heavier than those which are larger but not thus warmed;* or of Hall's ob servation that a heavy point moving over the skin seems to go faster than a lighter one moving at the same rate of speed, f Bleuler and Lehmann some years ago called attention to a strange idiosyncrasy found in some persons, and con sisting in the fact that impressions on the eye, skin, etc., were accompanied by distinct sensations of sound.\ Colored hearing is the name sometimes given to the phenomenon, which has now been repeatedly described. Quite lately the Viennese aurist Urbantschitsch has proved that these cases are only extreme examples of a very general law, and that all our sense-organs influence each other's sensations. § The hue of patches of color so distant as not to be recog nized was immediately, in U.'s patients, perceived when a tuning-fork was sounded close to the ear. Sometimes, on the contrary, the field was darkened by the sound. The acuity of vision was increased, so that letters too far off to be read could be read when the tuning-fork was heard. Urbantschitsch, varying his experiments, found that their * Ladd : Physiol. Psych., p. 348. f Mind, x. 567. | Zwangsmassige Lichtempfindung durch Schall (Leipzig, 1881). § Pfliiger's Archiv, XLII. 354 30 PSYCHOLOGY. results were mutual, and that sounds which were on the limits of audibility became audible when lights of various colors were exhibited to the eye. Smell, taste, touch, sense of temperature, etc., were all found to fluctuate when lights were seen and sounds were heard. Individuals varied much in the degree and kind of effect produced, but almost every one experimented on seems to have been in some way affected. The phenomena remind one somewhat of the ' dynamogenic ' effects of sensations upon the strength of muscular contraction observed by M. Fere, and later to be described. The most familiar examples of them seem to be the increase of pain by noise or light, and the increase of nausea by all concomitant sensations. Persons suffering in any way instinctively seek stillness and darkness. Probably every one will agree that the best way of for mulating all such facts is physiological : it must be that the cerebral process of the first sensation is reinforced or other wise altered by the other current which comes in. No one, surely, will prefer a psychological explanation here. Well,' \ it s^em^jfco^nje^that^ all cases of mental reaction to a plural- \ i tLHL s *'i ™ " ^ i mns Q>e_JjgeJl3jese_^^ the^ phy- > | siological formulation is every where_the simplest and the V best. When simultaneous red and green light make us see yellow, when three notes of the scale make us hear a chord, it is not because the sensations of red and of green and of each of the three notes enter the mind as such, and there ' combine ' or ' are combined by its relating activity ' into the yellow and the chord, it is because the larger sum of light- waves and of air- waves arouses new cortical processes, to which the yellow and the chord directly correspond. Even when the sensible jg^ialities of things enter into the objects of our highest thinking, it is surely the same? Their several jsensations do not continue to exist there tucked away. They are replaced by the HgFeFlhought jwhich, although a different psychic unitTrom thm^ Trrmwa iliA same sensible qualities which they know. The principles laid down in Chapter VI seem then to be corroborated in this new connection. You cannot build up one thought or one sensation out of many; and only direct SENSATION. 31 experiment can inform us of what we shall perceive when we get many stimuli at once. THE 'ECCENTRIC PROJECTION' OF SENSATIONS. We often hear the opinion expressed that all our sensa tions at first appear to us as subjective or internal, and are afterwards and by a special act on our part ' extradited ' or 'projected' so as to appear located in an outer world. Thus we read in Professor Ladd's valuable work that " Sensations . . . are psychical states whose place — so far as they can be said to have one— is the mind. The transference of these sensations from mere mental states to physical processes located in the periphery of the body, or to qualities of things projected in space external to the body, is a mental act. It may rather be said to be a mental achievement [cf. Cudworth, above, as to knowledge being conquering], for it is an act which in its perfection results from a long and intricate process of de velopment. . . . Two noteworthy stages, or 'epoch-making' achieve ments in the process of elaborating the presentations of sense, require a special consideration. These are ' localization,' or the transference of the composite sensations from mere states of the mind to processes or conditions recognized as taking place at more or less definitely fixed points or areas of the body; and ' eccentric projection ' (sometimes called 4 eccentric perception ') or the giving to these sensations an objective existence (in the fullest sense of the word * objective ') as qualities of objects situated within a field of space and in contact with, or more or less remotely distant from, the body." * It seems to me that there is not a vestige of evidence for this view. It hangs together with the opinion that our sen sations are originally devoid of all spatial content, t an opinion which I confess that I am wholly at a loss to under stand. As I look at my bookshelf opposite I cannot frame to myself an idea, however imaginary, of any feeling which I could ever possibly have got from it except the feeling of * Physiological Psychology, 385, 387. See also such passages as that in Bain ; The Senses and the Intellect, pp. 364-6. f ' ' Especially must we avoid all attempts, whether avowed or concealed, to account for the spatial qualities of the presentations of sense by merely describing the qualities of the simple sensations and the modes of their combination. It is position and extension in space which constitutes the very peculiarity of the objects as no longer mere sensations or affections of the mind. As sensations, they are neither out of ourselves nor possessed of the qualities indicated by the word spread-out." (Ladd, op. cit. p. 391.) 32 PSYCHOLOGY. the same big extended sort of outward fact which I now perceive. So far is it from being true that our first way of feeling things is the feeling of them as subjective or men tal, that the exact opposite seems rather to be the truth. Our earliest, most instinctive, least developed kind of con sciousness is the objective kind ; and only as reflection be comes developed do we become aware of an inner world at all. Then indeed we enrich it more and more, even to the point of becoming idealists, with the spoils of the outer world which at first was the only world we knew. But subjective consciousness, aware of itself as subjective, does not at first exist. Even an attack of pain is surely felt at first objectively as something in space which prompts to motor reaction, and to the very end it is located, not in the mind, but in some bodily part. "A sensation which should not awaken an impulse to move, nor any tendency to produce an outward effect, would manifestly be use less to a living creature. On the principles of evolution such a sensa tion could never be developed. Therefore every sensation originally refers to something external and independent of the sentient creature. Rhizopods (according to Engeimann's observations) retract their pseudo- podia whenever these touch foreign bodies, even if these foreign bodies are the pseudopodia of other individuals of their own species, whilst the mutual contact of their own pseudopodia is followed by no such contraction. These low animals can therefore already feel an outer world— even in the absence of innate ideas of causality, and probably without any clear consciousness of space. In truth the conviction that something exists outside of ourselves does not come from thought. It comes from sensation; it rests on the same ground as our conviction of our own existence. ... If we consider the behavior of new-born animals, we never find them betraying that they are first of all con scious of their sensations as purely subjective excitements. We far more readily incline to explain the astonishing certainty with which they make use of their sensations (and which is an effect of adaptation and inheritance) as the result of an inborn intuition of the outer world. . Instead of starting from an original pure subjectivity of sensa tion, and seeking how this could possibly have acquired an objective signification, wsmust, on the contrary, begin by the possession of objec tivity by the sensation and then show how for reflective consciousness the latter becomes interpreted as an effect of the object, how in short the original immediate objectivity becomes changed into a remote one."* * A. Riehl: Der Philosophischer Kriticismus, Bd. n. Theil n. p. 64. SENSATION. 33 Another confusion, much more common than the denial of all objective character to sensations, is the assumption that they are all originally located inside the body and are pro jected outward by a secondary act. This secondary judg ment is always false, according to M. Taine, so far as the place of the sensation itself goes. But it happens to hit a real object which is at the point towards which the sensation is projected ; so we may call its result, according to this author, a veridical hallucination.* The word Sensation, to * On Intelligence, part n. bk. n. chap. n. §g vn, vm. Compare such statements as these : "The consequence is that when a sensation has for its usual condition the presence of an object more or less distant from our bodies, and experience has once made us acquainted with this distance, we shall situate our sensation at this distance. — This, in fact, is the case with sensations of hearing and sight. The peripheral extremity of the acoustic nerve is in the deep-seated chamber of the ear. That of the optic nerve is in the most inner recess of the eye. But still, in our present state, we never situate our sensations of sound or color in these places, but without us, and often at a considerable distance from us. ... All our sensations of color are thus projected out of our body, and clothe more or less distant objects, furniture, walls, houses, trees, the sky, and the rest. This is why, when we afterwards reflect on them, we cease to at tribute them, to ourselves; they are alienated and detached from us, so far as to appear different from us. Projected from the nervous surface in which we localize the majority of the others, the tie which connected them to the others and to ourselves is undone. . . . Thus, all our sensa tions are wrongly situated, and the red color is no more extended on the arm chair than the sensation of tingling is situated at my fingers' ends. They are all situated in the sensory centres of the encephalon; all appear situated elsewhere, and a common law allots to each of them its apparent situation." (Vol. ii. pp. 47-53.) — Similarly Schopenhauer: "I will now show the same by the sense of sight. The immediate datum is here limited to the sensation of the retina which, it is true, admits of con siderable diversity, but at bottom reverts to the impression of light and dark with their shades, and that of colors. This sensation is through and through subjective, that is, inside of the organism and under the skin." (Schopenhauer: Satz vom Grunde, p. 58.) This philoso pher then enumerates seriatim what the Intellect does to make the origi nally subjective sensation objective: 1) it turns it bottom side up; 2) it reduces its doubleness to singleness; 3) it changes its flatness to solidity; and .x) it projects it to a distance from the eye. Again: "Sensations are what we call the impressions on our senses, in so far as they come to our consciousness as states of our own body, especially of our nervous apparatus; we call them perceptions when we form out of them the repre sentation of outer objects." (Helmholtz: Tonempfindungen, 1870, p. 101.) —Once more : " Sensation is always accomplished in the psychic centres, but it manifests itself at the excited part of the periphery. In other words, 34 PSYCHOLOGY, begin with, is constantly, in psychological literature, used as if it meant one and the same thing with the physical im pression either in the terminal organs or in the centres, which is its antecedent condition, and this notwithstanding that by sensation we mean a mental, not a physical, fact. But those who expressly mean by it a mental fact still leave to it a physical place, still think of it as objectively inhabiting the very neural tracts which occasion its appear ance when they are excited ; and then (going a step farther) they think that it must place itself where they place it, or be subjectively sensible of that place as its habitat in the first instance, and afterwards have to be moved so as to appear elsewhere. All this seems highly confused and unintelligible. Con- j sciousness, as we saw in an earlier chapter (p. 214) canno, ) properly be said to inhabit any place. It has dynamic re lations with the brain, and cognitive relations with every- j thing and anything. From the one point of view we may say that a sensation is in the same place with the brain (if we like), just as from the other point of view we may say that it is in the same place with whatever quality it may be cognizing. But the supposition that a sensation primi- \1 tively/eeZs either itself or its object to be in the same place with \ the brain is absolutely groundless, and neither a priori probability nor facts from experience can be adduced to show that such a deliverance forms any part of the original cognitive function of our sensibility. Where, then, do we feel the objects of our original sensa tions to be ? Certainly a child newly born in Boston, who gets a sen sation from the candle-flame which lights the bedroom, or from his diaper-pin, does not feel either of these objects to one is conscious of the phenomenon in the nervous centres, ... but one perceives it in the peripheric organs. This phenomenon depends on the experience of the sensations themselves, in which there is a reflection of the subjective phenomenon and a tendency on the part of perception to return as it were to the external cause which has roused the mental state because the latter is connected with the former." (Sergi : Psychologic Physiologique (Paris, 1888), p. 189.)-The clearest and best passage I know is in Liebmaun: Der Objective Anblick (1869), pp, 67-72, but it is unfortu nately too long to quote. SENSATION. 35 be situated in longitude 72° W. and latitude 41° N. He does not feel them to be in the third story of the house. He does not even feel them in any distinct manner to be to the right or the left of any of the other sensations which he may be getting from other objects in the room at the same time. He does not, in short, know anything about their space-relations to anything else in the world. The flame fills its own place, the pain fills its own place ; but as yet these places are neither identified with, nor discriminated from, any other places. That comes later. For the places thus first sensibly known are elements of the child's space- world which remain with him all his life ; and by memory and later experience he learns a vast number of things about those places which at first he did not know. But to the end of time certain places of the world remain defined for him as the places where those sensations ivere ; and his only possible answer to the question where anything is will be to say ' there,' and to name some sensation or other like those first ones, which shall identify the spot. Space means but the aggregate of all our possible sensations. There is no duplicate space known aliunde, or created by an ' epoch- making achievement ' into which our sensations, originally spaceless, are dropped. They bring space and all its places to our intellect, and do not derive it thence. By his body, then, the child later means simply that place where the pain from the pin, and a lot of other sensations like it, were or are felt. It is no more true to say that he locates that pain in his body, than to say that he locates his body in that pain. Both are true : that pain is part of what he means by the word body. Just so by the outer world the child means nothing more than that place where the candle- flame and a lot of other sensations like it are felt. He no more locates the candle in the outer world than he locates the outer world in the candle. Once again, he does both ; for the candle is part of what he means by 'outer world.' This (it seems to me) will be admitted, and will (I trust) be made still more plausible in the chapter on the Percep tion of Space. But the later developments of this percep tion are so complicated that these simple principles get 36 PSYCHOLOGY. easily overlooked. One of the complications comes from the fact that things move, and that the original object which we feel them to be splits into two parts, one of which re mains as their whereabouts and the other goes off as their quality or nature. We then contrast where they ivere with where they are. If we do not move, the sensation of where they ivere remains unchanged ; but we ourselves presently move, so that that also changes ; and ' where they were ' becomes no longer the actual sensation which it was origi nally, but a sensation which we merely conceive as possible. Gradually the system of these possible sensations, takes more and more the place of the actual sensations. ' Up ' and ' down ' become ' subjective ' notions ; east and west grow more ' correct ' than ' right ' and ' left ' etc.; and things get at last more ' truly ' located by their relation to certain ideal fixed co-ordinates than by their relation either to our bodies or to those objects by which their place was originally denned. Now this revision of our original locali zations is a complex affair; and contains some facts ivhich may very naturally come to be described as translocations ivhereby sensations get shoved farther off than they originally appeared. 1 Few things indeed are more striking than the change able distance which the objects of many of our sensations may be made to assume. A fly's humming may be taken for a distant steam-whistle ; or the fly itself, seen out of focus, may for a moment give us the illusion of a distant bird. The same things seem much nearer or much farther, according as we look at them through one end or another of an opera-glass. Our whole optical education indeed is largely taken up with assigning their proper distances to the objects of our retinal sensations. An infant will grasp at the moon ; later, it is said, he projects that sensation to a dis tance which he knows to be beyond his reach. In the much quoted case of the 'young gentleman who was born blind,' and who was ' couched ' for the cataract by Mr. Chesselden, it is reported of the patient that " when he first saw, he was so far from making any judgment about dis tances, that he thought all objects whatever touched his eyes (as he expressed it) as what he felt did his skin." And other patients born blind, but relieved by surgical op- SENSATION. 37 eration, have been described as bringing their hand close to their eyes to feel for the objects which they at first saw, and only gradually stretching out their hand when they found that no contact occurred. Many have concluded from these facts that our earliest visual objects must seem in immediate contact with our eyes. But tactile objects also may be affected with a like am biguity of situation. If one of the hairs of our head be pulled, we are pretty accurately sensible of the direction of the pulling by the movements imparted to the head.* But the feeling of the pull is localized, not in that part of the hair's length which the fingers hold, but in the scalp itself. This seems con nected with the fact that our hair hardly serves at all as a tactile organ. In creatures with vibrissce, however, and in those quadrupeds whose whiskers are tactile organs, it can hardly be doubted that the feeling is projected out of the root into the shaft of the hair itself. We ourselves have an approach to this when the beard as a whole, or the hair as a whole, is touched. We perceive the contact at some dis tance from the skin. When fixed and hard appendages of the body, like the teeth and nails, are touched, we feel the contact where it objectively is, and not deeper in, where the nerve-termina tions lie. If, however, the tooth is loose, we feel two contacts, spatially separated, one at its root, one at its top. From this case to that of a hard body not organically connected with the surface, but only accidentally in contact with it, the transition is immediate. With the point of a cane we can trace letters in the air or on a wall just as with the finger-tip ; and in so doing feel the size and shape of the path described by the cane's tip just as immediately as, without a cane, we should feel the path described by the tip of our finger. Similarly the draughtsman's immediate\ perception seems to be of the point of his pencil, the sur-| * This is proved by Weber's device of causing the head to be firmly pressed against a support by another person, whereupon the direction of traction ceases to be perceived. 38 PSYCHOLOGY. geon's of the end of his knife, the duellist's of the tip of his rapier as it plunges through his enemy's skin. When on the middle of a vibrating ladder, we feel not only our feet on the round, but the ladder's feet against the ground far below, If we shake a locked iron gate we feel trie middle, on which our hands rest, move, but we equally feel the sta bility of the ends where the hinges and the lock are, and we seem to feel all three at once.* And yet the place where the contact is received is in all these cases the skin, whose sensations accordingly are sometimes interpreted as objects on the surface, and at other times as objects a long distance off. We shall learn in the chapter on Space that our feelings of our own movement are principally due to the sensibility of our rotating joints. Sometimes by fixing the attention, say on our elbow-joint, we can feel the movement in the joint itself; but we always are simultaneously conscious of the path which during the movement our finger-tips describe through the air, and yet these same finger-tips themselves are in no way physically modified by the motion. A blow on our ulnar nerve behind the elbow is felt both there and in the fingers. Eefrigeration of the elbow pro duces pain in the fingers/ Electric currents passed through nerve-trunks, whether of cutaneous or of more special sen sibility (such as the optic nerve), give rise to sensations which are vaguely localized beyond the nerve-tracts traversed. Persons whose legs or arms have been ampu tated are, as is well known, apt to preserve an illusory feeling of the lost hand or foot being there. Even when they do not have this feeling constantly, it may be occa sionally brought back. This sometimes is the result of exciting electrically the nerve- trunks buried in the stump. " I recently faradized," says Dr. Mitchell, " a case of disarticulated shoulder without warning my patient of the possible result. 7 ''or two years he had altogether ceased to feel the limb. As the current affected the brachial plexus of nerves he suddenly cried aloud, ' Oh the hand,— the hand ! ' and attempted to seize the missing member. The phantom *Lotze: Med. Psych., 428-433; Lipps: Grundtatsachen des Seelenle bens, 582. SENSATION. 39 T had conjured up swiftly disappeared, but no spirit could have more amazed the man, so real did it seem." * Now the apparent position of the lost extremity varies. Often the foot seems on the ground, or follows the position of the artificial foot, where one is used. Sometimes where the arm is lost the elbow will seem bent, and the hand in a fixed position on the breast. Sometimes, again, the position is non-natural, and the hand will seem to bud straight out of the shoulder, or the foot to be on the same level with the knee of the remaining leg. Sometimes, again, the position is vague ; and sometimes it is ambiguous, as in another patient of Dr. Weir Mitchell's who "lost his leg at the age of eleven, and remembers that the foot by degrees approached, and at last reached the knee. When he began to wear an artificial leg it reassumed in time its old position, and he is never at present aware of tha leg as shortened, unless for some time he talks and thinks of the stump, and of the missing leg, when . . . the direction of attention to the part causes a feeling of discomfort, and the subjective sensation of active and unpleasant movement of the toes. With these feelings returns at once the delusion of the foot as being placed at the knee." All these facts, and others like them, can easily be de scribed as if our sensations might be induced by circum stances to migrate from their original locality near the brain or near the surface of the body, and to appear farther off ; and (under different circumstances) to return again after having migrated. But a little analysis of what happens shows us that this description is inaccurate. The objectivity with which each of our sensations originally comes to us, the roomy and spatial character ivhich is a primi tive part of its content, is not in the first instance relative to any other sensation. The first time we open our eyes we get an optical object which is a place, but which is not yet placed in relation to any other object, nor identified with any place otherwise known. It is a place with which so far we are only acquainted. When later we know that this same place is in ' front ' of us, that only means that we have learned Something about it, namely, that it is congruent with that * Injuries to Nerves (Philadelphia, 1872), p. 350 ff. 40 PSYCHOLOGY. other place, called 'front,' which is given us by certain sen sations of the arm and hand or of the head and body. But at the first moment of our optical experience, even though we already had an acquaintance with our head, hand, and body, we could not possibly know anything about their relations to this new seen object. It could not be immedi ately located in respect of them. How its place agrees with the places which their feelings yield is a matter of which only later experience can inform us; and in the next chapter we shall see with some detail how later experience does this by means of discrimination, association, selection, and other constantly working functions of the mind. When, therefore, the baby grasps at the moon, that does not mean that what he sees fails to give him the sensation which he afterwards knows as distance ; it means only that he has not learned at what tactile or manual distance things which ap pear at that visual distance are.* And when a person just operated for cataract gropes close to his face for far-off objects, that only means the same thing. All the ordinary optical signs of differing distances are absent from the poor creature's sensation anyhow. His vision is monocular (only one eye being operated at a time); the lens is gone, and every thing is out of focus; he feels photophobia, lachry- mation, and other painful resident sensations of the eyeball itself, whose place he has long since learned to know in tactile terms ; what wonder, then, that the first tactile reac tion which the new sensations provoke should be one associated with the tactile situation of the organ itself? And as for his assertions about the matter, what wonder, again, if, as Prof. Paul Janet says, they are still expressed in the tactile language which is the only one he knows. " To be touched; means for him to receive an impression with out first making a movement." His eye gets such an impression now ; so he can only say that the objects are * touching it.' " All his language, borrowed from touch, but applied to the objects of his sight, make us think that he perceives differently from ourselves, * In reality it probably means only a restless movement of desire, which he might make even after he had become aware of his impotence to touch the object. SENSATION. 41 whereas, at bottom, it is only his different way of talking about the same experience. " * The other cases of translocation of our sensations are equally easily interpreted without supposing any ' projec tion ' from a centre at which they are originally perceived. Unfortunately the details are intricate ; and what I say now can only be made fully clear when we come to the next chapter. We shall then see that we are constantly select ing certain of our sensations as realities and degrading others to the status of signs of these. When we get one of the signs we think of the reality signified ; and the strange thing is that then the reality (which need not be itself a sensation at all at the time, but only an idea) is so interest ing that it acquires an hallucinatory strength, which may even eclipse that of the relatively uninteresting sign and en tirely divert our attention from the latter. Thus the sen sations to which our joints give rise when they rotate are signs of what, through a large number of other sensations, tactile and optical, we have come to know as the movement of the whole limb. This movement of the whole limb is what we think of when the joint's nerves are excited in that way ; and its place is so much more important than the joint's place that our sense of the latter is taken up, so to speak, into our perception of the former, and the sensation of the movement seems to diffuse itself into our very fingers and toes. But by abstracting our attention from the sug gestion of the entire extremity we can perfectly well per ceive the same sensation as if it were concentrated in one spot. We can identify it with a differently located tactile and visual image of * the joint ' itself. Just so when we feel the tip of our cane against the ground. The peculiar sort of movement of the hand (im possible in one direction, but free in every other) which we experience when the tip touches 'the ground,' is a sign to us of the visual and tactile object which we already * Revue Philosophique, vii. p. 1 ff., an admirable critical article, in the course of which M. Janet gives a bibliography of the cases in question. See also Dunan: iMd. xxv. 165-7. They are also discussed and similarly interpreted by T. K. Abbot : Sight and Touch (1864), chapter x. 42 PSYCHOLOGY. know under that name. We think of 'the ground ' as being; there and giving us the sensation of this kind of movement. The sensation, we say, comes from the ground. The ground's place seems to be its place ; although at the same time, and for very similar practical reasons, we think of another optical and tactile object, ' the hand ' namely, and consider that us place also must be the place of our sensation. In other words, we take an object or sensible content A, and confounding it with another object otherwise known, B, or with two objects otherwise known, B and C, we identify its place with their places. But in all this there is no 'project ing ' (such as the extradition-philosophers talk of) of A out of an original place ; no primitive location which it first occupied, away from these other sensations, has to be con tradicted ; no natural ' centre,' from which it is expelled, exists. That would imply that A aboriginally came to us in definite local relations with other sensations, for to be out of B and C is to be in local relation with them as much as to be mthem is so. But it was no more out of B and C than it was in them when it first came to us. It simply had nothing to do with them. To say that we feel a sen sation's seat to be ' in the brain ' or ' against the eye ' or ' under the skin ' is to say as much about it and to deal with it in as non-primitive a way as to say that it is a mile off. These are all secondary perceptions, ways of defining the sensation's seat per aliud. They involve numberless associations, identifications, and imaginations, and admit a great deal of vacillation and uncertainty in the result.* / conclude, then, that there is no truth in the f eccentric pro jection ' theory. It is due to the confused assumption that the bodily processes which cause a sensation must also be its seat, f But sensations have no seat in this sense. They * The intermediary and shortened locations of the lost hand and foot in the amputation cases also show this. It is easy to see why the phantom foot might continue to follow the position of the artificial one. But I confess that I cannot explain its half way -positions. f It is from this confused assumption that the time-honored riddle comes, of how, with an upside-down picture on the retina, we can see things right-side up. Our consciousness is naively supposed to inhabit the SENSATION. 43 become seats for each other, as fast as experience associates them together ; but that violates no primitive seat possessed by any one of them. And though our sensations cannot then so analyze and talk of themselves, yet at their very first appearance quite as much as at any later date are they cognizant of all those qualities which we end by extracting and conceiving under the names of objectivity, exteriority, and extent. It is surely subjectivity and interiority which are the notions latest acquired by the human mind. * picture and to feel the picture's position as related to other objects of space. But the truth is that the picture is non-existent either as a habitat or as any thing else, for immediate consciousness. Our notion of it is an enormous ly late conception. The outer object is given immediately with all those qualities which later are named and determined in relation to other sensa tions. The ' bottom ' of this object is where we see what by touch we afterwards know as OUT feet, the ' top ' is the place in which we see what we know as other people's heads, etc., etc. Berkeley long ago made this matter perfectly clear (see his Essay towards a new Theory of Vision, §§ 93-98, 113-118). * For full justification the reader must see the next chapter. He may object, against the summary account given now, that in a babe's immediate field of vision the various things which appear are located relatively to each other from the outset. I admit that if discriminated, they would appear so located. But they are parts of the content of one sensation, not sensations separately experienced, such as the text is concerned with. The fully de veloped 'world,' in which all our sensations ultimately find location, is nothing but an imaginary object framed after the pattern of the field of vision, by the addition and continuation of one sensation upon another in an orderly and systematic way. In corroboration of my text I must refer to pp. 57-60 of RiehPs book quoted above on page 32, and to Uphues : Wahrnehmung und Empfindung (1888), especially the Einleitung and pp. 51-61. CHAPTEK XVIII. IMAGINATION. Sensations, once experienced, modify the nervous organism, %o that copies of them arise again in the mind after the orig inal outward stimulus is gone. No mental copy, however, can arise in the mind, of any kind of sensation which has never been directly excited from without. The blind may dream of sights, the deaf of sounds, for years after they have lost their vision or hearing ; * but the man born deaf can never be made to imagine what sound is like, nor can the man born blind ever have a mental vision. In Locke's words, already quoted, " the mind can frame unto itself no one new simple idea." The originals of them all must have been given from without. Fantasy, or Imagination, are the names given to the faculty of repro ducing copies of originals once felt. The imagination is called * reproductive ' when the copies are literal ; * pro ductive ' when elements from different originals are recom- bined so as to make new wholes. After-images belong to sensation rather than to imagi nation ; so that the most immediate phenomena of imagi nation would seem to be those tardier images (due to what the Germans call Sinnesgeddchtniss) which were spoken of in Vol. I, p. 647, — coercive hauntings of the mind by echoes of unusual experiences for hours after the latter have taken place. The phenomena ordinarily ascribed to imagination, however, are those mental pictures of possible sensible * Prof. Jastrow has ascertained by statistical inquiry among the blind that if their blindness have occurred before a period embraced between the fifth and seventh years the visual centres seem to decay, and visual dreams and images are gradually outgrown. If sight is lost after the seventh year, visual imagination seems to survive through life. See Prof. J. 's in teresting article on the Dreams of the Blind, in the New Princeton Review for January 1888. 44 IMAGINATION. 45 experiences, to which the ordinary processes of associa tive thought give rise. When represented with surroundings concrete enough to constitute a date, these pictures, when they revive, form recollections. We have already studied the machinery of recollection in Chapter XVI. When the mental pictures are of data freely combined, and reproducing no past com bination exactly, we have acts of imagination properly so called. OUK IMAGES ABE USUALLY VAGUE. For the ordinary * analytic ' psychology, each sensibly discernible element of the object imagined is repre sented by its own separate idea, and the total object is imagined by a ' cluster ' or * gang ' of ideas. We have seen abundant reason to reject this view (see p. 276 ff.). An imagined object, however complex, is at any one moment thought in one idea, which is aware of all its qualities to- gether. If I slip into the ordinary way of talking, and speak of various ideas * combining,' the reader will under stand that this is only for popularity and convenience, and he will not construe it into a concession to the atomistic theory in psychology. Hume was the hero of the atomistic theory. Not only were ideas copies of original impressions made on the sense- organs, but they were, according to him, completely ade quate copies, and were all so separate from each other as to possess no manner of connection. Hume proves ideas in the imagination to be completely adequate copies, not by appeal to observation, but by a priori reasoning, as fol lows: ' ' The mind cannot form any notion of quantity or quality, without forming a precise notion of the degrees of each,1' for "'tis confessed that no object can appear to the senses ; or in other words, that no im pression* can become present to the mind, without being determined in its degrees both of quantity and quality. The confusion in which im pressions are sometimes involved proceeds only from their faintness and unsteadiness, not from any capacity in the mind to receive any im pression, which in its real existence has no particular degree nor pro portion. That is a contradiction in terms; and even implies the flattest * Impression means sensation for Hume. 46 PSYCHOLOG T. of all contradictions, viz. , that 'tis possible for the same thing both to be and not to be. Now since all ideas are derived from impressions, and are nothing but copies and representations of them, whatever is true of the one must be acknowledged concerning the other. Impres sions and ideas differ only in their strength and vivacity. The forego ing conclusion is not founded on any particular degree of vivacity. It -cannot therefore be affected by any variation in that particular. An idea is a weaker impression ; and as a strong impression must neces sarily have a determinate quantity and quality, the case must be the same with its copy or representative." * The slightest introspective glance will show to anyone the falsity of this opinion. Hume surely had images of his own works without seeing distinctly every word and letter upon the pages which floated before his mind's eye. His dictum is therefore an exquisite example of the way in which a man will be blinded by a priori theories to the most flagrant facts. It is a rather remarkable thing, too, that the psychologists of Hume's own empiricist school have, as a rule, been more guilty of this blindness than their opponents. The fundamental facts of consciousness have been, on the whole, more accurately reported by the spiritualistic writers. None of Hume's pupils, so far as I know, until Taine and Huxley, ever took the pains to con tradict the opinion of their master. Prof. Huxley in his brilliant little work on Hume set the matter straight in the following words : "When complex impressions or complex ideas are reproduced as memories, it is probable that the copies never give all the details of the originals with perfect accuracy, and it is certain that they rarely do so. No one possesses a memory so good, that if he has only once observed a natural object, a second inspection does not show him something that he has forgotten. Almost all, if not all, our memories are therefore sketches, rather than portraits, of the originals — the salient features are obvious, while the subordinate characters are obscure or unrepre sented. "Now, when several complex impressions which are more or less different from one another — let us say that out of ten impressions in each, six are the same in all, and four are different from all the rest — are successively presented to the mind, it is easy to see what must be the nature of the result. The repetition of the six similar impressions will strengthen the six corresponding elements of the complex idea, * Treatise on Human Nature, part i. § YII. IMAGINATION, 47 which will therefore acquire greater vividness ; while the four differing impressions of each will not only acquire no greater strength than they had at first, but, in accordance with the law of association, they will all tend to appear at once, and will thus neutralize one another. ' ' This mental operation may be rendered comprehensible by consid ering what takes place in the formation of compound photographs — when the images of the faces of six sitters, for example, are each re ceived on the same photographic plate, for a sixth of the time requisite to take one portrait. The final result is that all those points in which the six faces agree are brought out strongly, while all those in which they differ are left vague ; and thus what may be termed a generic por trait of the six, in contradistinction to a specific portrait of any one, is produced. ' ' Thus our ideas of single complex impressions are incomplete in one way, and those of numerous, more or less similar, complex im pressions are incomplete in another way ; that is to say, they are gen eric, not specific. And hence it follows that our ideas of the impres sions in question are not, in the strict sense of the word, copies of those impressions ; while, at the same time, they may exist in the mind in dependently of language. 1 ' The generic ideas which are formed from several similar, but not identical, complex experiences are what are called abstract or general ideas ; and Berkeley endeavored to prove that all general ideas are nothing but particular ideas annexed to a certain term, which gives them a more extensive signification, and makes them recall, upon oc casion, other individuals which are similar to them. Hume says that he regards this as ' one of the greatest and the most valuable discover ies that has been made of late years in the republic of letters,' and en deavors to confirm it in such a manner that it shall be ' put beyond all doubt and controversy. ' " I may venture to express a doubt whether he has succeeded in his object ; but the subject is an abstruse one ; and I must content my self with the remark, that though Berkeley's view appears to be largely applicable to such general ideas as are formed after language has been acquired, and to all the more abstract sort of conceptions, yet that gen eral ideas of sensible objects may nevertheless be produced in the way indicated, and may exist independently of language. In dreams, one sees houses, trees, and other objects, which are perfectly recognizable as such, but which remind one of the actual objects as seen ' out of the corner of the eye,' or of the pictures thrown by a badly-focussed magic lantern. A man addresses us who is like a figure seen in twilight ; or we travel through countries where every feature of the scenery is vague ; the outlines of the hills are ill-marked, and the rivers have no defined banks. They are, in short, generic ideas of many past impressions of men, hills, and rivers. An anatomist who occupies himself intently with the examination of several specimens of some new kind of animal, in course of time acquires so vivid a conception of its form and struc- 48 PSYCHOLOGY. ture that the idea may take visible shape and become a sort of waking dream. But the figure which thus presents itself is generic, not spe cific. It is no copy of any one specimen, but, more or less, a mean of the series ; and there seems no reason to doubt that the minds of chil dren before they learn to speak, and of deaf-mutes, are peopled wifh similarly generated generic ideas of sensible objects.1' * Are Vague Images * Abstract Ideas ' ? The only point which I am tempted to criticise in this account is Prof. Huxley's identification of these generic images with * abstract or general ideas ' in the sense of universal concep tions. Taine gives the truer view. He writes : "Some years ago I saw in England, in Kew Gardens, for the first time, araucarias, and I walked along the beds looking at these strange plants, with their rigid bark and compact, short, scaly leaves, of a sombre green, whose abrupt, rough, bristling form cut in upon the fine softly-lighted turf of the fresh grass-plat. If I now inquire what this experience has left in me, I find, first, the sensible representation of an araucaria ; in fact, I have been able to describe almost exactly the form and color of the plant. But there is a difference between this represen tation and the former sensations, of which it is the present echo. The internal semblance, from which I have just made my description, is vague, and my past sensations were precise. For, assuredly, each of the araucarias I saw then excited in me a distinct visual sensation ; there are no two absolutely similar plants in nature ; I observed perhaps twenty or thirty araucarias ; without a doubt each one of them differed from the others in size, in girth, by the more or less obtuse angles of its branches, by the more or less abrupt jutting out of its scales, by the style of its texture ; consequently, my twenty or thirty visual sensations were different. But no one of these sensations has completely survived in its echo ; the twenty or thirty revivals have blunted one another ; thus, upset and agglutinated by their resemblance they are confounded together, and my present representation is their residue only. This is the product, or rather the fragment, which is deposited in us, when we have gone through a series of similar facts or individuals. Of our numerous experiences there remain on the following day four or five more or less distinct recollections, which, obliterated themselves, leave behind in us a simple colorless, vague representation, into which enter as components various reviving sensations, in an utterly feeble, incom plete, and abortive state. — But this representation is not the general and abstract idea. It is but its accompaniment, and, if I may say so, the- ore from which it is extracted. For the representation, though badly sketched, is a sketch, the sensible sketch of a distinct individual. . . . But my abstract idea corresponds to the whole class ; it differs, thenr from the representation of an individual. — Moreover, my abstract idea * Huxley's Hume, pp. 92-94. IMAGINATION. 4& is perfectly clear and determinate ; now that I possess it, I never fail to recognize an araucaria among the various plants which may be shown me ; it differs then from the confused and floating representation I have of some particular araucaria." * In other words, a blurred picture is just as much a single mental fact as a sharp picture is ; and the use of either picture by the mind to symbolize a whole doss of individuals is a new mental function, requiring some other modification of con sciousness than the mere perception that the picture is distinct or not. I may bewail the indistinctness of my mental image of my absent friend. That does not prevent my thought from meaning him alone, however. And I may mean all mankind, with perhaps a very sharp image of one man in my mind's eye. The meaning is a function of the more 'transitive' parts of consciousness, the 'fringe' of relations which we feel surrounding the image, be the latter sharp or dim. This was explained in a previous place (see p. 473 ff., especially the note to page 477), and I would not touch upon the matter at all here but for its historical interest. Our ideas or images of past sensible experiences may then be either distinct and adequate or dim, blurred, and incomplete. It is likely that the different degrees in which different men are able to make them sharp and complete has had something to do with keeping up such philosophic disputes as that of Berkeley with Locke over abstract ideas. Locke had spoken of our possessing ' the general idea of a, triangle ' which " must be neither oblique nor rectangle, neither equilateral, equicrural, nor scalenon, but all and none of these at once." Berkeley says : 44 If any man has the faculty of framing in his mind such an idea of a triangle as is here described, it is in vain to pretend to dispute him out of it, nor would I go about it. All I desire is that the reader would fully and certainly inform himself whether he has such an idea or no." f Until very recent years it was supposed by all philoso-' phers that there was a typical human mind which all indi- i vidual minds were like, and that propositions of universal I validity could be laid down about such faculties as ' the * On Intelligence (N. Y.), vol. n. p. 139. t Principles, Introd. § 13. Compare also the passage quoted above, p. 469 50 PSYCHOLOGY. Imagination.' Lately, however, a mass of revelations have ' poured in, which make us see how false a view this is. There are imaginations, not 'the Imagination,' and they must be studied in detail. INDIVIDUALS DIFPEB IN IMAGINATION. The first breaker of ground in this direction was Fechner, in 1860. Feehner was gifted with unusual talent for sub jective observation, and in chapter XLIV of his * Psychophy- sik' he gave the results of a most careful comparison of his own optical after-images, with his optical memory-pictures, together with accounts by several other individuals of their optical memory-pictures.* The result was to show a great * The differences noted by Fechner between after-images and images of imagination proper are as follows : Imagination-images. Feel subject to our spontaneity ; Have, as it were, more body ; Are blurred ; Are darker than even the darkest black of the% after-images ; Have lively coloration ; Incessantly disappear, and have to be renewed by an effort of will. At last even this fails to revive them. Can be exchanged at will for others. Cannot violate the necessary laws of appearance of their originals— e. g. , a man cannot be imagined from in front and behind at once. The imagination must walk round him, so to speak ; Are more easily had with open than with shut eyes ; Need not follow movements of head or eyes. The field is extensive in three dimen sions, and objects can be imagined in it above or behind almost as easily as in front. In imagining, the attention feels at if drawn backwards towards th& brain. Feel coercive ; Seem unsubstantial, vaporous ; Are sharp in outline ; Are bright ; Are almost colorless ; Are continuously enduring ; Cannot be voluntarily changed. Are exact copies of originals. Are more easily got with shut than with open eyes ; Seem to move when the head or eyes move ; The field within which they appear (with closed eyes) is dark, con tracted, flat, close to the eyes, in front, and the images have no perspective ; The attention seems directed for wards towards the sense-organ, in observing after-images Finally, Fechner speaks of the impossibility of attending to both after. IMAGINATION. 61 personal diversity. " It would be interesting," he writes, " to work up the subject statistically ; and I regret that other occupations have kept me from fulfilling my earlier intention to proceed in this way." 1 echner's intention was independently executed by Mr. Galton, the publication of whose results in 1880 may be said to have made an era in descriptive Psychology. " It is not necessary," says Galton, " to trouble the reader with my early tentative steps. After the inquiry had been fairly started it took the form of submitting a certain number of printed questions to a large number of persons. There is hardly any more difficult task than that of framing questions which are not likely to be misunderstood, which admit of easy reply, and which cover the ground of inquiry. I did my best in these respects, without forgetting the most important part of all — namely, to tempt my correspondents to write freely in fuller ex planation of their replies, and on cognate topics as well. These sepa rate letters have proved more instructive and interesting by far than the replies to the set questions. " The first group of the ratbei long series of queries related to the illumination, definition, and coloring of the mental image, and were framed thus : " l Before addressing yourself to any of the Questions on the opposite page, think of some definite object — suppose it is your breakfast- table as you sat down to it this morning— and consider carefully the picture that rises before your mind's eye. " ' 1. Illumination. — Is the image dim or fairly clear ? Is its bright ness comparable to that of the actual scene ? " * 2. Definition. — Are all the objects pretty well defined at the same time, or is the place of sharpest definition at any one moment more con tracted than it is in a real scene ? " ' 3. Coloring. — Are the colors of the china, of the toast, bread-crust, mustard, meat, parsley, or whatever may have been on the table, quite distinct and natural ? ' " The earliest results of my inquiry amazed me. I had begun by questioning friends in the scientific world, as they were the most likely class of men to give accurate answers concerning this faculty of visual- iinages and imagination -images at once, even when they are of the object and might be expected to combine. All these differences are true of Fechner ; but many of them would be untrue of other persons. I quote them as a type of observation which any reader with sufficient patience may repeat. To them may be added, as a universal proposition, that after- images seem larger if we project them on a distant screen, and smaller If we project them on a near one, whilst no such change takes place in mental pictures. -W5*trxJtov^l*4 W^ttvX fyptf'lf * -i. - \ . I. .£.+** i~*i»4£^-i 0V PSYCHOLOGY. izing, to which novelists and poets continually allude, which has left, an abiding mark on the vocabularies of every language, and which, supplies the material out of which dreams and the well-known halluci nations of sick people are built. '-To my astonishment, I found that the great majority of the men of science to whom I first applied protested that mental imagery was unknown to them, and they looked on me as fanciful and fantastic in supposing that the words ' mental imagery ' really expressed what I believed everybody supposed them to mean. They had no more notion of its true nature than a color-blind man, who has not discerned his defect, has of the nature of color. They had a mental deficiency of which they were unaware, and naturally enough supposed that those who affirmed they possessed it were romancing. To illustrate their mental attitude it will be sufficient to quote a few lines from the letter of one of my correspondents, who writes : " * These questions presuppose assent to some sort of a proposition re garding the "mind's eye," and the "images" which it sees. . . . This points to some initial fallacy. ... It is only by a figure of speech that I can describe my recollection of a scene as a " mental image " which lean "see "with my "mind's eye." . . . I do not see it . . . anymore than a man sees the thousand lines of Sophocles which under due pressure he is ready to repeat. The memory possesses it,' etc. ' ' Much the same result followed inquiries made for me by a friend among members of the French Institute. " On the other hand, when I spoke to persons whom I met in gen eral society, I found an entirely different disposition to prevail. Many men and a yet larger number of women, and many boys and girls, declared that they habitually saw mental imagery, and that it was- perfectly distinct to them and full of color. The more I pressed and crossed-questioned them, professing myself to be incredulous, the more obvious was the truth of their first assertions. They described their imagery in minute detail, and they spoke in a tone of surprise at my apparent hesitation in accepting what they said. I felt that I my self should have spoken exactly as they did if I had been describing a scene that lay before my eyes, in broad daylight, to a blina man who persisted in doubting the reality of vision. Reassured by this happier experience, I recommenced to inquire among scientific men, and soon found scattered instances of what I sought, though in by no means the same abundance as elsewhere. I then circulated my questions more generally among my friends and through their hands, and obtained re plies . . . from persons of both sexes, and of various ages, and in the end from occasional correspondents in nearly every civilized country. " I have also received batches of answers from various educational establishments both in England and America, which were made after the masters had fully explained the meaning of the questions, and in terested the boys in them. These have the merit of returns derived from a general census, which my other data lack, because I cannot for IMAGINATION. 53 a moment suppose that the writers of the latter are a haphazard pnv portion of those to whom they were sent. Indeed I know of some who, disavowing all possession of the power, and of many others who, pos sessing it in too faint a degree to enable them to express what their experiences really were, in a manner satisfactory to themselves, sent no returns at all. Considerable statistical similarity was, however, ob served between the sets of returns furnished by the schoolboys and those sent by my separate correspondents, and I may add that they ac cord in this respect with the oral information I have elsewhere obtained. The conformity of replies from so many different sources which was clear from the first, the fact of their apparent trustworthiness being on the whole much increased by cross-examination (though I could give one or two amusing instances of break-down), and the evident effort made to give accurate answers, have convinced me that it is a much easier matter than I had anticipated to obtain trustworthy replies to psychological questions. Many persons, especially women and intelli gent children, take pleasure in introspection, and strive their very best to explain their mental processes. I think that a delight in self -dissec tion must be a strong ingredient in the pleasure that many are said to take in confessing themselves to priests. " Here, then, are two rather notable results : the one is the proved facility of obtaining statistical insight into the processes of other per sons' minds, whatever a priori objection may have been made as to its possibility ; and the other is that scientific men, as a class, have feeble powers of visual representation. There is no doubt whatever on the latter point, however it may be accounted for. My own conclusion is that an over-ready perception of sharp mental pictures is antagonistic to the acquirement of habits of highly-generalized and abstract thought, especially when the steps of reasoning are carried on by words as symbols, and that if the faculty of seeing the pictures was ever possessed by men who think hard, it is very apt to be lost by disuse. The highest minds are probably those in which it is not lost, but subordinated, and is ready for use on suitable occasions. I am, however, bound to say that the missing faculty seems to be replaced so serviceably by other modes of conception, chiefly, I believe, connected with the incipient motor sense, not of the eyeballs only but of the muscles generally, that men who declare themselves entirely deficient in the power of seeing mental pictures can nevertheless give lifelike descriptions of what they have seen, and can otherwise express themselves as if they were gifted with a vivid visual imagination. They can also become painters of the rank of Royal Academicians* . . . * [I am myself a good draughtsman, and have a very lively interest in pictures, statues, architecture and decoration, and a keen sensibility to artistic effects. But I am an extremely poor visualizer, and find myself often unable to reproduce in my mind's eye pictures which I have most carefully examined. — W. J.] 54 PSYCHOLOGY. "It is a mistake to suppose that sharp sight is accompanied by clear visual memory. I have not a few instances in which the independence of the two faculties is emphatically commented on ; and I have at least one clear case where great interest in outlines and accurate appreciation of straightness, squareness, and the like, is unaccompanied by the power of visualizing. Neither does the faculty go with dreaming. I have cases where it is powerful, and at the same time where dreams are rare and faint or altogether absent. One friend tells me that his dreams have not the hundredth part of the vigor of his waking fancies. tk The visualizing and the identifying powers are by no means nec essarily combined. A distinguished writer on metaphysical topics as sures me that he is exceptionally quick at recognizing a face that he has seen before, but that he cannot call up a mental image of any face With clearness. " Some persons have the power of combining in a single perception more than can be seen at any one moment by the two eyes. . . . "I find that a few persons can, by what they often describe as a kind of touch -sight, visualize at the same moment all round the image of a solid body. Many can do so nearly, but not altogether round that of a terrestrial globe. An eminent mineralogist assures me that he is able to imagine simultaneously all the sides of a crystal with which he is familiar. I may be allowed to quote a curious faculty of my own in respect to this. It is exercised only occasionally and in dreams, or rather in nightmares, but under those circumstances I am perfectly conscious of embracing an entire sphere in a single perception. It ap pears to lie within my mental eyeball, and to be viewed centripetally. ' ' This power of comprehension is practically attained in many cases by indirect methods. It is a common feat to take in the whole sur roundings of an imagined room with such a rapid mental sweep as to leave some doubt whether it has not been viewed simultaneously. Some persons have the habit of viewing objects as though they were partly transparent ; thus, if they so dispose a globe in their imagination as to see both its north and south poles at the same time, they will not be able to see its equatorial parts. They can also perceive all the rooms of an imaginary house by a single mental glance, the walls and floors being as if made of glass. A fourth class of persons have the habit of recall ing scenes, not from the point of view whence they were observed, but from a distance, and they visualize their own selves as actors on the mental stage. By one or other of these ways, the power of seeing the whole of an object, and not merely one aspect of it, is possessed by many persons. "The place where the image appears to lie differs much. Most per sons see it in an indefinable sort of way, others see it in front of the eye, others at a distance corresponding to reality. There exists a power which is rare naturally, but can, I believe, be acquired without much difficulty, of projecting a mental picture upon a piece of paper, and of IMAGINATION. 55 holding it fast there, so that it can be outlined with a pencil. To this I shall recur. "Images usually do not become stronger by dwelling on them; the first idea is commonly the most vigorous, but this is not always the case. Sometimes the mental view of a locality is inseparably connected with the sense of its position as regards the points of the compass, real or imaginary. I have received full and curious descriptions from very different sources of this strong geographical tendency, and in one or two cases I have reason to think it allied to a considerable faculty of geographical comprehension. " The power of visualizing is higher in the female sex than in the male, and is somewhat, but not much, higher in public-school boys than in men. After maturity is reached, the further advance of age does not seem to dim the faculty, but rather the reverse, judging from numerous statements to that effect; but advancing years are sometimes accom panied by a growing habit of hard abstract thinking, and in these cases — not uncommon among those whom I have questioned — the faculty undoubtedly becomes impaired. There is reason to believe that it is very high in some young children, who seem to spend years of difficulty in distinguishing between the subjective and objective world. Language and book-learning certainly tend to dull it. "The visualizing faculty is a natural gift, and, like all natural gifts, has a tendency to be inherited. In this faculty the tendency to inheri tance is exceptionally strong, as I have abundant evidence to prove, especially in respect to certain rather rare peculiarities, . . . which, when they exist at all, are usually found among two, three, or more brothers and sisters, parents, children, uncles and aunts, and cousins. " Since families differ so much in respect to this gift, we may suppose that races would also differ, and there can be no doubt that such is the case. I hardly like to refer to civilized nations, because their natural faculties are too much modified by education to allow of their being appraised in an off-hand fashion. I may, however, speak of the French, who appear to possess the visualizing faculty in a high degree. The peculiar ability they show in prearranging ceremonials and fetes of all kinds, and their undoubted genius for tactics and strategy, show that they are able to foresee effects with unusual clearness. Their ingenuity in all technical contrivances is an additional testimony in the same direc tion, and so is their singular clearness of expression. Their phrase ' figurez-vous,' or ' picture to yourself ,' seems to express their dominant mode of perception. Our equivalent of ' imagine ' is ambiguous. "I have many cases of persons mentally reading off scores when playing the pianoforte, or manuscript when they are making speeches. One statesman has assured me that a certain hesitation in utterance which he has at times is due to his being plagued by the image of his 56 PSYCHOLOGY. manuscript speech with its original erasures and corrections. He can not lay the ghost, and he puzzles in trying to decipher it. 44 Some few persons see mentally in print every word that is uttered; they attend to the visual equivalent and not to the sound of the words, and they read them off usually as from a long imaginary strip of paper, such as is unwound from telegraphic instruments." The reader will find further details in Mr. Galton's 'Inquiries into Human Faculty,' pp. 83-114.* I have myself for many years collected from each and all of my psychology-students descriptions of their own visual imagination ; and found (together with some curious idio syncrasies) corroboration of all the variations which Mr. Galton reports. As examples, I subjoin extracts from two cases near the ends of the scale. The writers are first cous ins, grandsons of a distinguished man of science. The one who is a good visualizer says : " This morning's breakfast-table is both dim and bright; it is dim if I try to think of it when my eyes are open upon any object; it is per fectly clear and bright if I think of it with my eyes closed. —All the objects are clear at once, yet when I confine my attention to any one object it becomes far more distinct. — I have more power to recall color than any other one thing: if, for example, I were to recall a plate deco rated with flowers I could reproduce in a drawing the exact tone, etc. The color of anything that was on the table is perfectly vivid. — There is very little limitation to the extent of my images: I can see all four sides of a room, I can see all four sides of two, three, four, even more rooms with such distinctness that if you should ask me what was in any particular place in any one, or ask me to count the chairs, etc. , I could do it without the least hesitation.— The more I learn by heart the more clearly do I see images of my pages. Even before I can recite the lines I see them so that I could give them very slowly word for word, but my mind is so occupied in looking at my printed image that I have no idea of what I am saying, of the sense of it, etc. When I first found myself doing this I used to think it was merely because I knew the lines imperfectly; but I have quite convinced myself that I really do see an image. The strongest proof that such is really the fact is, I think, the following: "I can look down the mentally seen page and see the words that commence all the lines, and from any one of these words I can continue * See also McCosh and Osborne, Princeton Review, Jan. 1884. There are some good examples of high development of the Faculty in the London Spectator, Dec. 28, 1878, pp. 1631, 1634, Jan. 4, 11, 25, and March 18, 1879. IMAGINATION. 57 the line. I find this much easier to do if the words begin in a straight line than if there are breaks. Example : Etantfait Tons A des Quefit Ceres Avec Unfleur Comme (La Fontaine 8. iv.)" The poor visualizer says : " My ability to form mental images seems, from what I have studied of other people's images, to be defective, and somewhat peculiar. The process by which I seem to remember any particular event is not by a series of distinct images, but a sort of panorama, the faintest impres sions of which are perceptible through a thick fog.— I cannot shut my eyes and get a distinct image of anyone, although I used to be able to a few years ago, and the faculty seems to have gradually slipped away. — In my most vivid dreams, where the events appear like the most real facts, I am often troubled with a dimness of sight which causes the images to appear indistinct.— To come to the question of the breakfast- table there is nothing definite about it. Everything is vague. I can not say what I see. I could not possibly count the chairs, but I happen to know that there are ten. I see nothing in detail. — The chief thing is a general impression that I cannot tell exactly what I do see. The color ing is about the same, as far as I can recall it, only very much washed out. Perhaps the only color I can see at all distinctly is that of the table cloth, and I could probably see the color of the wall-paper if I could remember what color it was." A person whose visual imagination is strong finds it hard to understand how those who are without the faculty can think at all. Some people undoubtedly have no visual images at aU worthy of the name* and instead of seeing their breakfast-table, they tell you that they remember it or know what was on it. This knowing and remembering takes * Take the following report from one of my students : "I am unable to form in my mind's eye any visual likeness of the table whatever. After many trials, I can only get a hazy surface, with nothing on it or about it. I can see no variety in color, and no positive limitations in extent, while I cannot see whaf T see well enough to determine its position in respect to my eye, or to endow it with any quality of size. I am in the same position as to the word dog. I cannot see it in my mind's eye at all ; and so cannot tell whether I should have to run my eye along it, if I did see it. " 58 PSYCHOLOGY. place undoubtedly by means of verbal images, as was ex plained already in Chapter IX, pp. 265-6. The study of Aphasia (see p. 54) has of late years shown how unexpectedly great are the differences between individuals in respect of imagination. And at the same time the discrepan cies between lesion and symptom in different cases of the disease have been largely cleared up. In some indi-1 viduals the habitual ' thought-stuff,' if one may so call it, j is visual ; in others it is auditory, articulatory, or motor ; 1 in most, perhaps, it is evenly mixed. The same local cerebral injury must needs work different practical results in per sons who differ in this way. In one it will throw a much- used brain-tract out of gear ; in the other it may affect an unimportant region. A particularly instructive case was published by Charcot in 1883.* The patient was Mr. X., a merchant, born in Vienna, highly educated, master of German, Spanish, French, Greek, and Latin. Up to the beginning of the malady which took him to Professor Charcot, he read Homer at sight. He could, starting from any verse out of the first book of the Iliad, repeat the following verses without hesitating, by heart. Virgil and Horace were familiar. He also knew enough of modern Greek for business purposes. Up to within a year (from the time Charcot saw him) he enjoyed an exceptional visual memory. He no sooner thought of persons or things, but features, forms, and colors arose with the same clearness, sharpness, and accuracy as if the objects stood before him. When he tried to recall a fact or a figure in his voluminous polyglot correspondence, the letters themselves appeared before him with their entire content, irregularities, erasures and all. At school he recited from a mentally seen page which he read off line by line and letter by letter. In making computations, he ran his mental eye down imaginary columns of figures, and performed in this way the most varied operations of arithmetic. He could never think of a passage in a play without the entire scene, stage, actors, and audience appearing to him. He had been a great traveller. Being a good draughtsman, he used to sketch views which pleased him; and his memory always brought back the entire landscape exactly. If he thought of a conver sation, a saying, an engagement, the place, the people, the entire scene rose before his mind. His auditory memory was always deficient, or at least secondary He had no taste for music. * Progres Medical, 21 juillet. I abridge from the German report ot the case in Wilbrand: Die Seelenblindheit (1887). LdAUlNATION. 59 A year aud a half previous to examination, after business-anxieties, loss of sleep, appetite, etc., he noticed suddenly one day an extraordi nary change in himself. After complete confusion, there came a violent contrast between his old and his new state. Everything about him seemed so new and foreign that at first he thought he must be going mad. He was nervous and irritable. Although he saw all things dis tinct, he had entirely lost his memory for forms and colors. On ascer taining this, he became reassured as to his sanity. He soon discovered that he could carry on his affairs by using his memory in an altogether new way. He can now describe clearly the difference between his two conditions. Every time he returns to A., from which place business often calls him, he seems to himself as if entering a strange city. He views the monuments, houses, and streets with the same surprise as if he saw them for the first time. Gradually, however, his memory returns, and he finds himself at home again. When asked to describe the principal public place of the town, he answered, " I know that it is there, but it is impossible to imagine it, and I can tell you nothing about it. " He has often drawn the port of A. To-day he vainly tries to trace its principal outlines. Asked to draw a minaret, he reflects, says it is a square tower, and draws, rudely, four lines, one for ground, one for top, and two for sides. Asked to draw an arcade, he says, ' ' I remember that it contains semi-circular arches, and that two of them meeting at an angle make a vault, but how it looks I am absolutely unable to imagine." The profile of a man which he drew by request was as if drawn by a little child; and yet he confessed that he had been helped to draw it by look ing at the bystanders. Similarly he drew a shapeless scribble for a tree. He can no more remember his wife's and children's faces than he can remember the port of A. Even after being with them some time they seem unusual to him. He forgets his own face, and once spoke to his image in a mirror, taking it for a stranger. He complains of his loss of feeling for colors. " My wife has black hair, this I know; but I can no more recall its color than I can her person and features.'* This visual amnesia extends to dating objects from his childhood's years — paternal mansion, etc., forgotten. No other disturbances but this loss of visual images. Now when he seeks something in his correspondence, he must rummage among the letters like other men, until he meets the passage. He can recall only the first few verses of the Iliad, and must grope to read Homer, Virgil, and Horace. Figures which he adds he must now whisper to himself. He realizes clearly that he must help his memory out with auditory images, which he does with effort. The words and expressions which he recalls seem now to echo in his ear, an altogether novel sensation for him. If he wishes to learn by heart anything, a series of phrases for example, he must read them several times aloud, so as to impress his ear. When later he repeats the thing in question, the sensation of in- 60 PSYCHOLOGY. ward hearing which precedes articulation rises up in his mind. This feeling was formerly unknown to him. He speaks French fluently; but affirms that he can no longer think in French; but must get his French words by translating them from Spanish or German, the languages of his childhood. He dreams no more in visual terms, but only in words, usually Spanish words. A certain degree of verbal blindness affects him— he is troubled by the Greek alphabet, etc.* If this patient had possessed the auditory type of imag ination from the start, it is evident that the injury, what ever it was, to his centres for optical imagination, would have affected his practical life much less profoundly. u The auditory type" says M. A. Binet,f " appears to be rarer than the visual. Persons of this type imagine what they think of in the language of sound. In order to remember a lesson they impress upon their mind, not the look of the page, but the sound of the words. They reason, as well as remember, by ear. In performing a mental ad dition they repeat verbally the names of the figures, and add, as it were, the sounds, without any thought of the graphic signs. Imag ination also takes the auditory form. 'When I write a scene,' said Legouve to Scribe, ' I hear ; but you see. In each phrase which I write, the voice of tiie personage who speaks strikes my ear. Vous, qui etes le theatre meme, your actors walk, gesticulate before your eyes ; I am a listener, you a spectator.'— ' Nothing more true,1 said Scribe ; ' do you know where I am when I write a piece ? In the middle of the parterre.' It is clear that the pure audile, seeking to develop only a single one of his faculties, may, like the pure visualizer, perform astounding feats of memory— Mozart, for example, noting from memory the Miserere of the Sistine Chapel after two hearings ; the deaf Beethoven, composing and inwardly repeating his enormous symphonies. On the other hand, the man of auditory type, like the visual, is exposed to serious dangers ; for if he lose his auditory images, he is without resource and breaks do"Wn completely. " It is possible that persons with hallucinations of hearing, and in- * In a letter to Charcot this interesting patient adds that his character also is changed : "I was formerly receptive, easily made enthusiastic, and possessed a rich fancy. Now I am quiet and cold, and fancy never carries my thoughts away. ... I am much less susceptible than formerly to anger »r sorrow. I lately lost my dearly-beloved mother; but felt far less grief at the bereavement than if I had been able to see in my mind's eye her physiognomy and the phases of her suffering, and especially less than if 1 had been able to witness in imagination the outward effects of her un timely loss upon the members of the family. " f Psychologie du Raisonneinent (1886), p. 25. IMAGINATION. 61 dividuals afflicted with the mania that they are victims of persecution, may all belong to the auditory type ; and that the predominance of a certain kind of imagination may predispose to a certain order of hal lucinations, and perhaps of delirium. : The motor type remains — perhaps the most interesting of all, and certainly the one of which least is known. Persons who belong to this type [les moteurs, in French, motiles, as Mr. Galton proposes to call them in English] make use, in memory, reasoning, and all their intellectual operations, of images derived from movement. In order to understand this important point, it is enough to remember that ' all our perceptions, and in particular the important ones, those of sight and touch, contain as integral elements the movements of our eyes and limbs ; and that, if movement is ever an essential factor in our really seeing an object, it must be an equally essential factor when we see the same object in imagination ' (Ribot).* For example, the complex im pression of a ball, which is there, in our hand, is the resultant of optical impressions of touch, of muscular adjustments of the eye, of the move ments of our fingers, and of the muscular sensations which these yield. When we imagine the ball, its idea must include the images of these muscular sensations, just as it includes those of the retinal and epider mal sensations. They form so many motor images. If they were not earlier recognized to exist, that is because our knowledge of the muscu lar sense is relatively so recent. In older psychologies it never was mentioned, the number of senses being restricted to five. ' ' There are persons who remember a drawing better when they have followed its outlines with their finger. Lecoq de Boisbaudran used this means in his artistic teaching, in order to accustom his pupils to draw from memory. He made them follow the outlines of figures with a pencil held in the air, forcing them thus to associate muscular with visual memory. Galton quotes a curious corroborative fact. Colonel Moncrieff often observed in North America young Indians who, visit ing occasionally his quarters, interested themselves greatly in the engravings which were shown them. One of them followed with care with the point of his knife the outline of a drawing in the Illustrated London News, saying that this was to enable him to carve it out the better on his return home. In this case the motor images were to * [I am myself a very poor visualizer, and find that I can seldom call to mind even a single letter of the alphabet in purely retinal terms. I must trace the letter by running my mental eye over its contour in order that the image of it shall have any distinctness at all. On questioning a large number of other people, mostly students, I find that perhaps half of them say they have no such difficulty in seeing letters mentally. Many affirm that they can see an entire word at once, especially a short one like ' dog,' with no such feeling of creating the letters successively by tracing them with the eye.— W. J.] 62 PSYCHOLOGY. reinforce the visual ones. The young savage was a motor* . . . When one's motor images are destroyed, one loses one's remembrance of move ments, and sometimes, more curiously still, one loses the power of exe cuting them. Pathology gives us examples in motor aphasia, agraphia, etc. Take the case of agraphia. An educated man, knowing how to write, suddenly loses this power, as a result of cerebral injury. His hand and arm are in no way paralytic, yet he cannot write. Whence this loss of power ? He tells us himself : he no longer knows how. He has forgotten how to set about it to trace the letters, he has lost the memory of the movements to be executed, he has no longer the motor images which, when formerly he wrote, directed his hand. . . . Other patients, affected with word-blindness, resort to these motor images precisely to make amends for their other deficiency. . . . An individ ual affected in this way cannot read letters which are placed before his eyes, even although his sight be good enough for the purpose. This loss of the power of reading by sight may, at a certain time, be the only trouble the patient has. Individuals thus mutilated succeed in reading by an ingenious roundabout way which they often discover themselves : it is enough that they should trace the letters with their finger to under stand their sense. What happens in such a case ? How can the hand supply the place of the eye? The motor image gives the key to the problem. If the patient can read, so to speak, with his fingers, it is because in tracing the letters he gives himself a certain number of mus cular impressions which are those of writing. In one word, the patient reads by writing (Charcot): the feeling of the graphic movements sug gests the sense of what is being written as well as sight would." f The imagination of a blind-deaf mute like Laura Bridg- man must be confined entirely to tactile and motor material. All blind persons must belong to the l tactile ' and 'motile* types of the French authors. When the young man whose cataracts were removed by Dr. Franz was shown different geometric figures, he said he " had not been able to form from them the idea of a square and a disk until he perceived a sensa tion of what he saw in the points of his fingers, as if he really touched the objects." % Professor Strieker of Vienna, who seems to have the motile form of imagination developed in unusual strength, * It is hardly needful to say that in modern primary education, in which the blackboard is so much used, the children are taught their letters, etc., by all possible channels at once, sight, hearing, and movement. f See an interesting case of a similar sort, reported by Farges, in l'En« cephale, 7me An nee, p. 545. | Philosophical Transactions, 1841, p. 65. IMAGINATION. 63 given a very careful analysis of "his own case in a couple of monographs with which all students should be come familiar.* His recollections both of his own move ments and of those of other things are accompanied invariably by distinct muscular feelings in those parts of his body which would naturally be used in effecting or in following the movement. In thinking of a soldier march ing, for example, it is as if he were helping the image to march by marching himself in his rear. And if he sup presses this sympathetic feeling in his own legs, and con centrates all his attention on the imagined soldier, the latter becomes, as it were, paralyzed. In general his imagined movements, of whatsoever objects, seem paralyzed the moment no feelings of movement either in his own eyes or in his own limbs accompany them.f The movements of articulate speech play a predominant part in his mental life. "When after my experimental work I proceed to its description, as a rule I reproduce in the first instance only words, which I had already associated with the perception of the various details of the ob servation whilst the latter was going on. For speech plays in all my observing so important a part that I ordinarily clothe phenomena in words as fast as I observe them. " \ Most persons, on being asked in what sort of terms they imagine ivords, will say ' in terms of hearing.' It is not until their attention is expressly drawn to the point that they find it difficult to say whether auditory images or motor images connected with the organs of articulation predomi nate. A good way of bringing the difficulty to consciousness is that proposed by Strieker : Partly open your mouth and then imagine any word with labials or dentals in it, such as ' bubble,' * toddle.' Is your image under these conditions distinct ? To most people the image is at first * thick,' as the sound of the word would be if they tried to pronounce it with the lips parted. Many can never imagine the words * Studien tlber die Sprachvorstellungen (1880), and Studien ilber die Bewegungsvorstellungen (1882). f Prof. Strieker admits that by practice he has succeeded in making his eye-movements ' act vicariously ' for his leg-movements in imagining men walking. t Bewegungsvorstellungen, p. 6. 64 PSYCHOLOGY. clearly with the mouth open ; others succeed after a few preliminary trials. The experiment proves how dependent our verbal imagination is on actual feelings in lips, tongue, iaroat, larynx, etc. ' " When we recall the impression of a word or sentence, if we do not speak it out, we feel the twitter of the organs just about to come to that pc'nt. The articulating parts — the larynx, the tongue, the lips — are all sensitly excited ; a suppressed articulation is in fact the mate rial of our recollection, the intellectual manifestation, the idea of speech."* The open mouth in Strieker's experiment not only pre vents actual articulation of the labials, but our feeling of its openness keeps us from imagining their articulation, just as a sensation of glaring light will keep us from strongly imagining darkness. In persons whose auditory imagination is weak, the articulatory image seems to con stitute the whole material for verbal thought. Professor Strieker says that in his own case no auditory image enters- into the words of which he thinks. t Like most psycholo gists, however, he makes of his personal peculiarities a rule, and says that verbal thinking is normally and univer sally an exclusively motor representation. I certainly get auditory images, both of vowels and of consonants, in addition to the articulatory images or feelings on which this author lays such stress. And I find that numbers of my students, after repeating his experiments, come to this conclusion. There is at first a difficulty due to the open mouth. That, however, soon vanishes, as does also the difficulty of thinking of one vowel whilst continuously sounding another. What probably remains true, however, j is that most men have a less auditory and a more articu-l latory verbal imagination than they are apt to be aware of./ * Ba;a : Senses and Intellect, p. 339. 7 Studien iibe Sprachvorstellungen, 28, 31, etc. Cf. pp. 49-50, etc. A.gaiust Strieker, see Stumpf, Tonpsychol., 155-162, and Revue Phi- losophique, xx. 617. See also Paulhan, Rev. Philosophique, xvi. 405 Strieker replies to Paulhan in vol. xvm. p. 685. P. retorts in vol. xix p. 118. Strieker reports that out of 100 persons questioned he found only one who had no feeling in his lips when silently thinking the letters M B, P; and out of 60 only two who were conscious of no internal articulation whilst reading (pp 59-60). IMAGINATION. 65 Professor Strieker himself has acoustic images, and can imagine the sounds of musical instruments, and the pecul iar voice of a friend. A statistical inquiry on a large scale, into the variations of acoustic, tactile, and motor imagina tion, would probably bear less fruit than Galton's inquiry into visual images. A few monographs by competent ob servers, like Strieker, about their own peculiarities, would give much more valuable information about the diversities which prevail.* Toitch-images are very strong in some people. The most vivid touch-images come when we ourselves barely escape local injury, or when we see another injured. The place * I think it must be admitted that some people have no vivid substan tive images in any department of their sensibility. One of my students, an intelligent youth, denied so pertinaciously that there was anything in his mind at all when he thought, that I was much perplexed by his case. I my self certainly have no such vivid play of nascent movements or motor images as Professor Strieker describes. When I seek to represent a row of soldiers marching, all I catch is a view of stationary legs first in one phase of movement and then in another, and these views are extremely imperfect and momentary. Occasionally (especially when I try to stimulate my imagination, as by repeating Victor Hugo's lines about the regiment, " Leur pas est si correct, sans tarder ni courir, Qu'on croit voir des ciseaux se fermer et s'ouvrir,") I seem to get an instantaneous glimpse of an actual movement, but it is to the last degree dim and uncertain. All these images seem at first as if purely retinal. 1 think, however, that rapid eye-movements accompany them, though these latter give rise to such slight feelings that they are almost impossible of detection. Absolutely no leg-movements of my own are there ; in fact, to call such up arrests my imagination of the soldiers. My optical images are in general yery dim, dark, fugitive, and contracted. It would be utterly impossible to draw from them, and yet I perfectly well distinguish one from the other. My auditory images are excessively inade quate reproductions of their originals. I have no images of taste or smell. Touch-imagination is fairly distinct, but comes very little into play with most objects thought of. Neither is all my thought verbalized; for I have shadowy schemes of relation, as apt to terminate in a nod of the head or an expulsion of the breath as in a definite word. On the whole, vague images or sensations of movement inside of my head towards the various parts of space in which the terms I am thinking of either lie or are momentarily sym bolized to lie together with movements of the breath through my pharynx and nostrils, form a by no means inconsiderable part of my thought-stuff. I doubt whether my difficulty in giving a clearer account is wholly a mat ter of inferior power of introspective attention, though that doubtless pluya its part. Attention, ceteris pcvribu*, must always be inferior in proportion to the feebleness of the internal images which are offered it to hold on to 66 PSYCHOLOGY. may then actually tingle with the imaginary sensation— perhaps not altogether imaginary, since goose-flesh, pal ing or reddening, and other evidences of actual muscular contraction in the spot may result. " An educated man," says a writer who must always be quoted when it is question of the powers of imagination,* " told me once that on entering his house one day he received a shock from crushing the finger of one of his little children in the door. At the moment of his fright he felt a violent pain in the corresponding finger of his own body, and this pain abode with him three days." The same author makes the following discrimination, which probably most men could verify : " On the skin I easily succeed in bringing out suggested sensation* wherever I will. But because it is necessary to protract the mental ef fort I can only awaken such sensations as are in their nature prolonged, as warmth, cold, pressure. Fleeting sensations, as those of a prick, a cut, a blow, etc., I am unable to call up, because I cannot imagine them ex abrupto with the requisite intensity. The sensations of the former order I can excite upon any part of the skin; and they may become so lively that, whether I will or not, I have to pass my hand over the place just as if it were a real impression on the skin." \ Meyer's account of his own visual images is very interest ing ; and with it we may close our survey of differences be tween the normal powers of imagining in different indi viduals. " With much practice," he says, " I have succeeded in making it possible for me to call up subjective visual sensations at will. I tried all my experiments by day or at night with closed eyes. At first it was very difficult. In the first experiments which succeeded the whole picture was luminous, the shadows being given in a somewhat less strong bluish light. In later experiments I saw the objects dark, with bright outlines, or rather I saw outline drawings of them, bright on a dark ground. I can compare these drawings less to chalk drawings on a blackboard than to drawings made with phosphorus on a dark wall at night, though the phosphorus would show luminous vapors which were absent from my lines. If I wished, for example, to see a face, without intending that of a particular person, I saw the outline of a profile against the dark background. When I tried to repeat an ex- * Geo. Herm. Meyer, Untersuchungen ub. d. Physiol. d. Nervenf: (1848), p. 233. For other cases see Tuke's Influence of Mind upon Body chaps, n and vn. f Meyer, op. dt. p. 238. IMAGINATION. 67 periment of the elder Darwin I saw only the edges of the die as bright lines on a dark ground. Sometimes, however, I saw the die really white and its edges black ; it was then on a paler ground. I could soon at will change between a white die with black borders on a light field, and a black die with white borders on a dark field ; and I can do this at any moment now. After long practice . . . these experiments succeeded better still. I can now call before my eyes almost any object which I please, as a subjective appearance, and this in its own natural color and illumination. I see them almost always on a more or less light or dark, mostly dimly changeable ground. Even known faces I can see quite sharp, with the true color of hair and cheeks. It is odd that I see these faces mostly in profile, whereas those described [in the previous extract] were all full-face. Here are some of the final results of these experiments : " 1) Some time after the pictures have arisen they vanish or change into others, without my being able to prevent it. 1 ' 2) When the color does not integrally belong to the object, I cannot always control it. A face, e.g., never seems to me blue, but always in its natural color ; a red cloth, on the other hand, I can sometimes change to a blue one. " 3) I have sometimes succeeded in seeing pure colors without objects; they then fill the entire field of view. " 4) I often fail to see objects which are not known to me, mere fic tions of my fancy, and instead of them there will appear familiar ob jects of a similar sort ; for instance, I once tried to see a brass sword- hilt with a brass guard, instead of which the more familiar picture of a rapier-guard appeared. 44 5) Most of these subjective appearances, especially when they were bright, left after-images behind them when the eyes were quickly opened during their presence. For example, I thought of a silver stir rup, and after I had looked at it a while I opened my eyes and for a long while afterwards saw its after-image. ' k These experiments succeeded best when I lay quietly on my back and closed my eyes. I could bear no noise about me, as this kept the vision from attaining the requisite intensity. The experiments succeed with me now so easily that I am surprised they did not do so at first, and I feel as though they ought to succeed with everyone. The im portant point in them is to get the image sufficiently intense by the ex clusive direction of the attention upon it, and by the removal of all disturbing impressions." * The negative after-images ivhich succeeded upon Meyer's imagination when he opened his eyes are a highly interest ing, though rare, phenomenon. So far as I know there is Meyer, op. cit. pp. 238-41. 68 PSYCHOLOGY. only one other published report of a similar experience.* It would seem that in such a case the neural process corre sponding to the imagination must be the entire tract con cerned in the actual sensation, even down as far as the retina. This leads to a new question to which we may now turn — of what is THE NEURAL PROCESS "WHICH UNDERLIES IMAGINATION P The commonly-received idea is that it is only a milder degree of the same process which took place when the thing now imagined was sensibly perceived. Professor Bain writes: " Since a sensation in the first instance diffuses nerve-currents through the interior of the brain outwards to the organs of expression and movement, — the persistence of that sensation, after the outward exciting cause is withdrawn, can be but a continuance of the same dif fusive currents, perhaps less intense, but not otherwise different. The shock remaining in the ear and brain, after the sound of thunder, must pass through the same circles, and operate in the same way as during the actual sound. We can have no reason for believing that, in this self-sustaining condition, the impression changes its seat, or passes into some new circles that have the special property of retaining it. Every part actuated after the shock must have been actuated by the shock, only more powerfully. With this single difference of intensity, the mode of existence of a sensation existing after the fact is essentially the same as its mode of existence during the fact. . . . Now if this be the case with impressions persisting when the cause has ceased, what view are we to adopt concerning impressions reproduced by mental causes alone, or without the aid of the original, as in ordinary recollection ? What is the manner of occupation of the brain with a resuscitated feeling of resistance, a smell or a sound ? There is only one answer that seems admissable. The renewed feeling occupies the very same parts, and in the same manner, as the original feeling, and no other parts, nor in any other assignable manner. I imagine that if our present knowledge of the brain had been present to the earliest speculators, this is the only * That of Dr. Ch. Fere in the Revue Philosophique, xx. 364. Johannes Mtiller's account of hypnagogic hallucinations floating before the eyes for a few moments after these had been opened, seems to belong more to the category of spontaneous hallucinations (see his Physiology, London, 1842, p. 1394). It is impossible to tell whether the words in Wundt's Vorle- sungen, i. 387, refer to a personal experience of his own or not ; probably not. 11 va sans dire that an inferior visualizer like myself can get no such after-images. Nor have I as yet succeeded in getting report of any from my students. IMAGINATION. 69 hypothesis that would have occurred to them. For where should a past feeling be embodied, if not in the same organs as the feeling when present ? It is only in this way that its identity can be preserved ; a feeling differently embodied would be a different feeling." * It is not plain from Professor Bain's text whether by the * same parts ' he means only the same parts inside the brain, or the same peripheral parts also, as those occupied by the original feeling. The examples which he himself pro ceeds to give are almost all cases of imagination of move ment, in which the peripheral organs are indeed affected, for actual movements of a weak sort are found to accom pany the idea. This is what we should expect. All cur rents tend to run forward in the brain and discharge into the muscular system ; and the idea of a movement tends to do this with peculiar facility. But the question remains : Do currents run backward, so that if the optical centres (for example) are excited by ' association ' and a visual ob ject is imagined, a current runs down to the retina also, and excites that sympathetically with the higher tracts ? In other words, can peripheral sense-organs be excited from above, or only from without ? Are they excited in imagi nation ? Professor Bain's instances are almost silent as to this point. All he says is this : " We might think of a blow on the hand until the skin were actually irritated and inflamed. The attention very much directed to any part of the body, as the great toe, for instance, is apt to produce a distinct feeling in the part, which we account for only by supposing a revived nerve-current to flow there, making a sort of false sensation, an influ ence from within mimicking the influences from without in sensation proper. — (See the writings of Mr. Braid, of Manchester, on Hypnotism, etc.)" If I may judge from my own experience, all feelings of this sort are consecutive upon motor currents invading the skin and producing contraction of the muscles there, the muscles whose contraction gives ' goose-flesh ' when it takes place on an extensive scale. I never get a feeling in the; skin, however strongly I imagine it, until some actual change in the condition of the skin itself has occurred, j The truth seems to be that the cases where peripheral * Senses and Intellect, p. 338. 70 PSYCHOLOGY. sense-organs are directly excited in consequence of imagi nation are exceptional rarities, if they exist at all. In com mon cases of imagination it tvould seem more natural to suppose that the seat of the process is purely cerebral, and that the sense- organ is left out. Reasons for such a conclusion would be briefly these : 1) In imagination the starting-point of the process must be in the brain. Now we know that currents usually flow one way in the nervous system ; and for the peripheral sense- organs to be excited in these cases, the current would have to flow backward. 2) There is between imagined objects and felt objects a difference of conscious quality which may be called al most absolute. It is hardly possible to confound the live liest image of fancy with the weakest real sensation. The felt object has a plastic reality and outwardness which the imagined object wholly lacks. Moreover, as Fechner says? in imagination the attention feels as if drawn backwards to the brain ; in sensation (even of after-images) it is directed forward towards the sense-organ.* The difference between the two processes feels like one of kind, and not like a mere 'more ' or 'less ' of the same.f If a sensation of sound were only a strong imagination, and an imagination a weak sensation, there ought to be a border-line of experience where we never could tell whether we were hearing a weak sound or imagining a strong one. In comparing a present sensation felt with a past one imagined, it will be remem bered that we often judge the imagined one to have been ike stronger (see above, p. 500, note). This is inexplicable if the imagination be simply a weaker excitement of the sen sational process. To these reasons the following objections may be made : To 1) : The current demonstrably does flow backward * See above, Vol. II. p. 50, note. t V. Kandinsky (Kritische u. klinische Betrachtungen im Gebiete der Sinnestauschungen (Berlin, 1885), p. 135 if.) insists that in even the live liest pseudo-hallucinations (see below, Chapter XX), which may be re garded as the intensest possible results of the imaginative process, there Is no outward objectivity perceived in the thing represented, and that a garner Abgrund separates these ' ideas ' from true hallucination and objec tive perception. IMAGINATION. 71 down the optic nerve in Meyer's and Fere's negative after image. Therefore it can flow backward ; therefore it may flow backward in some, however slight, degree, in all imag ination.* To 2) : The difference alleged is not absolute, and sensa tion and imagination are hard to discriminate where the sensation is so weak as to be just perceptible. At m an ima£e Dwells for awhile before the TRye (see Vol. I. p. 243). Again, whenever the asso- - e processes are reduced and impeded by the approach ^ ^consciousness, as in falling asleep, or growing faint, or becoming narcotized, we find a concomitant increase in the intensity of whatever partial consciousness may survive. In some people what M. Maury has called ' hypnagogic ' hal lucinations * are the regular concomitant of the process of * Le Sommeil et les R6ves (1865), chaps, in, iv. THE PERCEPTION OF THINGS. 125 falling asleep. Trains of faces, landscapes, etc., pass before the mental eye, first as fancies, then as pseudo-hallucina tions, finally as full-fledged hallucinations forming dreams. If we regard association-paths as paths of drainage, then the shutting off of one after another of them as the encroaching cerebral paralysis advances ought to act like the plugging GA the hole in the bottom of the pail, and make the activity more intense in those systems of cells that retain any activity at all. The level rises because the currents are not drained away, until at last the full sensational explosion may occur. The usual explanation of hypnagogic hallucinations is that they are ideas deprived of their ordinary reductives. In somnolescence, sensations being extinct, the mind, it is said, then having no stronger things to compare its ideas with, ascribes to these the fulness of reality. At ordinary times the objects of our imagination are reduced to the status of subjective facts by the ever-present contrast of our sensa tions with them. Eliminate the sensations, however, this view supposes, and the ' images ' are forthwith ' projected ' into the outer world and appear as realities. Thus is the illusion of dreams also explained. This, indeed, after a fashion gives an account of the facts.* And yet it certainly fails to explain the extraordinary vivacity and completeness of so many of our dream-fantasms. The process of ' imagin ing ' must (in these cases at least f) be not merely relatively, but absolutely and in itself more intense than at other times. The fact is, it is not a process of imagining, but a genuine sensational process ; and the theory in quesfcp. is therefore false as far as that point is concerned. Dr. Hugblmgs Jackson's explanation of the tic seizure is acknowledged to be masterly. It ng, but i uesjjftp i it; inv^Hei This theory of incomplete rectification of the inner images by their usual reductives is most brilliantly stated by M. Taine in his work on Intelligence, book u. chap. i. f Not, of course, in all cases, because the cells remaining active are them selves on the way to be overpowered by the general (unknown) condition to which sleep is due. 126 PSYCHOLOGY. principles exactly like those which I am bringing forward here. The ' loss of consciousness ' in epilepsy is due to the most highly organized brain-processes being exhausted and thrown out of gear. The less organized (more instinc tive) processes, ordinarily inhibited by the others, are then exalted, so that we get as a mere consequence of relief from the inhibition, the meaningless or maniacal action which so often follows the attack. * Similarly the subsultus tendinorum or jerking of the muscles which so often startles us when we are on the point * For a full account of Jackson's theories, see his ' Croonian Lectures ' published in the Brit. Med. Journ. for 1884. Of. also his remarks in the Discussion of Dr. Mercier's paper on Inhibition in ' Brain,' xi. 361. The loss of vivacity in the images in the process of waking, as well as the gain of it in falling asleep, are both well described by M. Taine, who writes (on Intelligence, i. 50, 58) that often in the daytime, when fatigued and seated in a chair, it is sufficient for him to close one eye with a hand kerchief, when, " by degrees, the sight of the other eye becomes vague, and it closes. All external sensations are gradually effaced, or cease, at all events, to be remarked ; the internal images, on the other hand, feeble and rapid during the state of complete wakefulness, become intense, distinct, colored, steady, and lasting : there is a sort of ecstasy, accompanied by a feeling of expansion and of comfort. Warned by frequent experience, I know that sleep is coming on, and that I must not disturb the rising vision ; I remain passive, and in a few minutes it is complete. Architecture, landscapes, moving figures, pass slowly by, and sometimes remain, with incomparable clearness of form and fulness of being ; sleep comes on, and I know no more of the real world I am in. Many times, like M. Maury, I have caused myself to be gently roused at different moments of this state, and have thus been able to mark its characters. — The intense image which seems an external object is but a more forcible continuation of the feeble image which an instant before I recognized as internal ; some scrap of a forest, ^jke house, some person which I vaguely imagined on closing my eyes, hUro a minute become present to me with full bodily details, so as to change into a complete hallucination. Then, waking up on a hand touch ing me, I feel the figure decay, lose color, and evaporate ; what had ap peared a substance is reduced to a shadow. . . . In such a case, I have of ten seen, for a passing moment, the image grow pale, waste away, and evapo rate ; sometimes, on opening the eyes, a fragment of landscape or the skirt of a dress appears still to float over the fire-irons or on the black hearth." This persistence of dream-objects for a few moments after the eyes are opened seems to be no extremely rare experience. Many cases of it have been reported to me directly. Compare Mtiller's Physiology, Baly's tr., p 945. THE PERCEPTION OF THINGS. 127 of failing asleep, may be interpreted as due to the rise (in certain lower motor centres) of the ordinary < tonic ' tension to the explosion-point, when the inhibition commonly ex erted by the higher centres falls too suddenly away. One possible condition of hallucination then stands revealed, whatever other conditions there may be. When the normal paths of association between a centre and other centres are thrown out of gear, any activity ivhich may exist in the first centre tends to increase in intensity until finally the pwnt may be reached at which the last inward resistance is overcome, and the full sensational process explodes* Thus it will happen that causes of an amount of activity in brain-cells which would ordinarily result in a weak consciousness may pro duce a very strong consciousness when the overflow of these cells is stopped by the torpor of the rest of the brain. A slight peripheral irritation, then, if it reaches the centres of consciousness at all during sleep, will give rise to the dream of a violent sensation. All the books about dreaming are full of anecdotes which illustrate this. For example, M. Maury's nose and lips are tickled with a feather while he sleeps. He dreams he is being tortured by having a pitch- plaster applied to his face, torn off, lacerating the skin of nose and lips. Descartes, on being bitten by a flea, dreams of being run through by a sword. A friend tells me, as I write this, of his hair changing its position in his forehead just as he 'dozed off' in his chair a few days since. In stantly he dreamed that some one had struck him a blow. Examples can be quoted ad libitum, but these are enough, f * I say the ' normal ' paths, because hallucinations are not incompatible with some paths of association being left- Some hypnotic patients will not only have hallucinations of objects suggested to them, but will amplify them and act out the situation. But the paths here seem excessively nar row, and the reflections which ought to make the hallucination incredible dp not occur to the subject's miud. In general, the narrower a train of ' ideas ' is, the vivider the consciousness is of each. Under ordinary cir cumstances, the entire brain probably plays a part in draining any centre which may be ideationally active. When the drainage is reduced in any way it probably makes the active process more intense. f M. A. Maury gives a number: op. cit. pp. 136-8. PSYCHOLOGY. We seem herewith to have an explanation for a certain number of hallucinations. Whenever the normal fonvard irradiation of intra-cortical excitement through association-paths is checked, any accidental spontaneous activity or any peripheral stimulation (hoiuever inadequate at other times) by which a brain- centre may be visited, sets up a process of full sensational inten sity therein. In the hallucinations artificially produced in hypnotic subjects, some degree of peripheral excitement seems usu ally to be required. The brain is asleep as far as its own spontaneous thinking goes, and the words of the ' magneti- zer ' then awaken a cortical process which drafts off into itself any currents of a related sort which may come in from the periphery, resulting in a vivid objective percep tion of the suggested thing. Thus, point to a dot on a sheet of paper, and call it * General Grant's photograph,' and your subject will see a photograph of the General there instead of the dot. The dot gives objectivity to the appearance, and the suggested notion of the General gives it form. Then magnify the dot by a lens ; double it by a prism or by nudging the eyeball ; reflect it in a mirror ;, turn it upside down ; or wipe it out ; and the subject will tell you that the ' photograph ' has been enlarged, doubled, reflected, turned about, or made to disappear. In M. Binet's language, * the dot is the outward point de repere which is needed to give objectivity to your suggestion, and without which the latter will only produce a conception in the subject's mind.t M. Binet has shown that such a periphe- * M. Bluet's highly important experiments, which were first published in vol. xvii of the Revue Philosophique (1884), are also given in full in chapter ix of his and Fere's work on ' Animal Magnetism ' in the Inter national Scientific Series. Where there is no dot on the paper, nor any other visible mark, the subject's judgment about the ' portrait ' would seem to be guided by what he sees happening to the entire sheet. f It is a difficult thing to distinguish in a hypnotic patient between a genuine sensorial hallucination of something suggested and a conception of it merely, coupled with belief that it is there. I have been surprised at the vagueness with which such subjects will often trace upon blank paper the outlines of the pictures which they say they ' see ' thereupon. On the other THE PERCEPTION OF THINGS. ral point de repere is used in an enormous number, not only of hypnotic hallucinations, but of hallucinations of the insane. These latter are often unilateral ; that is, the patient hears the voices always on one side of him, or sees the, figure only when a certain one of his eyes is open. In many of these cases it has been distinctly proved that a morbid irritation in the internal ear, or an opacity in the humors of the eye, was the starting point of the current which the patient's diseased acoustic or optical centres clothed with their peculiar products in the way of ideas. Hallucinations produced in this way are 'ILLUSIONS '; and M. Binet' s theory, that all hallucinations must start in the periphery, may be called an attempt to reduce hallucination and illusion to one physiological type, the type, namely, to which normal per ception belongs, In every case, according to M. Binet, whether of perception, of hallucination, or of illusion, we get the sensational vividness by means of a current from the peripheral nerves. It may be a mere trace of a cur rent. But that trace is enough to kindle the maximal or supra-ideational process so that the object perceived will have the character of externality. What the nature of the object shall be will depend wholly on the particular sys tem of paths in which the process is kindled. Part of the thing in all cases comes from the sense-organ, the rest is furnished by the mind. But we cannot by introspection distinguish between these parts ; and our only formula for the result is that the brain has reacted on the impression in the normal way. Just so in the dreams which we have considered, and in the hallucinations of which M. Binet tells, we can only say that the brain has reacted in an abnor mal way. M. Binetfs theory accounts indeed for a multitude of cases, but certainly not for all. The prism does not always double hand, you will hear them say that they find no difference between a real flower which you show them and an imaginary flower which you tell them is beside it. When told that one is imaginary and that they must pick out the real one, they sometimes say the choice is Impossible, ai: 1 sometimes they point to the imaginary flower. 130 PSYCHOLOGY. the false appearance,* nor does the latter always disappear when the eyes are closed. Dr. Hack Tuke t gives several examples in sane people of well-exteriorized hallucinations which did not respond to Binet's tests ; and Mr. Edmund Gurney J gives a number of reasons why intensity in a cor tical process may be expected to result from local patho logical activity just as much as its peculiar nature does. For Binet, an abnormally or exclusively active part of the cortex gives the nature of what shall appear, whilst a pe ripheral sense-organ alone can give the intensity sufficient to make it appear projected into real space. But since this intensity is after all but a matter of degree, one does not see why, under rare conditions, the degree in question might not be attained by inner causes exclusively. In that case we should have certain hallucinations centrally initiated alongside of the peripherally initiated hallucinations, which are the only sort that M. Binet's theory allows. It seems probable on the whole, therefore, that centrally initiated hallu cinations can exist. How often they do exist is another ques tion. The existence of hallucinations which affect more than one sense is an argument for central initiation. For grant that the thing seen may have its starting point in the outer world, the voice which it is heard to utter must be due to an influence from the visual region, i.e. must be of central origin. Sporadic cases of hallucination, visiting people only once in a lifetime (which seem to be by far the most fre quent type), are on any theory hard to understand in detail. They are often extraordinarily complete ; and the fact that many of them are reported as veridical^ that is, as coincid ing with real events, such as accidents, deaths, etc., of the persons seen, is an additional complication of the phe nomenon. The first really scientific study of hallucination * Only the other day, in three hypnotized girls, I failed to double afi hallucination with a prism. Of course it may not have been a fully- developed hallucination. t Brain, xi. 441. iMind, x. 161, 316 ; and Phantasms of the Living (1886), I. 47(M88 THE PERCEPTION OF THINGS. 131 in all its possible bearings, on the basis of a large mass of empirical material, was begun by Mr. Edmund Gurney and is continued by other members of the Society for Psy chical Eesearch ; and the ' Census ' is now being applied to several countries under the auspices of the International Congress of Experimental Psychology. It is to be hoped that out of these combined labors something solid will eventually grow. The facts shade off into the phenomena of motor automatism, trance, etc.; and nothing but a wide comparative study can give really instructive results.* The part played by the peripheral sense-organ in hallucina tion is just as obscure as we found it in the case of imagina tion. The things seen often seem opaque and hide the background upon which they are projected. It does not follow from this, however, that the retina is actually in volved in the vision. A contrary process going on in the visual centres would prevent the retinal impression made by the outer realities from being felt, and this would in mental terms be equivalent to the hiding of them by the imaginary figure. The negative after-images of mental pictures reported by Meyer and Fere, and the negative after images of hypnotic hallucinations reported by Binet and others so far constitute the only evidence there is for the retina being involved. But until these after-images are explained in some other way we must admit the possibility of a centrifugal current from the optical centres downwards into the peripheral organ of sight, paradoxical as the course of such a current may appear. ' PEBCEPTION-TIME.' The, time which the perceptive process occupies has been inquired into by various experimenters. Some call it per ception-time, some choice-time, some discrimination-time. The results have been already given in Chapter XIII (voL I, p. 523 ff.), to which the reader is consequently referred * In Mr. Gurney's work, just cited, a very large number of veridical cases are critically discussed. PSYCHOLOGY. Dr. Bomanes gives an interesting variation of these time-measurements. He found * "an astonishing difference between different individuals with respect to the rate at which they are able to read. Of course reading implies enormously, intricate processes of perception both of the sensuous and of the intellectual order ; but if we choose for these observations per sons who have been accustomed to read much, we may consider that they are all very much on a par with respect to the amount of practice which they have had, so that the differences in their rates of reading may fairly be attributed to real differences in their rates of forming complex perceptions in rapid succession, and not to any merely acci dental differences arising from greater or less facility acquired by special practice. " My experiments consisted in marking a brief printed paragraph in a book which had never been read by any of the persons to whom it was to be presented. The paragraph, which contained simple state ments of simple facts, was marked on the margin with pencil. The book was then placed before the reader open, the page, however, being covered with a sheet of paper. Having pointed out to the reader upon this sheet of paper what part of the underlying page the marked para graph occupied, I suddenly removed the sheet of paper with one hand, while I started a chronograph with the other. Twenty seconds being allowed for reading the paragraph (ten lines octavo), as soon as the time was up I again suddenly placed the sheet of paper over the printed page, passed the book on to the next reader, and repeated the experi ment as before. Meanwhile, the first reader, the moment after the book had been removed, wrote down all that he or she could remember having read. And so on with all the other readers. 4 ' Now the results of a number of experiments conducted on this method were to show, as I have said, astonishing differences in the maximum rate of reading which is possible to different individuals, all of whom have been accustomed to extensive reading. That is to say, the difference may amount to 4 to 1 ; or, otherwise stated, in a given time one individual may be able to read four times as much as another. Moreover, it appeared that there was no relationship between slowness of reading and power of assimilation ; on the contrary, when all the efforts are directed to assimilating as much as possible in a given time, the rapid readers (as shown by their written notes) usually give a bet ter account of the portions of the paragraph which have been com passed by the slow readers than the latter are able to give ; and the most rapid reader 1 have found is also the best at assimilating. I should further say that there is no relationship between rapidity of perception as thus tested and intellectual activity as tested by the gen eral results of intellectual work ; for I have tried the experiment witb Mental Evolution in Animals, p. 136. THE PERCEPTION OF THINGS. 133 several highly distinguished men in science and literature, most of whom I found to be slow readers."* * Literature. The best treatment of perception with which I am ac quainted is that in Mr. James Sully's book on ' Illusions ' in the Interna tional Scientific Series. On hallucinations the literature is large. Gurney, Kandinsky (as already cited), and some articles by Kraepelin in the Vierteljahrschrift fur Wissenschaftliche Philosophic, vol. v (1881), are the most systematic studies recently made. All works on Insanity treat of them. Dr. W. W. Ireland's works, ' The Blot upon the Brain ' (1886) and ' Through the Ivory Gate ' (1890) have much information on the subject. Gurney gives pretty complete references to older literature. The most important thing on the subject from the point of view of theory is the article by Mr. Myers on the Demon of Socrates in the Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research for 1889, p. 522. CHAPTEK XX. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE.* THE FEELING OF CRUDE EXTENSITY. IN the sensations of hearing, touch, sight, and pain we are accustomed to distinguish from among the other elements the element of voluminousness. We call the reverberations of a thunderstorm more voluminous than the squeaking of a slate-pencil ; the entrance into a warm bath gives our skin a more massive feeling than the prick of a pin ; a little neuralgic pain, fine as a cobweb, in the face, seems less ex tensive than the heavy soreness of a boil or the vast discom fort of a colic or a lumbago ; and a solitary star looks smaller than the noonday sky. In the sensation of dizziness or subjective motion, which recent investigation has proved to be connected with stimulation of the semi-circular canals of the ear, the spatial character is very prominent. Whether the * muscular sense ' directly yields us knowledge of space is still a matter of litigation among psychologists. Whilst some go so far as to ascribe our entire cognition of exten sion to its exclusive aid, others deny to it all extensive quality whatever. Under these circumstances we shall do better to adjourn its consideration ; admitting, however, that it seems at first sight as if we felt something decidedly more voluminous when we contract our thigh-muscles than when we twitch an eyelid or some small muscle in the face. It seems, moreover, as if this difference lay in the feeling of the thigh-muscles themselves. In the sensations of smell and taste this element of varying vastness seems less" prominent but not altogether absent. Some tastes and smells appear less extensive than complex flavors, like that of roast meat or plum pudding, on the one hand, or heavy odors like musk or tuberose, on * Reprinted, with considerable revision, from ' Mind ' for 1887. 134 THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 135 the other. The epithet sharp given to the acid class would seem to show that to the popular mind there is something narrow and, as it were, streaky, in the impression they make, other flavors and odors being bigger and rounder. The sensations derived from the inward organs are also distinctly more or less voluminous. Eepletion and empti ness, suffocation, palpitation, headache, are examples of this, and certainly not less spatial is the consciousness we have of our general bodily condition in nausea, fever, heavy drowsiness, and fatigue. Our entire cubic content seems then sensibly manifest to us as such, and feels much larger than any local pulsation, pressure, or discomfort. Skin and retina are, however, the organs in which the space- element plays the most active part. Not only does the maximal vastness yielded by the retina surpass that yielded by any other organ, but the intricacy with which our atten tion can subdivide this vastness and perceive it to be com posed of lesser portions simultaneously coexisting along side of each other is without a parallel elsewhere.* The ear gives a greater vastness than the skin, but is consider ably less able to subdivide it.f Noiv my first thesis is that this element, discernible in each and every sensation, though more developed in some than in others, is the original sensation of space, out of which all the exact knowledge about space that we afterwards come to have is woven by processes of discrimination, association, and selection. ' Extensity,' as Mr. James Ward calls it,J * Prof. Jastrow has found that invariably we tend to underestimate the amount of our skin which may be stimulated by contact with an object when we express it in terms of visual space; that is, when asked to mark on paper the extent of skin alfected, we always draw it much too small. This shows that the eye gets as much space-feeling from the smaller line as the skin gets from the larger one. Of. Jastrow : Mind, xi. 546-7; Ameri can Journal of Psychology, in. 53. f Amongst sounds the graver ones seem the most extensive. Stumpf gives three reasons for this : 1) association with bigger causes; 2) wider reverberation of the hand and body when grave notes are sung; 3) audi bility at a greater distance. He thinks that these three reasons dispense us from supposing an immanent extensity in the 'sensation of sound as such. See his remarks in the Tonpsychologie, i. 207-211. \ Encyclopaedia Britannica, 9th Edition, article Psychology, pp. 46, 53. 136 PSYCHOLOGY. on this view, becomes an element in each sensation just as intensity is. The latter every one will admit to be a dis tinguishable though not separable ingredient of the sensible quality. In like manner extensity, being an entirely pecul iar kind of feeling indescribable except in terms of itself, and inseparable in actual experience from some sensational quality which it must accompany, can itself receive no other name than that of sensational element. It must now be noted that the vastness hitherto spoken of is as great in one direction as in another. Its dimensions are so vague that in it there is no question as yet of surface as opposed to depth ; ' volume ' being the best short name for the sensation in question. Sensations of different orders are roughly comparable, inter se, with respect to their volumes. This shows that the spatial quality in each is identical wherever found, for different qualitative elements, e.g. warmth and odor, are incommensurate. Persons born blind are reported surprised at the largeness with which objects appear to them when their sight is restored. Franz says of his patient cured of cataract : "He saw everything much larger than he had supposed from the idea obtained by his sense of touch. Moving, and especially living, objects appeared very large." * Loud sounds have a cer tain enormousness of feeling. It is impossible to conceive of the explosion of a cannon as filling a small space. In general, sounds seem to occupy all the room between us and their source ; and in the case of certain ones, the cricket's song, the whistling of the wind, the roaring of the surf, or a distant railway train, to have no definite start ing point. In the sphere of vision we have facts of the same order. 'Glowing' bodies, as Hering says, give us a perception "which seems roomy (raumhaft) in comparison with that of strictly surface color. A glowing iron looks luminous through and through, and so does a flame." t A luminous fog, a band of sunshine, affect us in the same way. As Hering urges : * Philosophical Transactions (1841). f Hermann's Handb d. Physiol., Bd. in. 1, S 575. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 137 " We must distinguish roomy from superficial, as well as distinctly from indistinctly bounded, sensations. The dark which with closed eyes one sees before one is, for example, a roomy sensation. We do not see a black surface like a wall in front of us, but a space filled with dark ness, and even when we succeed in seeing this darkness as terminated by a black wall there still remains in front of this wall the dark space. The same thing happens when we find ourselves with open eyes in an absolutely dark room. This sensation of darkness is also vaguely bounded. An example of a distinctly bounded roomy sensation is that of a clear and colored fluid seen in a glass ; the yellow of the wine is seen not only on the bounding surface of the glass ; the yellow sensa tion fills the whole interior of the 'glass. By day the so-called empty space between us and objects seen appears very different from what it is by night. The increasing darkness settles not only upon the things but also between us and the things, so as at last to cover them com pletely and fill the space alone. If I look into a dark box I find it filled with darkness, and this is seen not merely as the dark-colored sides or walls of the box. A shady corner in an otherwise well-lighted room is full of a darkness which is not only on the walls and floor but between them in the space they include. Every sensation is there where I ex perience it, and if I have it at once at every point of a certain roomy space, it is then a voluminous sensation. A cube of transparent green glass gives us a spatial sensation ; an opaque cube painted green, on the contrary, only sensations of surfa.ce." * There are certain quasi-motor sensations in the head when we change the direction of the attention, which equally seem to involve three dimensions. If with closed eyes we think of the top of the house and then of the cellar, of the distance in front of us and then of that behind us, of space far to the right and then far to the left, we have something far stronger than an idea, — an actual feeling, namely, as if something in the head moved into another direction. Fechner was, I believe, the first to publish any remarks on these feelings. He writes as follows : " When we transfer the attention from objects of one sense to those of another we have an indescribable feeling (though at the same time one perfectly determinate and reproducible at pleasure) of altered direc tion, or differently localized tension (Spannung). We feel a strain for ward in the eyes, one directed sideways in the ears, increasing with the degree of our attention, and changing according as we look at an object carefully, or listen to something attentively ; wherefore we speak of straining the attention. The difference is most plainly felt when * Loc. cit. S. 572. 138 PSYCHOLOGY. the attention vibrates rapidly between eye and ear. This feeling local- izes itself with most decided difference in regard to the various sense- organs according as we wish to discriminate a thing delicately by touch, taste, or smell. * ' But now I have, when I try to vividly recall a picture of memory or fancy, a feeling perfectly analogous to that which I experience when I seek to grasp a thing keenly by eye or ear ; and this analogous feeling is very differently localized. While in sharpest possible attention to real objects (as well as to after-images) the strain is plainly forwards, and, when the attention changes from one sense to another, only alters its direction between the sense-organs, leaving the rest of the head free from strain, the case is different in memory or fancy ; for here the feel ing withdraws entirely from the external sense-organs, and seems rather to take refuge in that part of the head which the brain fills. If I wish, for example, to recall a place or person, it will arise before me with vividness, not according as I strain my attention forwards, but rather in proportion as I, so to speak, retract it backwards. " * It appears probable that the feelings which Fechner de scribes are in part constituted by imaginary semi-circular canal sensations. t These undoubtedly convey the most delicate perception of change in direction ; and when, as here, the changes are not perceived as taking place in the external world, they occupy a vague internal space located within the head.J * Elemente der Psychophysik, n. 475-6. f See Foster's Text-book of Physiology, bk. m. c. vr. § 2. j Fechner, who was ignorant of the but lately discovered function of the semi-circular canals, gives a different explanation of the organic seat of these feelings. They are probably highly composite. -With me, actual move ments in the eyes play a considerable part in them, though I am hardly con scious of the peculiar feelings in the scalp which Fechner goes on to de scribe thus : ' ' The feeling of strained attention in the different sense-organs seems to be only a muscular one produced in using these various organs by setting in motion, by a sort of reflex action, the set of muscles which belong to them. One can ask, then, with what particular muscular con traction the sense of strained attention in the effort to recall something is associated ? On this question my own feeling gives me a decided answer ; it comes to me distinctly not as a sensation of tension in the inside of the head, but as a feeling of strain and contraction in the scalp, with a pressure from outwards in over the whole cranium, undoubtedly caused by a con traction of the muscles of the scalp. This harmonizes very well with the expressions, sich den Kopf zerbrecTien, den Kopf zusammenneJimen. In a former illness, when I could not endure the slightest effort after continuous thought, and had no theoretical bias on this question, the muscles of the scalp, especially those of the back-head, assumed a fairly morbid degree of sensibility whenever I tried to think." (Elem. der Psychophysik, 11. 490-91.) THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 139 In the skin itself there is a vague form of projection into the third dimension to which Bering has called atten tion. * ' Heat is not felt only against the cutaneous surface, but when com municated through the air may appear extending more or less out from the surface into the third dimension of surrounding space. . . . We can determine in the dark the place of a radiant body by moving the hand to and fro, and attending to the fluctuation of our feeling of warmth. The feeling itself, however, is not projected fully into the spot at which we localize the hot body, but always remains in the neighborhood of the hand." The interior of one's mouth-cavity feels larger when ex plored by the tongue than when looked at. The crater of a newly-extracted tooth, and the movements of a loose tooth in its socket, feel quite monstrous. A midge buzzing against the drum of the ear will often seem as big as a but terfly. The spatial sensibility of the tympanic membrane has hitherto been very little studied, though the subject will well repay much trouble. If we approach it by intro ducing into the outer ear some small object like the tip of a rolled-up tissue-paper lamplighter, we are surprised at the large radiating sensation which its presence gives us, and at the sense of clearness and openness which comes when it is removed. It is immaterial to inquire whether the far-reaching sensation here be due to actual irradiation upon distant nerves or not. We are considering now, not the objective causes of the spatial feeling, but its subjective varieties, and the experiment shows that the same object gives more of it to the inner than to the outer cuticle of the ear. The pressure of the air in the tympanic cavity upon the membrane gives an astonishingly large sensation. We can increase the pressure by holding our nostrils and closing our mouth and forcing air through our Eustachian tubes by an expiratory effort ; and we can diminish it by either inspiring or swallowing under the same conditions of closed mouth and nose. In either case we get a large round tridimensional sensation inside of the head, which seems as if it must come from the affection of an organ much larger than the tympanic membrane, whose surface hardly exceeds that of one's little-finger-nail. 140 PSYCHOLOGY. The tympanic membrane is furthermore able to render sensible differences in the pressure of the external atmos phere, too slight to be felt either as noise or in this more violent way. If the reader will sit with closed eyes and let a friend approximate some solid object, like a large book, noiselessly to his face, he will immediately become aware of the object's presence and position — likewise of its de parture. -A friend of the writer, making the experiment for the first time, discriminated unhesitatingly between the three degrees of solidity of a board, a lattice-frame, and a sieve, held close to his ear. Now as this sensation is never used by ordinary persons as a means of perception, we may fairly assume that its felt quality, in those whose attention is called to it for the first time, belongs to it qua sensation, and owes nothing to educational suggestions. But this felt quality is most distinctly and unmistakably one of vague spatial vastness in three dimensions — quite as much so as is the felt quality of the retinal sensation when we lie on our back and fill the entire field of vision with the empty blue sky. When an object is brought near the ear we im mediately feel shut in, contracted ; when the object is removed, we suddenly feel as if a transparency, clearness, openness, had been made outside of us. And the feeling will, by any one who will take the pains to observe it, be acknowledged to involve the third dimension in a vague, unmeasured state.* The reader will have noticed, in this enumeration of facts, that voluminousness of the feeling seems to bear very little relation to the size of the organ that yields it The ear and eye are comparatively minute organs, yet they give us feel ings of great volume. The same lack of exact proportion between size of feeling and size of organ affected obtains within the limits of particular sensory organs. An object appears smaller on the lateral portions of the retina than it does on the fovea, as may be easily verified by holding the * That the sensation in question is one of tactile rather than of acoustic sensibility would seem proved by the fact that a medical friend of the writer, both of whose membrana tympani are quite normal, but one of whose ears is almost totally deaf, feels the presence and withdrawal of ob jects as well at one ear as at the other. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 141 two forefingers parallel and a couple of inches apart, and transferring the gaze of one eye from one to the other. Then the finger not directly looked at will appear to shrink, and this whatever be the direction of the fingers. On the tongue a crumb, or the calibre of a small tube, appears larger than between the fingers. If two points kept equi distant (blunted compass- or scissors-points, for example) be drawn across the skin so as really to describe a pair of parallel lines, the lines will appear farther apart in some spots than in others. If, for example, we draw them hori zontally across the face, so that the mouth falls between them, the person experimented upon will feel as if they began to diverge near the mouth and to include it in a well- marked ellipse. In like manner, if we keep the compass- Fio. 51 (after Weber). points one or two centimetres apart, and draw them down the forearm over the wrist and palm, finally drawing one along one finger, the other along its neighbor, the appear ance will be that of a single line, soon breaking into two, which become more widely separated below the wrist, to contract again in the palm, and finally diverge rapidly again towards the finger-tips. The dotted lines in Figs. 51 and 52 represent the true path of the compass-points ; the full lines their apparent path. The same length of skin, moreover, will convey a more extensive sensation according to the manner of stimulation. If the edge of a card be pressed against the skin, the dis tance between its extremities will seem shorter than that be tween two compass-tips touching the same terminal points.* * The skin seems to obey a different law from the eye here. If a given retinal tract be excited, first by a series of points, and next by the two 142 PSYCHOLOGY. In the eye, intensity of nerve-stimulation seems to in crease the volume of the feeling as well as its brilliancy. If we raise and lower the gas alternately, the whole room and all the objects in it seem alternately to enlarge and contract. If we cover half a page of small print with a gray glass, the print seen through the glass appears decidedly smaller than that seen outside of it, and the darker the glass the greater the difference. When a circumscribed opacity in front of the retina keeps off part of the light from the portion which it covers, objects projected on that portion may seem but half as large as when their image falls outside of it.* The inverse effect seems produced by certain drugs and anaesthetics. Mor phine, atropine, daturine, and cold blunt the sensibility of the skin, so that dis tances upon it seem less. Haschish pro duces strange perversions of the general sensibility. Under its influence one's body may seem either enormously en larged or strangely contracted. Some times a single member will alter its proportion to the rest ; or one's back, for instance, will appear entirely absent, as if one were hollow behind. Objects comparatively near will recede to a vast distance, a short street assume to the eye an immeasurable perspective. Ether and chloroform b c a> FIG. 52 (after Weber). extreme points, with the interval between themun excited, this interval will seein considerably less in the second case than it seemed in the first. In the skin the unexcited interval feels the larger. The reader may easily verify the facts in this case by taking a visiting-card, cutting one edge of it into a saw-tooth pattern, and from the opposite edge cutting out all but the two corners, and then comparing the feelings aroused by the two edges when held against the skin. * Classen, Physiologic des Gesichtssinnes, p. 114 ; see also A. Riehl, Der Philosophische Kriticismus, 11. p. 149. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. occasionally produce not wholly dissimilar results. Panum, the German physiologist, relates that when, as a boy, he was etherized for neuralgia, the objects in the room grew extremely small and distant, before his field of vision dark ened over and the roaring in his ears began. He also men tions that a friend of his in church, struggling in vain to keep awake, saw the preacher grow smaller and smaller and more and more distant. I myself on one occasion observed the same recession of objects during the begin ning of chloroformization. In various cerebral diseases we find analogous disturbances. Can ive assign the physiological conditions which make the elementary sensible largeness of one sensation vary so much from that of another ? Only imperfectly. One factor in the re sult undoubtedly is the number of nerve-terminations simultaneously excited by the outward agent that awakens the sensation. When many skin-nerves are warmed, or much retinal surface illuminated, our feeling is larger than when a lesser nervous surface is excited. The single sen sation yielded by two compass-points, although it seems simple, is yet felt to be much bigger and blunter than that yielded by one. The touch of a single point may always be recognized by its quality of sharpness. This page looks much smaller to the reader if he closes one eye than if both eyes are open. So does the moon, which latter fact shows I that the phenomenon has nothing to do with parallax.} The celebrated boy couched for the cataract by Cheselden thought, after his first eye was operated, " all things he saw extremely large," but being couched of his second eye, said " that objects at first appeared large to this eye, but not so large as they did at first to the other ; and looking upon the same object with both eyes, he thought it looked about twice as large as with the first couched eye only, but not double, that we can anyways discover." The greater extensiveness that the feeling of certain parts of the same surface has over other parts, and that one order of surface has over another (retina over skin, for example), may also to a certain extent be explained by the operation of the same factor. It is an anatomical fact that the most spatially sensitive surfaces (retina, tongue, finger- 144 PSYCHOLOGY. tips, etc.) are supplied by nerve-trunks of unusual thick ness, which must supply to every unit of surface-area an unusually large number of terminal fibres. But the varia tions of felt extension obey probably only a very rough law of numerical proportion to the number of fibres. A sound is not twice as voluminous to two ears as to one ; and the above-cited variations of feeling, when the same surface is excited under different conditions, show that the feeling is. a resultant of several factors of which the anatomical one is only the principal. Many ingenious hypotheses have been brought forward to assign the co-operating factors where different conditions give conflicting amounts of felt space. Later we shall analyze some of these cases in de tail, but it must be confessed here in advance that many of them resist analysis altogether. * * It is worth while at this point to call attention with some emphasis to the fact that, though the anatomical condition of the feeling resembles the feeling itself, such resemblance cannot be taken by our understanding to explain why the feeling should be just what it is. We hear it untiringly reiterated by materialists and spiritualists alike that we can see no possible inward reason why a certain brain-process should produce the feeling of redness and another of anger : the one process is no more red than the other is angry, and the coupling of process and feeling is, as far as our understanding goes, a juxtaposition pure and simple. But in the matter of spatial feeling, where the retinal patch that produces a triangle in the mind is itself a triangle, etc., it looks at first sight as if the sensation might be a direct cognition of its own neural condition. Were this true, however, our sensation should be one of multitude rather than of continuous extent ; for the condition is number of optical nerve-termini, and even this is only a remote condition and not an immediate condition. The immediate condi tion of the feeling is not the process in the retina, but the process in the brain; and the process in the brain may, for aught we know, be as unlike a triangle, — nay, it probably is so, — as it is unlike redness or rage. It is simply a coincidence that in the case of space one of the organic conditions, viz. , the triangle impressed on the skin or the retina, should lead to a rep resentation in the mind of the subject observed similar to that which it produces in the psychological observer. In no other kind of case is the coincidence found. Even should we admit that we cognize triangles in space because of our immediate cognition of the triangular shape of our excited group of nerve-tips, the matter would hardly be more transparent, for the mystery would still remain, why are we so much better cognizant of triangles on our finger-tips than on the nerve-tips of our back, on our eye than on our ear, and on any of these parts than in our brain ? Thos. Brown very rightly rejects the notion of explaining the shape of the space perceived by the shape of the 'nervous expansion affected.' "If this THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 145 THE FEBCEPTION OF SPATIAL OKDEK. So far, all we have established or sought to establish is the existence of the vague form or quote of spatiality as an inseparable element bound up with the other peculiarities of each and every one of our sensations. The numerous examples we have adduced of the variations of this extensive element have only been meant to make clear its strictly sensational character. In very few of them will the reader have been able to explain the variation by an added intel lectual element, such as the suggestion of a recollected ex perience. In almost all it has seemed to be the immediate psychic effect of a peculiar sort of nerve-process excited ; and all the nerve-processes in question agree in yielding what space they do yield, to the mind, in the shape of a simple total vastness, in which, primitively at least, no order of parts or of subdivisions reigns. Let no one be surprised at this notion of a space without order. There may be a space without order just as there may be an order without space.* And the primitive percep tions of space are certainly of an unordered kind. The order which the spaces first perceived potentially include must, before being distinctly apprehended by the mind, be woven into those spaces by a rather complicated set of in tellectual acts. The primordial largenesses which the sen sations yield must be measured and subdivided by conscious ness, and added together, before they can form by theii synthesis what we know as the real Space of the objective] world. In these operations, imagination, association, at tention, and selection play a decisive part ; and although they nowhere add any new material to the space-data of sense, they so shuffle and manipulate these data and hide alone were necessary, we should have square inches and half inches, and various other forms, rectilinear and curvilinear, of fragance and sound." (Lectures, xxn.) * Musical tones, e.g., have an order of quality independent either off their space- or time-order. Music comes from the time-order of the notes upsetting their quality- order. In general, if a b c d efg h ij k, etc., stand for an arrangement of feelings in the order of their quality, they may as sume any space-order or time-order, as def a hg, etc., and still the order of quality will remain fixed and unchanged. 146 PSYCHOLOGY. present ones behind imagined ones that it is no wonder if some authors have gone so far as to think that the sense- data have no spatial worth at all, and that the intellect, since it makes the subdivisions, also gives the spatial quality to them out of resources of its own. As for ourselves, having found that all our sensations (however as yet unconnected and undiscriminated) are oi{ extensive objects, our next problem is : How do we ARRANGE these at first chaotically given spaces into the one regular and^ orderly ' world of space ' which we now know ? To begin with, there is no reason to suppose that the several sense-spaces of which a sentient creature may become conscious, each filled with its own peculiar content, should tend, simply because they are many, to enter into any definite spatial intercourse with each other, or lie in any particular order of positions. Even in ourselves we can recognize this. Different feelings may coexist in us without assuming any particular spatial order. The sound of the brook near which I write, the odor of the cedars, the comfort with which my breakfast has filled me, and my in terest in this paragraph, all lie distinct in my consciousness, but in no sense outside or alongside of each other. Their spaces are interfused and at most fill the same vaguely ob jective world. Even where the qualities are far less dis parate, we may have something similar. If we take our subjective and corporeal sensations alone, there are moments when, as we lie or sit motionless, we find it very difficult to feel distinctly the length of our back or the direction of our feet from our shoulders. By a strong effort we can succeed in dispersing our attention impartially over our whole per son, and then we feel the real shape of our body in a sort of unitary way. But in general a few parts are strongly emphasized to consciousness and the rest sink out of notice ; and it is then remarkable how vague and ambiguous our perception of their relative order of location is. Obviously, for the orderly arrangement of a multitude of sense-spaces in consciousness, something more than their mere separate existence is required. What is this further condition ? If a number of sensible extents are to be perceived alongside THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 147 of each other and in definite order they must appear as parts in a vaster sensible extent which can enter the mind simply and all at once. I think it will be seen that the difficulty of esti-' mating correctly the form of one's body by pure feeling > arises from the fact that it is very hard to feel its totality as ., a unit at all. The trouble is similar to that of thinking for wards and backwards simultaneously. When conscious of our head we tend to grow unconscious of our feet, and there enters thus an element of time-succession into our percep tion of ourselves which transforms the latter from an act of intuition to one of construction. This element of con- structiveness is present in a still higher degree, and carries with it the same consequences, when we deal with objective spaces too great to be grasped by a single look. The rela tive positions of the shops in a town, separated by many tortuous streets, have to be thus constructed from data ap prehended in succession, and the result is a greater or less degree of vagueness. That a sensation be discriminated as a part from out of ail larger enveloping space is then the conditio sine qua non of itsn being apprehended in a definite spatial order. The problem of ordering our feelings in space is then, in the first instance, a problem of discrimination, but not of discrimination pure and simple ; for then not only coexistent sights but coex istent sounds would necessarily assume such order, which they notoriously do not. Whatever is discriminated will appear as a small space within a larger space, it is true, but this is but the very rudiment of order. For the location of it within that space to become precise, other conditions still must supervene ; and the best way to study what they are will be to pause for a little and analyze what the expression 'spatial order* means. Spatial order is an abstract term. The concrete percep tions which it covers are figures, directions, positions, mag nitudes, and distances. To single out any one of these things from a total vastness is partially to introduce order into the vastness. To subdivide the vastness into a multi tude of these things is to apprehend it in a completely orderly way. Now what are these things severally ? To 148 PSYCHOLOGY. begin with, no one can for an instant hesitate to say that some of them are qualities of sensation, just as the total vastness is in which they lie. Take figure : a square, a circle, and a triangle appear in the first instance to the eye simply as three different kinds of impressions, each so pecul iar that we should recognize it if it were to return. When Nunnely's patient had his cataracts removed, and a cube and a sphere were presented to his notice, he could at once perceive a difference in their shapes ; and though he could not say which was the cube and which the sphere, he saw they were not of the same figure. So of lines : if we can notice lines at all in our field of vision, it is inconceivable that a vertical one should not affect us differently from an horizontal one, and should not be recognized as affecting us similarly when presented again, although we might not yet know the name * vertical,' or any of its connotations, beyond this peculiar affection of our sensibility. So of angles : an obtuse one affects our feeling immediately in a different way from an acute one. Distance-apart, too, is a tion — the sensation of a line joining the two distant points : lengthen the line, you alter the feeling and with it the distance felt. Space-relations. But with distance and direction we pass to the category of ^pace-relations , and are immediately confronted by an opinion which makes of all relations something toto ccdo different from all facts of feeling or imagination whatsoever. A relation, for the Platonizing school in psychology, is an energy of pure thought, and, as such, is quite incommen surable with the data of sensibility between which it may be perceived to obtain. We may consequently imagine a disciple of this school to say to us at this point : " Suppose you have made a sep arate specific sensation of each line and each angle, what boots it? You have still the order of directions and of distances to account for ; you have still the relative magni tudes ot all these felt figures to state ; you h»ve their re spective positions to define before you can be said to have brought order into your space. And not one of these de- THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 149 terminations can be effected except through an act of re lating thought, so that your attempt to give an account of space in terms of pure sensibility breaks down almost at the very outset. Position, for example, can never be a sen sation, for it has nothing intrinsic about it ; it can only obtain between a spot, line, or other figure and extraneous co-ordinates, and can never be an element of the sensible datum, the line or the spot, in itself. Let us then confess that Thought alone can unlock the riddle of space, and that Thought is an adorable but unfathomable mystery." Such a method of dealing with the problem has the merit of shortness. Let us, however, be in no such hurry, but see whether we cannot get a little deeper by patiently considering what these space-relations are. 'Eelation' is a very slippery word. It has so many different concrete meanings that the use of it as an abstract universal may easily introduce bewilderment into our thought. We must therefore be careful to avoid ambiguity by making sure, wherever we have to employ it, what its precise meaning is in that particular sphere of application. At present we have to do with space-relations, and no others. Most ' relations ' are feelings of an entirely different order from the terms they relate. The relation of similarity, e.g., may equally obtain between jasmine and tuberose, or be tween Mr. Browning's verses and Mr. Story's ; it is itself neither odorous nor poetical, and those may well be pardoned who have denied to it all sensational content whatever. But just as, in the field of quantity, the relation between two numbers is another number, so in the field of space the relations are facts of the same order with the facts they relate. If these latter be patches in the circle of vision, the former are certain other patches between them. When we speak of the relation of direction of two points toward each other, we mean simply the sensation of the line that joins the two points together. The line is the relation; feel it and you feel the relation, see it and you see the relation ; nor can you in any conceivable way think the latter except by im agining the former (however vaguely), or describe or indi cate the one except by pointing to the other. And the moment you have imagined the line, the relation stands 150 PSYCHOLOGY. before you in all its completeness, with nothing further to be done. Just so the relation of direction between two lines is identical with the peculiar sensation of shape of the space enclosed between them. This is commonly called an angular relation. If these relations are sensations, no less so are the rela tions of position. The relation of position between the top and bottom points of a vertical line is that line, and nothing else. The relations of position between a point and a horizontal line below it are potentially numerous. There is one more important than the rest, called its distance. This is the sensation, ideal or actual, of a perpendicular drawn from the point to the line.* Two lines, one from each extremity of the horizontal to the point, give us a peculiar sensation of triangularity. This feeling may be said to constitute the locus of all the relations of position of the elements in ques tion, tightness and leftness, upness and downness, are again pure sensations differing specifically from each other, and generically from everything else. Like all sensations, they can only be indicated, not described. If we take a cube and label one side top, another bottom, a third front, and a fourth back, there remains no form of words by which we can de scribe to another person which of the remaining sides is right and which left. We can only point and say here is right and there is left, just as we should say this is red and that blue. Of two points seen beside each other at all, one isjj always affected by one of these feelings, and the other by| the opposite ; the same is true of the extremities of anyl line.t * The whole science of geometry may be said to owe its being to the exorbitant interest which the human mind takes in lines. We cut space up in every direction in order to manufacture them. f Kant was, I believe, the first to call attention to this last order of facts. After pointing out that two opposite spherical triangles, two gloves of a pair, two spirals wound in contrary directions, have identical inward de terminations, that is, have their parts defined with relation to each other by the same law, and so must be conceived as identical, he showed that the im possibility of their mutual superposition obliges us to assign to each figure of a symmetrical pair a peculiar difference of its own which can only con sist in an outward determination or relation of its parts, no^longer to each other, but to the whole of an objectively outlying space with its points of the compass given absolutely. This inconceivable difference is perceived only THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 151 Thus it appears indubitable that all space-relations ex cept those of magnitude are nothing more or less than pure sensational objects. But magnitude appears to outstep this narrow sphere. We have relations of muchness and little- . /id* ness between times, numbers, intensities, and qualities," as well as spaces. It is impossible, then, that such relations should form a particular kind of simply spatial feeling. This we must admit : the relation of quantity is generic and occurs in many categories of consciousness, whilst the other relations we have considered are specific and occur in space alone. "When our attention passes from a shorter line to a longer, from a smaller spot to a larger, from a feebler light to a stronger, from a paler blue to a richer, from a march tune to a galop, the transition is accompanied in the synthetic field of consciousness by a peculiar feeling of difference which is what we call the sensation of more, — more length, more expanse, more light, more blue, more motion. This transitional sensation of more must be iden tical with itself under all these different accompaniments, or we should not give it the same name in every case. We get it when we pass from a short vertical line to a long horizontal one, from a small square to a large circle, as well as when we pass between those figures whose shapes are congruous. But when the shapes are congruous our consciousness Q| the relation is a good deal more distinct, and it is most distiact of all when, in the exercise of our analytic attention, we notice, first, a part, and then the whole, of a single line or shape. Then the more of the whole actually sticks out, as a separate piece of space, and is so envisaged. The same exact sensation of it is given when we are able to superpose one line or figure on another. This indispensable condition of exact measurement of the more has led some to think that the feeling itself arose in every case from original experiences of superposition. This is ''through the relation to right and left, which is a matter of immediate intuition." In these last words (welcfos unmittelbar auf Anschauung geht — Prolegomena, § 12) Kant expresses all that we have meant by speaking of up and down, right and left, as sensations. He is wrong, however, in invoking relation to extrinsic total space as essential to the existence of these contrasts in figures. Relation to our own body is enough. 152 PSYCHOLOGY. probably not aii absolutely true opinion, but for our pres ent purpose that is immaterial. So far as the subdivisions of a sense-space are to be measured exactly against each other, objective forms occupying one subdivision must directly or indirectly be superposed upon the other, and the mind must get the immediate feeling of an outstanding plus. And even where we only feel one subdivision to be vaguely larger or less, the mind must pass rapidly between it and the other subdivision, and receive the immediate sen sible shock of the more. We seem thus to have accounted for all space-relations, and made them clear to our understanding. They are nothing but sensations of particular lines .particular angles, particular forms of transition, or (in the case of a distinct more) of particular outstanding portions of space after two figures have been super posed. These relation-sensations may actually be produced as such, as when a geometer draws new lines across a figure with his pencil to demonstrate the relations of its parts, or they may be ideal representations of lines, not really drawn. But in either case their entrance into the mind is equivalent to a more detailed subdivision, cognizance, and measurement of the space considered. The bringing of sub- divisions to consciousness constitutes, then, the entire process by which we pass from our first vague feeling of a total vastness to a cognition of the vastness in detail. The more numerous the subdivisions are, the more elaborate and per fect the cognition becomes. But inasmuch as all the sub divisions are themselves sensations, and even the feeling of ' more ' or ' less ' is, where not itself a figure, at least a sensation of transition between two sensations of figure, it follows, for aught we can as yet see to the contrary, that all spatial knowledge is sensational at bottom, and that, as the sensations lie together in the unity of consciousness, no new material element whatever comes to them from a supra-sensible source.* * In the eyes of many it will have seemed strange to call a relation a mere line, and a line a mere sensation. We may easily learn a great deal about any relation, say that between two points: we may divide the line which joins these, and distinguish it, and classify it, and find out its rela- THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 153 The bringing of subdivisions to consciousness ! This, then, is our next topic. They may be brought to consciousness under three aspects in respect of their locality, in respect of their size, in respect of their shape. The Meaning of Localization. Confining ourselves to the problem of locality for the pres ent, let us begin with the simple case of a sensitive surface, only two points of which receive stimulation from without. How, first, are these two points felt as alongside of each other with an interval of space between them ? We must be conscious of two things for this : of the duality of the ex cited points, and of the extensiveness of the unexcited interval. The duality alone, although a necessary, is not a sufficient condition of the spatial separation. We may, for instance, discern two sounds in the same place, sweet and sour in the same lemonade, warm and cold, round and pointed contact in the same place on the skin, etc.* In all discrimination the recognition of the duality of two feelings by the mind is the easier the more strongly the feelings are tions by drawing or representing new lines, and so on. But all this further industry has naught to do with our acquaintance with the relation itself, in its first intention. So cognized, the relation is the line and nothing more. It would indeed be fair to call it something less; and in fact it is easy to understand how most of us come to feel as if the line were a much &^osser thing than the relation. The line is broad or narrow, blue or red, made by this object or by that alternately, in the course of our experience; it is therefore independent of any one of these accidents; and so, from viewing it as no one of such sensible qualities, we may end by thinking of it as something which cannot be defined except as the negation of all sen- ^Voie quality whatever, and which needs to be put into the sensations by a mysterious act of 'relating thought.' Another reason why we get to feel as if a space-relation must be some thing other than the mere feeling of a line or angle is that between two positions we can potentially make any number of lines and angles, or find, to suit our purposes, endlessly numerous relations. The sense of this indefi nite potentiality cleaves to our words when we speak in a general way of 'relations of place,' and misleads us into supposing that not even any single one of them can be exhaustively equated by a single angle or a single line. * This often happens when the warm and cold points, or the round and pointed ones, are applied to the skin within the limits of a single ' Em- pfindungskreis.' 154 PSYCHOLOGY. contrasted in quality. If our two excited points awaken identical qualities of sensation, they must, perforce, appear to the mind as one ; and, not distinguished at all, they are, a fortiori, not localized apart. Spots four centimetres dis tant on the back have no qualitative contrast at all, and fuse into a single sensation. Points less than three thousandths of a millimetre apart awaken on the retina sensations so contrasted that we apprehend them immediately as two. Now these unlikenesses which arise so slowly when we pass from one point to another in the back, so much faster on the tongue and finger-tips, but with such inconceivable rapidity on the retina, what are they ? Can we discover anything about their intrinsic nature ? The most natural and immediate answer to make is that they are unlikeness of place pure and simple. In the words of a German physiologist,* to whom psychophysics owes much: " The sensations are from the outset (von vornhereiri) localized. . . . Every sensation as such is from the very beginning affected with the spatial quality, so that this quality is nothing like an external attribute coming to the sensation from a higher faculty, but must be regarded as something immanently residing in the sensation itself." And yet the moment we reflect on this answer an insu perable logical difficulty seems to present itself. No single quale of sensation can, by itself, amount to a consciousness of position. Suppose no feeling but that of a single point ever to be awakened. Could that possibly be the feeling of any special whereness or thereness ? Certainly not. Only when a second point is felt to arise can the first one acquire a determination of up, down, right or left, and these determina tions are all relative to that second point. Each point, so far as it is placed, is then only by virtue of what it is not, namely, by virtue of another point. This is as much as to say that position has nothing intrinsic about it ; and that, although a feeling of absolute bigness may, a feeling of place cannot^ possibly form an immanent element in any single isolated sensa tion. The very writer we have quoted has given heed to this objection, for he continues (p. 335) by saying that the * Vierordt, Grundriss der Physiologic, 5te Auflage (1877), pp. 326, 436. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. sensations thus originally localized " are only so in them selves, but not in the representation of consciousness, which is not yet present. . . . They are, in the first instance, de void of all mutual relations with each other." But such a localization of the sensation 'in itself ' would seem to mean nothing more than the susceptibility or potentiality of being distinctly localized when the time came and other conditions became fulfilled. Can we now discover anything about such susceptibility in itself before it has borne its ulterior fruits in the developed consciousness ? 'Local Signs.' To begin with, every sensation of the skin and every vis ceral sensation seems to derive from its topographic seat a peculiar shade of feeling, which it would not have in another place. And this feeling per se seems quite another thing from the perception of the place. Says Wundt * : " If with the finger we touch first the cheek and then the palm, exerting each time precisely the same pressure, the sensation shows not withstanding a distinctly marked difference in the two cases. Similarly, when we compare the palm with the back of the hand, the nape of the neck with its anterior surface, the breast with the back ; in short, any two distant parts of the skin with each other. And moreover, we easily remark, by attentively observing, that spots even tolerably close together differ in respect of the quality of their feeling. If we pass from one point of our cutaneous surface to another, we find a perfectly gradual and continuous alteration in our feeling, notwithstanding the objective nature of the contact has remained the same. Even the sen sations of corresponding points on opposite sides of the body, though similar, are not identical. If, for instance, we touch first the back of one hand and then of the other, we remark a qualitative unlikeness of sensation. It must not be thought that such differences are mere mat ters of imagination, and that we take the sensations to be different because we represent each of them to ourselves as occupying a different place. With sufficient sharpening of the attention, we may, confining ourselves to the quality of the feelings alone, entirely abstract from their locality, and yet notice the differences quite as markedly. " *Vorlesungen iib. Menschen- u. Thierseele (Leipzig, 1863), i. 214. See also Ladd's Physiological Psychology, pp. 396-8, and compare the account by G. Stanley Hall (Mind, x. 571) of the sensations produced by moving a blunt point lightly over the skin. Points of cutting pain, quivering, thrilling, whirling, tickling, scratching, and acceleration, alternated with each other along the surface. 156 PSYCHOLOGY. Whether these local contrasts shade into each other with absolutely continuous gradations, we cannot say. But we know (continues Wuiidt) that " they change, when we pass from one point of the skin to its neigh bor, with very different degrees of rapidity. On delicately-feeling parts, used principally for touching, such as the finger-tips, the dif ference of sensation between two closely approximate points is already strongly pronounced ; whilst in parts of lesser delicacy, as the arm, the back, the legs, the disparities of sensation are observable only between distant spots." The internal organs, too, have their specific qualia of sen sation. An inflammation of the kidney is different from one of the liver ; pains in joints and muscular insertions are distinguished. Pain in the dental nerves is wholly unlike the pain of a burn. But very important and curious similarities prevail throughout these differences. Internal pains, whose seat we cannot see, and have no means of knowing unless the character of the pain itself reveal it, are felt where they belong. Diseases of the stomach, kidney, liver, rectum, prostate, etc., of the bones, of the brain and its membranes, are referred to their proper posi tion. Nerve-pains describe the length of the nerve. Such localizations as those of vertical, frontal, or occipital head ache of intracranial origin force us to conclude that parts which are neighbors, whether inner or outer, may possess by mere virtue of that fact a common peculiarity of feeling, a respect in which their sensations agree, and which serves as a token of their proximity. These local colorings are, moreover, so strong that we cognize them as the same, throughout all contrasts of sensible quality in the accom panying perception. Cold and heat are wide as the poles asunder ; yet if both fall on the cheek, there mixes with them something that makes them in that respect identical ; just as, contrariwise, despite the identity of cold with itself wherever found, when we get it first on the palm and then on the cheek, some difference comes, which keeps the two experiences for ever asunder.* * Of the anatomical and physiological conditions of these facts we know as yet but little, and that little need not here be discussed. Two principal hypotheses have been invoked in the case of the retina. Wundt (Men- THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 157 And now let us revert to the query propounded a moment since : Can these differences of mere quality in feeling, varying according to locality yet having each sensibly and in trinsically and by itself nothing to do with position, constitute the ' susceptibilities ' we mentioned, the conditions of being per ceived in position, of the localities to ivhich they belong ? The numbers on a row of houses, the initial letters of a set of words, have no intrinsic kinship with points of space, and yet they are the conditions of our knowledge of where any house is in the row, or any word in the dictionary. Can the modifications of feeling in question be tags or labels of this kind which in no wise originally reveal the position of the spot to which they are attached, but guide us to it by what Berkeley would call a ' customary tie ' ? Many authors have unhesitatingly replied in the affirmative ; Lotze, who in his Medizinische Psychologic* first described the sensations in this way, designating them, thus conceived, as local-signs. This term has obtained wide currency in Germany, and in speaking of the ' LOCAL-SIGN THEORY ' hereafter, I shall always mean the theory ivhich denies that there can be in a sensation any element of actual locality, of inherent spatial order, any tone as schen-u. Thierseele, i. 214) called attention to the changes of color-sensibility which the retina displays as the image of the colored object passes from the fovea to the periphery. The color alters and becomes darker, and the change is more rapid in certain directions than in others. This alteration in general, however, is one of which, as such, \ve are wholly unconscious. We see the sky as bright blue all over, the modifications of the blue sensa tion being interpreted by us, not as differences in the objective color, but as distinctions in its locality. Lotze (Medizinische Psychologic, 333, 355), on the other hand, has pointed out the peculiar tendency which each particu lar point of the retina has to call forth that movement of the eyeball which will carry the image of the exciting object from the point in question to the fovea. With each separate tendency to movement (as with each actual movement) we may suppose a peculiar modification of sensibility to be conjoined. This modification would constitute the peculiar local tingeing of the image by each point. See also Sully 's Psychology, pp. 118-121. Prof. B. Erdman has quite lately (Vierteljahrsschrift f. wiss. Phil., x. 324-9) denied the existence of all evidence for such immanent qualia of feeling characterizing each locality. Acute as his remarks are, they quite fail to convince me. On the skin the qualia are evident, 1 should say. Where, as on the retina, they are less so (Kries and Auerbach), this may well be a mere difficulty of discrimination not yet educated to the analysis. * 1852, p. 331. 158 PSYCHOLOGY. it were which cries to us immediately and without further ado, 'I am here,' or 'I am there.' If, as may well be the case, we by this time find our selves tempted to accept the Local-sign theory in a general way, we have to clear up several farther matters. If a sign is to lead us to the thing it means, we must have some other source of knowledge of that thing. Either the thing has been given in a previous experience of which the sign also formed part — they are associated ; or it is what Reid calls a ' natural ' sign, that is, a feeling which, the first time it enters the mind, evokes from the native powers thereof a cognition of the thing that hitherto had lain dormant. In both cases, however, the sign is one thing, and the thing another. In the instance that now concerns us, the sign is a quality of feeling and the thing is a position. Now we have seen that the position of a point is not only revealed, but created, by the existence of other points to which it stands in determinate relations. If the sign can by any machinery which it sets in motion evoke a consciousness either of the other points, or of the relations, or of both, it would seem to fulfil its function, and reveal to us the position we seek. But such a machinery is already familiar to us. It is neither more nor less than the law of habit in the nervous system. When, any point of the sensitive surface has been frequently excited simultaneously with, or immediately before or after, other points, and afterwards comes to be excited alone, there will be a tendency for its perceptive nerve-centre to irradiate into the nerve-centres of the other points. Subjectively considered, this is the same as if we said that the peculiar feeling of the first point SUGGESTS the feeling of the entire region with whose stimulation its own ex citement has been habitually ASSOCIATED. Take the case of the stomach. When the epigastrium is heavily pressed, when certain muscles contract, etc., the stomach is squeezed, and its peculiar local sign awakes in consciousness simultaneously with the local signs of the other squeezed parts. There is also a sensation of total vastness aroused by the combined irritation, and someiuhere in this the stomach-feeling seems to lie. Suppose that later a pain arises in the stomach from some non-mechani- THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 159 cal cause. It will be tinged by the gastric local sign, and. the nerve-centre supporting this latter feeling will excite the centre supporting the dermal and muscular feelings habitually associated with it when the excitement was mechanical. From the combination the same peculiar vastness will again arise. In a word, ' something ' in the stomach-sensation ' reminds ' us of a total space, of which the diaphragmatic and epigastric sensations also form a part, or, to express it more briefly still, suggests the neigh borhood of these latter organs.* Revert to the case of two excited points on a surface with an unexcited space between them. The general result of previous experience has been that when either point was impressed by an outward object, the same object also touched the immediately neighboring parts. Each point, together with its local sign, is thus associated with a circle of surrounding points, the association fading in strength as the circle grows larger. Each will revive its own circle ; but when both are excited together, the strongest revival will be that due to the combined irradiation. Now the tract joining the two excited points is the only part common to the two circles. And the feelings of this whole tract will there fore awaken with considerable vividness in the imagination when its extremities are touched by an outward irritant. The mind receives with the impression of the two distinct points the vague idea of a line. The twoness of the points comes from the contrast of their local signs : the line conies from the associations into which experience has wrought these latter. If no ideal line arises we have duality with out sense of interval ; if the line be excited actually rather * Maybe the localization of intracranial pain is itself due to such asso ciation as this of local signs with each other, rather than to their qualita tive similarity in neighboring parts (supra, p. 19); though it is conceivable that association and similarity itself should here have one and the same neural basis. If we suppose the sensory nerves from those parts of the body beneath any patch of skin to terminate in the same sensorial brain- tract as those from the skin itself, and if the excitement of any one fibre tends to irradiate through the whole of that tract, the feelings of all fibres going to that tract would presumably both have a similar intrinsic quality, and at the same time tend each to arouse the other. Since the same nerve- trunk in most cases supplies the skin and the parts beneath, the anatomical hypothesis presents nothing improbable. 10U PSYCHOLOGY. than ideally, we have the interval given with its ends, in the form of a single extended object felt. E. H. Weber, in the famous article in which he laid the foundations of all our accurate knowledge of these subjects, laid it down as the logical requisite for the perception of two separated points, that the mind should, along with its consciousness of them, be come aware of an unexcited interval as such. I have only tried to show how the known laws of experience may cause this requi site to be fulfilled. Of course, if the local signs of the entire region offer but little qualitative contrast inter se, the line suggested will be but dimly denned or discriminated in length or direction from other possible lines in its neighbor hood. This is what happens in the back, where conscious ness can sunder two spots, whilst only vaguely apprehend ing their distance and direction apart. The relation of position of the two points is the sug gested interval or line. Turn now to the simplest case, that of a single excited spot. Hoiv can it suggest its position ? Not by recalling any particular line unless experience have constantly been in the habit of marking or tracing some one line from it towards some one neighboring point. Now on the back, belly, viscera, etc., no such tracing habitually occurs. The consequence is that the only suggestion is that of the whole neighboring circle ; i.e., the spot simply recalls the general region in which it happens to lie. By a pro cess of successive construction, it is quite true that we can also get the feeling of distance between the spot and some other particular spot. Attention, by reinforcing the local sign of one part of the circle, can awaken a new circle round this part, and so de proche en proche we may slide our feeling down from our cheek, say, to our foot. But when we first touched our cheek we had no consciousness of the foot at all.* In the extremities, the lips, the tongue and other mobile parts, the case is different. We there have an instinctive tendency, when a part of lesser discriminative * Unless, indeed, the foot happen to be spontaneously tingling or some thing of the sort at the moment. The whole surface of the body is always in a state of semi-conscious irritation which needs only the emphasis of attention, or of some accidental inward irritation, to become strong at any point. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 161 sensibility is touched, to move the member so that the touching object glides along it to the place where sensi bility is greatest. If a body touches our hand we move the hand over it till the finger-tips are able to explore it. If the sole of our foot touches anything we bring it towards the toes, and so forth. There thus arise lines of habitual passage from all points of a member to its sensitive tip. These are the lines most readily recalled when any point is touched, and their recall is identical with the conscious ness of the distance of the touched point from the ' tip.' I think anyone must be aware when he touches a point of his hand or wrist that it is the relation to the finger-tips of which he is usually most conscious. Points on the fore arm suggest either the finger-tips 'or the elbow (the latter being a spot of greater sensibility*). In the foot it is the toes, and so on. A point can only be cognized in its rela tions to the entire body at once by awakening a visual image of the whole body. Such awakening is even more obviously than the previously considered cases a matter of pure association. This leads us to the eye. On the retina the fovea and the yellow spot about it form a focus of exquisite sensibility, towards which every impression falling on an outlying por tion of the field is moved by an instinctive action of the muscles of the eyeball. Few persons, until their attention is called to the fact, are aware how almost impossible it is to keep a conspicuous visible object in the margin of the field of view. The moment volition is relaxed we find that without our knowing it our eyes have turned so as to bring it to the centre. This is why most persons are unable to keep the eyes steadily converged upon a point in space with nothing in it. The objects against the walls of the room * It is true that the inside of the fore- arm, though its discriminative sensibility is often less than that of the outside, usually rises very promi nently into consciousness when the latter is touched. Its esthetic sensi bility to contact is a good deal finer. We enjoy stroking it from the ex tensor to the flexor surface around the ulnar side more than in the reverse direction. Pronating movements give rise to contacts in this order, and are frequently indulged in when the back of the fore-arm feels an object against it. 162 PSYCHOLOGY. invincibly attract the foveae to themselves. If we contem plate a blank wall or sheet of paper, we always observe in a moment that we are directly looking at some speck upon it which, unnoticed at first, ended by 'catching our eye.' Thus ivhenever an image falling on the point P of the retina excites attention, it more habitually moves from that point toivards the fovea than in any one other direction. The line traced thus by the image is not always a straight line. When the direction of the point from the fovea is neither vertical nor horizon tal but oblique, the line traced is often a curve, with its con cavity directed upwards if the direction is upwards, down wards if the direction is downwards. This may be verified by anyone who will take the trouble to make a simple ex periment with a luminous body like a candle-flame in a dark enclosure, or a star. Gazing first at some point remote from the source of light, let the eye be suddenly turned 'full upon the latter. The luminous image will necessarily fall in succession upon a continuous series of points, reaching from the one first affected to the fovea. But by virtue of the slowness with which retinal excitements die away, the entire series of points will for an instant be visible as an after-image, displaying the above peculiarity of form ac cording to its situation.* These radiating lines are neither regular nor invariable in the same person, nor, probably, equally curved in different individuals. We are incessant ly drawing them between the fovea and every point of the field of view. Objects remain in their peripheral indistinct ness only so long as they are unnoticed. The moment we attend to them they grow distinct through one of these mo tions — which leads to the idea prevalent among uninstructed persons that we see distinctly all parts of the field of view at once. The result of this incessant tracing of radii is that whenever a local sign P is awakened by a spot of light falling upon it, it recalls forthwith, even though the eyeball be unmoved, the local signs of all the other points ivhich lie between P and the fovea. It recalls them in imaginary form, just as the normal reflex movement would recall them in vivid form ; and with their recall is given a consciousness more or less * These facts were first noticed by Wundt: see his Beitrage, p. 140, 202 See also Larnansky, Pfliiger's Archiv, xi. 418. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 163 faint of the whole line on which they lie. In other words, no ray of light can fall on any retinal spot without the lo cal sign of that spot revealing to us, by recalling the line of its most habitual associates, its direction and distance from the centre of the field. The fovea acts thus as the origin of a system of polar co-ordinates, in relation to which each and every retinal point has through an incessantly-re peated process of association its distance and direction de termined. Were P alone illumined and all the rest of the field dark we should still, even with motionless eyes, know whether P lay high or low, right or left, through the ideal .streak, different from all other streaks, which P alone has the power of awakening.* * So far all has been plain sailing, but our course begins to be so tortu ous when we descend into minuter detail that I will treat of the more pre cise determination of locality in a long note. When P recalls an ideal line leading to the fovea the line is felt in its entirety and but vaguely ; whilst P, which we supposed to be a single star of actual light, stands out in strong distinction from it. The ground of the distinction between P and the ideal line which it terminates is manifest— P being vivid while the line is faint ; but why should P hold the particular position it does, at the end of tlie line, rather than anywhere else— for example, in its middle? That seems something not at all manifest. To clear up our thoughts about this latter mystery, let us take the case of an actual line of light, none of whose parts is ideal. The feeling of the line is produced, as we know, when a multitude of retinal points are excited together, each of which when excited separately would give rise to one of the feelings called local signs. Each of these signs is the feeling of a small space. From their simultaneous arousal we might well suppose a feeling of larger space to result. But why is it necessary that in this larger spaciousness the sign a should appear always at one end of the line, 2 at the other, and m in the middle ? For though the line be a unitary streak of light, its several constituent points can nevertheless break out from it, and become alive, each for itself, under the selective eye of atten tion. The uncritical reader, giving his first careless glance at the subject, will say that there is no mystery in this, and that ' of course ' local signs must appear alongside of each other, each in its own place; — there is no other way possible. But the more philosophic student, whose business it is to discover difficulties quite as much as to get rid of them, will reflect that it is conceivable that the partial factors might fuse into a larger space, and yet not each be located within it any more than a voice is located in a chorus. He will wonder how, after combining into the line, the points can become severally alive again : the separate puffs of a ' sirene ' no longer strike the ear after they have fused into a certain pitch of sound. He will recall the fact that when, after looking at things with one eye closed, we PSYCHOLOGY. And with this we can close the first great division of our subject. We have shown that, within the range of double^bVopening the other eye, the number of retinal points affected, the new retinal sensations do not as a rule appear alongside of the old ones and additional to them, but merely make the old ones seem laro-er and nearer. Why should the affection of new points on the same retina have so different a result? In fact, he will see no sort of logical connection between (1) the original separate local signs, (2) the line as a unit (3) the line with the points discriminated in it, and (4) the various nerve-processes which subserve all these different things. He will suspect our local sign of being a very slippery and ambiguous sort of creature. Positionless at first, it no sooner appears in the midst of a gang of compan ions than it is found maintaining the strictest position of its own, and as signing place to each of its associates. How is this possible? Must we accept what we rejected a while ago as absurd, and admit the points each to have position in se ? Or must we suspect that our whole construction has been fallacious, and that we have tried to conjure up, out of association, qualities which the associates never contained? There is no doubt a real difficulty here; and the shortest way of dealing with it would be to confess it insoluble and ultimate. Even if position be not an intrinsic character of any one of those sensations we have calle local signs we must still admit that there is something about everyone of them that stands for the potentiality of position, and is the ground why tl local sign when it gets placed at all, gets placed Aero rather than there. ' something ' be interpreted as a physiological something, as a mere nerve- process it is easy to say in a blank way that when it is excited alone, it an 'ultimate fact '(1) that a positionless spot will appear; that when il excited together with other similar processes, but without Ithe process o discriminative attention, it is another 'ultimate fact ' (2) that a unitary line will come- and that the final 'ultimate fact' (3) is that, when the nerve- process is excited in combination with that other process which subserves the feeling of attention, what results will be the line with the local sign inside of it determined to a particular place. Thus we should escape the responsibility of explaining, by falling back on the everlasting inscruta bility of the psycho-neural nexus. The moment we call the ground of 1 calization physiological, we need only point out how, in those cases i which localization occurs, the physiological process differs from those 11 which it does not, to have done all we can possibly do in the matter, would be unexceptionable logic, and with it we might let the matter drop, satisfied that there was no self-contradiction in it, but only the universal psychological puzzle of how a new mode of consciousness emerges when ever a fundamentally new mode of nervous action occurs. But blameless as such tactics would logically be on our part, let us see whether we cannot push our theoretic insight a little farther. It seems t me we can We cannot, it is true, give a reason why the line we feel when process (2) awakens should have its own peculiar shape; nor can we explain the essence of the process of discriminative attention. But we can s. why if the brute facts be admitted that a line may have one of its parts singled out by attention at all, and that that part may appear in relation to THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 165 every sense, experience takes ab initio the spatial form. We have also shown that in the cases of the retina and skin other parts at all, the relation must be in the line itself, — for the line and the parts are the only things supposed to be in consciousness. And we can furthermore suggest a reason why parts appearing thus in relation to each other in a line should fall into an immutable order, and each within that order keep its characteristic place. If a lot of such local signs all have any quality which evenly augments as we pass from one to the other, we can arrange them in an ideal serial order, in which any one local sign must lie below those with more, above those with less, of the quality in question. It must divide the series into two parts, — unless indeed it have a maximum or minimum of the quality, when it either begins or ends it. Such an ideal series of local signs in the mind is, however, not yet iden tical with the feeling of a line in space. Touch a dozen points on the skin successively, and there seems no necessary reason why the notion of a defi nite line should emerge, even though we be strongly aware of a gradation of quality among the touches. We may of course symbolically arrange them in a line in our thought, but we can always distinguish between a line symbolically thought aud a line directly felt. But note now the peculiarity of the nerve-processes of all these local signs: though they may give no line when excited successively, when ex cited together they do give the actual sensation of a line in space. The sum of them is the neural process of that line; the sum of their feelings is the feeling of that line; and if we begin to single out particular points from the line, and notice them by their rank, it is impossible to see how this rank can appear except as an actual fixed space-position sensibly felt as a bit of the total line. The scale itself appearing as a line, rank in it must appear as a definite part of the line. If the seven notes of an octave, when heard together, appeared to the sense of hearing as an outspread line of sound— which it is needless to say they do not— why then no one note could be discriminated without being localized, according to its pitch, in the line, either as one of its extremities or as some part between. But not alone the gradation of their quality arranges the local-sign feelings in a scale. Our movements arrange them also in a towd-scale. Whenever a stimulus passes from point a of the skin or retina to point/, it awakens the local -sign feelings in the perfectly definite time-order abcdef. It cannot excite/ until cde have been successively aroused. The feeling c sometimes is preceded by ab, sometimes followed by ba, according to the movement's direction; the result of it all being that we never feel either a, c, or/, without there clinging to it faint reverberations of the various time- orders of transition in which, throughout past experience, it has been aroused. To the local sign a there clings the tinge or tone, the penumbrn or fringe, of the transition bed. To/ to c, there cling quite different tones. Once admit the principle that a feeling may be tinged by the reproductive consciousness of an habitual transition, even when the transition is not made, and it seems entirely natural to admit that, if the transition be habit ually in the order abcdef, and if a, c, and/ be felt separately at all, a will be felt with an essential earliness, /with an essential lateness, and that c will 166 PSYCHOLOGY. every sensible total may be subdivided by discriminative attention into sensible parts, which are also spaces, and into relations between the parts, these being sensible spaces too. Furthermore, we have seen (in a foot-note) that differ ent parts, once discriminated, necessarily fall into a deter minate order, both by reason of definite gradations in their quality, and by reason of the fixed order of time-succes sion in which movements arouse them. But in all this nothing has been said of the comparative measurement of one sensible space- total against another, or of the way in which, by summing our divers simple sensible space- experiences together, we end by ronstructing what we re gard as the unitary, continuous, and infinite objective Space of the real world. To this more difficult inquiry we next THE CONSTRUCTION OF 'HEAL' SPACE, The problem breaks into two subordinate problems < (1) How is the subdivision and measurement of the several sensorial spaces completely effected ? and (2) Now do their mutual addition and fusion and reduction to the same scale, in a ivord, hoiv does their synthesis, occur ? I think that, as in the investigation just finished, we found ourselves able to get along without invoking any data but those that pure sensibility on the one hand, and the ordinary intellectual powers of discrimination and recollec- fall between. Thus those psychologists who set little store by local signs and great store by movements in explaining space-perception, would have a perfectly definite time-order, due to motion, by which to account for the definite order of positions that appears when sensitive spots are excited all at once. Without, however, the preliminary admission of the * ulti mate fact' that this collective excitement shall feel like a line and nothing else, it can never be explained why the new order should needs be an order of positions, and not of merely ideal serial rank. We shall hereafter have any amount of opportunity to observe how thoroughgoing is the par ticipation of motion in all our spatial measurements. Whether the local signs have their respective qualities evenly graduated or not, the feelings of transition must be set down as among the verce causa in localization. But the gradation of the local signs is hardly to be doubted ; so we may be lieve ourselves really to possess two sets of reasons for localizing any point we may happen to distinguish from out the midst of any line or any larger space. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 167 tion on the other, were able to yield ; so here we shall emerge from our more complicated quest with the convic tion that all the facts can be accounted for on the supposi tion that no other mental forces have been at work save those we find everywhere else in psychology : sensibility, namely, for the data ; and discrimination, association, memory, and choice for the rearrangements and combina tions which they undergo. 1. The Subdivision of the Original Sense-spaces. How are spatial subdivisions brought to consciousness ? in other words, How does spatial discrimination occur? The general subject of discrimination has been treated in a previous chapter. Here we need only inquire what are the conditions that make spatial discrimination so much finer in sight than in touch, and in touch than in hearing, smell, or taste. The first great condition is, that different points of the surface shall differ in the quality of their immanent sensibility r, that is, that each shall carry its special local-sign. If the skin felt everywhere exactly alike, a foot-bath could be dis tinguished from a total immersion, as being smaller, but never distinguished from a wet face. The local-signs are indispensable ; two points which have the same local-sign will always be felt as the same point. "We do not judge them two unless we have discerned their sensations to be different.* Granted none but; homogeneous irritants, that organ would then distinguish the greatest multiplicity of irritants — would count most stars or compass-points, or best compare the size of two wet surfaces — whose local sensibility was the least even. A skin whose sensibility shaded rapidly off from a focus, like the apex of a boil, would be better than a homogeneous integument for spatial perception. The retina, with its exquisitely sensitive fovea, has this peculiarity, and undoubtedly owes to it a great part *M. Binet (Revue Philosophique, Sept. 1880, page 291) says we judge them locally different as soon as their sensations differ enough for us to distinguish them as qualitatively different when successively excited. This is not strictly true. Skin-sensations, different enough to be discriminated when successive, may still fuse locally if excited both at once. 168 PSYCHOLOGY. * • of the minuteness with which we are able to subdivide the total bigness of the sensation it yields. On its periphery the local differences do not shade off very rapidly, and we can count there fewer subdivisions. But these local differences of feeling, so long as the surface is unexcited from without, are almost null. I canot feel them by a pure mental act of attention unless they belong to quite distinct parts of the body, as the nose and the lip, the finger tip and the ear ; their contrast needs the reinforcement of outward excitement to be felt. In the spatial muchness of a colic — or, to call it by the more spacious-sounding verna cular, of a ' bellyache ' — one can with difficulty distinguish the north-east from the south-west corner, but can do so much more easily if, by pressing one's finger against the former region, one is able to make the pain there more in tense. The local differences require then an adventitious sensa tion, superinduced upon them, to awaken the attention. After the attention has once been awakened in this way, it may continue to be conscious of the unaided difference ; just as a sail on the horizon may be too faint for us to notice until someone's finger, placed against the spot, has pointed it out to us, but may then remain visible after the finger has been withdrawn. But all this is true only on condition that separate points of the surface may be exclusively stimulated. If the whole surface at once be excited from without, and homogeneously, as, for example, by immersing the body in salt water, local discrimination is not furthered. The local- signs, it is true, all awaken at once ; but in such multitude that no one of them, with its specific quality, stands out in contrast with the rest. If, however, a single extremity be immersed, the contrast between the wet and dry parts is strong, and, at the surface of the water especially, the local- signs attract the attention, giving the feeling of a ring sur rounding the member. Similarly, two or three wet spots separated by dry spots, or two or three hard points against the skin, will help to break up our consciousness of the latter's bigness. In cases of this sort, where points re ceiving an identical kind of excitement are, nevertheless, felt to be locally distinct, and the objective irritants are also THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 169 judged multiple, — e.g., compass-points on skin or stars ou retina, — the ordinary explanation is no doubt just, and we judge the outward causes to be multiple because we have discerned the local feelings of their sensations to be dif ferent. Capacity for partial stimulation is thus the second condi tion favoring discrimination. A sensitive surface which has to be excited in all its parts at once can yield nothing but a sense of undivided largeness. This appears to be the case with the olfactory, and to all intents and purposes with the gustatory, surfaces. Of many tastes and flavors, even sim ultaneously presented, each affects the totality of its re spective organ, each appears with the whole vastness given by that organ, and appears interpenetrated by the rest* * It may. however, be said that even iu the tongue there is a determina tion of bitter flavors to the back and of acids to the front edge of the organ. Spices likewise affect its sides and front, and a taste like that of alum localizes itself, by its styptic effect on the portion of mucous membrane, which it immediately touches, more sharply than roast pork, for example, which stimulates all parts alike. The pork, therefore, tastes more spacious than the alum or the pepper. In the nose, too, certain smells, of which viuegar may be taken as the type, seem less spatially extended than heavy, suffocating odors, like musk. The reason of this appears to be that the former inhibit inspiration by their sharpness, whilst the latter are drawn into the lungs, and thus excite an objectively larger surface. The asc? p- tion of height and depth to certain notes seems due, not to any localization of the sounds, but to the fact that a feeling of vibration in the chest and tension in the gullet accompanies the singing of a bass note, whilst, when we sing high, the palatine mucous membrane is drawn upon by the muscles which move the larynx, and awakens a feeling in the roof of the mouth. The only real objection to the law of partial stimulation laid down in the text is one that might be drawn from the organ of hearing; for, ac cording to modern theories, the cochlea may have its separate nerve-termini exclusively excited by sounds of differing pitch, and yet the sounds seem all to fill a common space, and not necessarily to be arranged alongside of each other. At most the high note is felt as a thinner, brighter streak against a darker background. In an article on Space, published in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy for January, 1879, 1 ventured to suggest that possibly the auditory nerve termini might be "excited all at once by sounds of any pitch, as the whole retina would be by every luminous point if there were no dioptric apparatus affixed." And I added : "Notwith standing the brilliant conjectures of the last few years which assign differ ent acoustic end-organs to different rates of air-wave, we are still greatly in the dark about the subject ; and I, for my part, would much more con fidently reject a theory of hearing which violated the principles advanced in 170 PSYCHOLOGY. I should have been willing some years ago to name with out hesitation a third condition of discrimination — saying it would be most developed in that organ which is susceptible of the most various qualities of feeling. The retina is un questionably such an organ. The colors and shades it perceives are infinitely more numerous than the diversities of skin -sensation. And it can feel at once white and black, whilst the ear can in nowise so feel sound and silence. But the late researches of Donaldson, Blix, and Goldscheider, * on specific points for heat, cold, pressure, and pain in the skin ; the older ones of Czermak (repeated later by Klug in Ludwig's laboratory), showing that a hot and a cold compass-point are no more easily discriminated as two than two of equal temperature ; and some unpublished experi ments of my own — all disincline me to make much of this condition now.t There is, however, one quality of sensa- tliis article than give up those principles for the sake of any hypothesis hitherto published about either organs of Corti or basilar membrane." Professor Rutherford's theory of hearing, advanced at the meeting of the British Association for 1886, already furnishes an alternative view which would make hearing present no exception to the space-theory I defend and which, whether destined to be proved true or false, ought, at any rate to make us feel that the Helmholtzian theory is probably not the last wora in the physiology of hearing. Stepano, ff. (Hermann und Schwalbe's Jahres- bericht, xv. 404. Literature 1886) reports a case in which more than the upper half of one cochlea was lost without any such deafness to deep notes on that side as Helmholtz's theory would require. * Donaldson, in Mind, x. 399, 577; Goldscheider, in Archiv f . (Anat u.) Physiologie; Blix, in Zeitschrift fur Biologic. A good resume may be found in Ladd's Physiol. Psychology, part n. chap. TV. §§ 21-23. fl tried on nine or ten people, making numerous observations on each, what difference it made in the discrimination of two points to have them alike or unlike. The points chosen were (1) two large needle-heads, (2) two screw-heads, and (3) a needle-head and a screw- head. The distance of the screw-heads was measured from their centres. I found that when the points gave diverse qualities of feeling (as in 3), this facilitated the discrimination, but much less strongly than I expected The difference, in fact, would often not be perceptible twenty times running When, however, one of the points was endowed with a rotary movement, the other remaining still, the doubleness of the points became much more evi dent than before. To observe this I took an ordinary pair of compasses with one point blunt, and the movable leg replaced by a metallic rod which could, at any moment, be made to rotate in situ by a dentist's drilling-machine, to which it was attached. The compass had then its points applied to the skin at such a distance apart as to be felt as one impression. Suddenly rotating the drill-apparatus then almost always made them seem as two. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 171 tion which is particularly exciting, and that is the feeling of motion over any of our surfaces. The erection of this into a separate elementary quality of sensibility is one of the most recent of psychological achievements, and is worthy of detaining us a while at this point. The Sensation of Motion over Surfaces. The feeling of motion has generally been assumed by physiologists to be impossible until the positions of terminus a quo and terminus ad quern are severally cognized, and the successive occupancies of these positions by the moving body are perceived to be separated by a distinct interval of time.* As a matter of fact, however, we cognize only the very slowest motions in this way. Seeing the hand of a clock at XII and afterwards at VI, we judge that it has moved through the interval. Seeing the sun now in the east and again in the west, I infer it to have passed over my head. But we can only infer that which we already generically know in some more direct fashion, and it is ex perimentally certain that we have the feeling of motion given us as a direct and simple sensation. Czermak long ago pointed out the difference between seeing the motion of the second-hand of a watch, when we look directly at it, and noticing the fact of its having altered its position when we fix our gaze upon some other point of the dial-plate. In the first case we have a specific quality of sensation which is absent in the second. If the reader will find a portion of his skin — the arm, for example — where a pair of com pass-points an inch apart are felt as one impression, and if he will then trace lines a tenth of an inch long on that spot with a pencil-point, he will be distinctly aware of the point's motion and vaguely aware of the direction of the motion. The perception of the motion here is certainly not derived from a pre-existing knowledge that its starting and ending points are separate positions in space, because positions in space ten times wider apart fail to be discriminated as such * This is only another example of what I call ' the psychologist's fal lacy '—thinking that the mind he is studying must necessarily be conscious of the object after the fashion in which the psychologist himself is con scious of it. 172 PSYCHOLOGY. when excited by the dividers. It is the same with the retina. One's fingers when cast upon its peripheral portions cannot be counted — that is to say, the five retinal tracts which they occupy are not distinctly apprehended by the mind as five separate positions in space — and yet the slight est movement of the fingers is most vividly perceived as movement and nothing else. It is thus certain that our sense of movement, being so much more delicate than our sense of position, cannot possibly be derived from it. A curious observation by Exner * completes the proof that move ment is a primitive form of sensibility, by showing it to be much more delicate than our sense of succession in time. This very able physiologist caused two electric sparks to appear in rapid succession, one beside the other. The observer had to state whether the right-hand one or the left-hand one appeared first. When the interval was re duced to as short a time as 0.044" the discrimination of temporal order in the sparks became impossible. But Exner found that if the sparks were brought so close to gether in space that their irradiation-circles overlapped, the eye then felt their flashing as if it were the motion of a single spark from the point occupied by the first to the point occupied by the second, and the time-interval might then be made as small as 0.015" before the mind began to be in doubt as to whether the apparent motion started from the right or from the left. On the skin similar ex periments gave similar results. Vierordt, at almost the same time,^ called atttention to cer tain persistent illusions, amongst which are these : If another person gently trace a line across our wrist or finger, the latter being stationary, it will feel to us as if the mem ber were moving in the opposite direction to the tracing point. If, on the contrary, we move our limb across a fixed point, it will be seen as if the point were moving as well. If the reader will touch his forehead with his forefinger kept motionless, and then rotate the head so that the skin of the forehead passes beneath the finger's tip, he will Lave *Sitzb. der. k. Akad. Wien, Bd. LXXII., Abth. 3 (1875). f Zeitschrift fttr Biologie, xii. 226 (1876). TEE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 173 an irresistible sensation of the latter being itself in motion in the opposite direction to the head. So in abducting the fingers from each other ; some may move and the rest be still still, but the still ones will feel as if they were actively sep arating from the rest. These illusions, according to Vierordt, are survivals of a primitive form of perception, when motion was felt as such, but ascribed to the whole content of consciousness, and not yet distinguished as belonging ex clusively to one of its parts. When our perception is fully developed we go beyond the mere relative motion of thing and ground, and can ascribe absolute motion to one of these components of our total object, and absolute rest to another. When, in vision for example, the whole background moves together, we think that it is ourselves or our eyes which are moving ; and any object in the foreground which may move relatively to the background is judged by us to be still. But primitively this discrimination cannot be per fectly made. The sensation of the motion spreads over all that we see and infects it. Any relative motion of object and retina both makes the object seem to move, and makes us feel ourselves in motion. Even now when our whole ob ject moves we still get giddy ; and we still see an apparent motion of the entire field of view, whenever we suddenly jerk our head and eyes or shake them quickly to and fro. Pushing our eyeballs gives the same illusion. We knoiv in all these cases what really happens, but the conditions are unusual, so our primitive sensation persists unchecked. So it does when clouds float by the moon. We know the moon is still ; but we see it move even faster than the clouds. Even when we slowly move our eyes the primitive sensation persists under the victorious conception. If we notice closely the experience, we find that any object towards which we look appears moving to meet our eye. But the most valuable contribution to the subject is the paper of G. H. Schneider,* who takes up the matter zoologically, and shows by examples from every branch of the animal kingdom that movement is the quality by which animals most easily attract each other's attention. The in- * Vierteljahrsch. ftir wiss. Philos., n. 377. 174 PSYCHOLOGY. stinct of ' shamming death ' is no shamming of death at all, but rather a paralysis through fear, which saves the insect, crustacean, or other creature from being noticed at oil by his enemy. It is parallelled in the human race by the breath- Jiolding stillness of the boy playing ' I spy,' to whom the seeker is near ; and its obverse side is shown in our invol untary waving of arms, jumping up and down, and so forth, when we wish to attract someone's attention at a distance. Creatures ' stalking ' their prey and creatures hiding from their pursuers alike show how immobility diminishes con- spicuity. In the woods, if we are quiet, the squirrels aiid birds will actually touch us. Flies will light on stuffed birds and stationary frogs.* On the other hand, the tre mendous shock of feeling the thing we are sitting on begin to move, the exaggerated start it gives us to have an insect unexpectedly pass over our skin, or a cat noiselessly come and snuffle about our hand, the excessive reflex effects of tickling, etc., show how exciting the sensation of motion is per se. A kitten cannot help pursuing a moving ball. Im pressions too faint to be cognized at all are immediately felt if they move. A fly sitting is unnoticed, —we feel it the moment it crawls. A shadow may be too faint to be per ceived. As soon as it moves, however, we see it. Schneider found that a shadow, with distinct outline, and directly fix ated, could still be perceived when moving, although its objective strength might be but half as great as that of a stationary shadow so faint as just to disappear. With a blurred shadow in indirect vision the difference in favor of motion was much greater — namely, 13.3 : 40.7. If we hold a finger between our closed eyelid and the sunshine we shall not notice its presence. The moment we move it to and fro, however, we discern it. Such visual perception as this reproduces the conditions of sight among the radiates, t * Bxner tries to show that the structure of the faceted eye of articulates adapts it for perceiving motions almost exclusively. f Schneider tries to explain why a sensory surface is so much more ex cited when its impression moves. It has long since been noticed how much more acute is discrimination of successive than of simultaneous differences. But in the case of a moving impression, say on the retina, we have a sum- THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 175 Enough has now been said to show that in the education of spatial discrimination the motions of impressions across sen sory surfaces must have been the principal agent in breaking up our consciousness of the surfaces into a consciousness of their parts. Even to-day the main function of the pe ripheral regions of our retina is that of sentinels, which, when beams of light move over them, cry ' Who goes there ? ' and call the fovea to the spot. Most parts of the skin do but perform the same office for the finger-tips. Of course finger-tips and fovea leave some power of direct perception to marginal retina and skin respectively. But it is worthy of note that such perception is best developed on the skin of the most movable parts (the labors of Vierordt and his pupils have well shown this) ; and that in the blind, whose skin is exceptionally discriminative, it seems to have become so through the inveterate habit which most of them possess of twitching and moving it under whatever object may touch them, so as to become better acquainted with the con formation of the same. Czermak was the first to notice this. It may be easily verified. Of course movement of surface und&r object is (for purposes of stimulation) equivalent to move ment of object over surface. In exploring the shapes and mation of both sorts of difference ; whereof the natural effect must be to produce the most perfect discrimination of all. Fio. 68. In the left-hand figure let the dark spot B move, for example, from right to left. At the outset there is the simultaneous contrast of black and white in B and A. When the motion has occurred so that the right-hand figure is produced, the same contrast remains, the black and the white having changed places. But in addition to it there is a double suc cessive contrast, first in A, which, a moment ago white, has now become black ; and second in B, which, a moment ago black, has now become white. If we make each single feeling of contrast = 1 (a supposition tar too favorable to the state of rest), the sum of contrasts in the case of motion will be 3, as against 1 in the state of rest. That is, our attention will be called by a treble force to the difference of color, provided the color be gin to move.— (Cf. also Fleischl, Physiologische Optische Notizen, 2te Mittheilung, Wiener Sitzungsberichte, 1882.) 176 PSYCHOLOGY. sizes of things by either eye or skin the movements of these organs are incessant and unrestrainable. Every such move ment draws the points and lines of the object across the surface, imprints them a hundred times more sharply, and drives them home to the attention. The immense part thus played by movements in our perceptive activity is held by many psychologists* to prove that the muscles are them selves the space-perceiving organ. Not surface-sensibility, but ' the muscular sense,' is for these writers the original and only revealer of objective extension. But they have all failed to notice with what peculiar intensity muscular contractions call surface-sensibilities into play, and that the mere discrimination of impressions (quite apart from any question of measuring the space between them) largely depends on the mobility of the surface upon which they fall, t * Brown, Bain, J. 8. Mill, and in a modified manner Wundt, Helmholtz, Sully, etc. fM. Ch. Dunan, in his forcibly written essay ' 1'Espace Visuel et 1'Espace Tactile ' in the Revue Philosophique for 1888, endeavors to prove that surfaces alone give no perception of extent, by citing the way in which the blind go to work to gain an idea of an object's shape. If surfaces were the percipient organ, he says, " both the seeing and the blind ought to gain an exact idea of the size (and shape) of an object by merely laying their hand flat upon it (provided of course that it were smaller than the hand), and this because of their direct appreciation of the amount of tactile surface affected, and with no recourse to the muscular sense. . . . But the fact is that a person born blind never proceeds in this way to measure ob jective surfaces. The only means which he has of getting at the size of a body is that of running his finger along the lines by which it is bounded. For instance, if you put into the hands of one born blind a book whose dimensions are unknown to him, he will begin by resting it against his chest so as to hold it horizontal ; then, bringing his two hands together at the middle of the edge opposite to the one against his body, he will draw them asunder till they reach the ends of the edge in question . and then, and not till then, will he be able to say what the length of the object is " (vol. xxv. p. 148). I think that anyone who will try to appreciate the size and shape of an object by simply ' laying his hand flat upon it ' will find that the great obstacle is that he feels the contours so imperfectly. The moment, however, the hands move, the contours are emphatically and dis tinctly felt. All perception of shape and size is perception of contours, and first of all these must be made sharp. Motion does this ; and the impulse to move our organs in perception is primarily due to the craving which we feel to get our surface-sensations sharp. When it comes to the naming and THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. Ill 2. The Measurement of the sense-spaces against each other. What precedes is all we can say in answer to the problem of discrimination. Turn now to that of measurement of the several spaces against each other, that being the first step in our constructing out of our diverse space-experiences the one space we believe in as that of the real world. The first thing that seems evident is that we have no immediate power of comparing together with any accuracy the extents revealed by different sensations. Our mouth- cavity feels indeed to itself smaller, and to the tongue larger, than it feels to the finger or eye, our tympanic membrane feels larger than our finger-tip, our lips feel larger than a surface equal to them on our thigh. So much comparison is immediate ; but it is vague ; and for anything exact we must resort to other help. The great agent in comparing the extent felt by one sensory surface with that felt by another, is superposition — superposition of one surface upon another, and superposition of one outer thing upon many surfaces. Thus are exact equivalencies and common measures introduced, and the way prepared for numerical results. Could we not superpose one part of our skin upon an other, or one object on both parts, we should hardly suc ceed in coming to that knowledge of our own form which we possess. The original differences of bigness of our dif ferent parts would remain vaguely operative, and we should have no certainty as to how much lip was equivalent to so much forehead, how much finger to so much back. But with the power of exploring one part of the surface by another we get a direct perception of cutaneous equiva lencies. The primitive differences of bigness are over powered when we feel by an immediate sensation that a certain length of thigh-surface is in contact with the entire palm and fingers. And when a motion of the opposite finger tips draws a line first along this same length of thigh and measuring of objects in terms of some common standard we shall see pres ently how movements help also , but no more in this case than the other do they help, because the quality of extension itself is contributed by iha 'muscular sense.' 178 PSYCHOLOGY, then along the whole of the hand in question, we get a new manner of measurement, less direct but confirming the equivalencies established by the first. In these ways, by superpositions of parts and by tracing lines on different parts by identical movements, a person deprived of sight can soon learn to reduce all the dimensions of his body to a homogeneous scale. By applying the same methods to objects of his own size or smaller, he can with equal ease make himself acquainted with their extension stated in terms derived from his own bulk, palms, feet, cubits, spans, paces, fathoms (armspreads), etc. In these reductions it is to be noticed that when the resident sensations of largeness of two opposed surfaces conflict, one of the sensations is chosen as the trite standard and the other treated as illusory. Thus an empty tooth-socket is believed to be really smaller than the finger-tip which it will not admit, although it may feel larger ; and in general it may be said that the hand, as the almost exclusive organ of palpation, gives its own magnitude to the other parts, instead of having its size determined by them. In general, it is, as Fechner says, the extent felt by the more sensitive part to which the other extents are re duced. * But even though exploration of one surface by another were impossible, we could always measure our various surfaces against each other by applying the same extended object first to one and then to another. We should of course have the alternative of supposing that the object itself waxed and waned as it glided from one place to another (cf. above, p. 141) ; but the principle of simplifying as much as possible our world would soon drive us out of that assumption into the easier one that objects as a rule * Fechner describes (Psychophysik, i. 132) a ' method of equivalents' for measuring the sensibility of the skin. Two compasses are used, one on the part A another on the part B, of the surface The points on B must be adjusted so that their distance apart appears equal to that between the points on A With the place A constant, the second pair of points must be varied a great deal for every change in the place B though for the snrne A and B the relation of the two compasses is remarkably constant, and con tinues unaltered for mouths provided but few experiments are made on each day. If, however, we practise dally their difference grows less, in accordance with the law given tn the text THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 179 keep their sizes, and that most of our sensations are affected by errors for which a constant allowance must be made. In the retina there is no reason to suppose that the bignesses of two impressions (lines or blotches) falling on different regions are primitively felt to stand in any exact mutual ratio. It is only when the impressions come from the same object that we judge their sizes to be the same. And this, too, only when the relation of the object to the eye is believed to be on the whole unchanged. When the object by moving changes its relations to the eye the sensa tion excited by its image even on the same retinal region becomes so fluctuating that we end by ascribing no absolute import whatever to the retinal space-feeling which at any moment we may receive. So complete does this overlook ing of retinal magnitude become that it is next to impossi ble to compare the visual magnitudes of objects at different distances without making the experiment of superposition.' We cannot say beforehand how much of a distant house or tree our finger will cover. The various answers to the familiar question, How large is the moon ? — answers which vary from a cartwheel to a wafer — illustrate this most strikingly. The hardest part of the training of a young draughtsman is his learning to feel directly the retinal (i.e. primitively sensible) magnitudes which the different objects in the field of view subtend. To do this he must recover what Buskin calls the ' innocence of the eye ' — that is, a sort of childish perception of stains of color merely as such, without consciousness of what they mean. With the rest of us this innocence is lost. Out of all the ^JUi visual magnitudes of each known object we have selected one as the REAL one to think of, and degraded all the others to serve as its signs. This ' real ' magnitude is determined by aesthetic and practical interests. It is that which we get when the object is at the distance most propitious for exact visual discrimination of its details. This is the distance at which we hold anything we are examining. Farther than this we see it too small, nearer too large. And the larger and the smaller feeling vanish in the act of suggesting this one, their more important meaning. As I look along the dining- 180 PSYCHOLOGY. table I overlook the fact that the farther plates and glasses feel so much smaller than my own, for I know that they are all equal in size ; and the feeling of them, which is a present sensation, is eclipsed in the glare of the knowledge, which is a merely imagined one. If the inconsistencies of sight-spaces inter se can thus be reduced, of course there can be no difficulty in equating sight-spaces with spaces given to touch. In this equation it is probably the touch-feeling which prevails as real and the sight which serves as sign — a reduction made necessary not only by the far greater constancy of felt over seen magnitudes, but by the greater practical interest which the sense of touch possesses for our lives. As a rule, things only benefit or harm us by coming into direct contact with our skin : sight is only a sort of anticipatory touch ; the latter is, in Mr. Spencer's phrase, the 'mother-tongue of thought,' and the handmaid's idiom must be translated into the language of the mistress before it can speak clearly to the mind.* Later on we shall see that the feelings excited in the joints when a limb moves are used as signs of the path traversed by the extremity. But of this more anon. As for the equating of sound-, smell-, and taste-volumes with those yielded by the more discriminative senses, they are too vague to need any remark. It may be observed of pain, however, that its size has to be reduced to that of the normal tactile size of the organ which is its seat. A finger with a felon on it, and the pulses of the arteries therein, both 'feel ' larger than we believe they really 'are.' * Prof. Jastrow gives as the result of his experiments this general conclusion (Am. Journal of Psychology, in. 53) : "The space-perceptions of disparate senses are themselves disparate, and whatever harmony there is amongst them we are warranted in regarding as the result of experience. The spacial notions of one deprived of the sense of sight and reduced to the use of the other space-senses must indeed be different from our own." But he continues: "The existence of the striking disparities between our visual and our other space-perceptions without confusing us, and, indeed, without usually being noticed, can only be explained by the tendency to interpret all dimensions into their visual equivalents." But this author gives no reasons for saying ' visual ' rather than ' tactile ;' and I must continue to think that probabilities point the other way so far as what we call real magnitudes are concerned. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 181 It will have been noticed in the account given that when two sensorial space-impressions, believed, to come from the same object, differ, then THE ONE MOST INTERESTING, practically or aesthetically, is JUDGED TO BE THE TRUE ONE. This law of interest holds throughout — though a permanent interest, like that of touch, may resist a strong but fleeting one like that of pain, as in the case just given of the felon. 3. The Summation of the Sense-spaces. Now for the next step in our construction of real space : How are the various sense-spaces added together into a consolidated and unitary continuum ? For they are, in man at all events, incoherent at the start. Here again the first fact that appears is that primitively our space-experiences form a chaos, out of which we have no immediate faculty for extricating them. Objects of different sense-organs, experienced together, do not in the first instance appear either inside or alongside or far outside of each other, neither spatially continuous nor discontinuous, in any definite sense of these words. The same thing is almost as true of objects felt by different parts of the same organ before discrimination has done its finished work. The most we «an say is that all our space-experiences together form an objective total and that this objective total is vast. Even now the space inside our mouth, which is so inti mately known and accurately measured by its inhabitant the tongue, can hardly be said to have its internal direc tions and dimensions known in any exact relation to those of the larger world outside. It forms almost a little world by itself. Again, when the dentist excavates a small cavity in one of our teeth, we feel the hard point of his instrument scraping, in distinctly differing directions, a surface which seems to our sensibility vaguely larger than the subsequent use of the mirror tells us it ' really ' is. And though the directions of the scraping differ so completely inter se, not one of them can be identified with the particular direction in the outer world to which it corresponds. The space of the tooth-sensibility is thus really a little world by itself, which can only become congruent with the outer space- 182 PSYCHOLOGY. world by farther experiences which shall alter its bulk, identify its directions, fuse its margins, and finally imbed it as a definite part within a definite whole. And even though every joint's rotations should be felt to vary inter se as so many differences of direction in a common room ; even though the same were true of diverse tracings on the skin, and of diverse tracings on the retina respectively, it would still not follow that feelings of direction, on these different surfaces, are intuitively comparable among each other, or with the other directions yielded by the feelings of the semi-circular canals. It would not follow that we should immediately judge the relations of them all to each other in one space-world. If with the arms in an unnatural attitude we ' feel ' things, we are perplexed about their shape, size, and position. Let the reader lie on his back with his arms stretched above his head, and it will astonish him to find how ill able he is to recognize the geometrical relations of objects placed within reach of his hands. But the geomet rical relations here spoken of are nothing but identities recognized between the directions and sizes perceived in this way and those perceived in the more usual ways. The two ways do not fit each other intuitively. How lax the connection between the system of visual and the system of tactile directions is in man, appears from the facility with which microscopists learn to reverse the move ments of their hand in manipulating things on the stage of the instrument. To move the slide to the seen left they must draw it to ihefelt right. But in a very few days the habit becomes a second nature. So in tying our cravat, shaving before a mirror, etc., the right and left sides are inverted, and the directions of our hand movements are the opposite of what they seem. Yet this never annoys us. Only when by accident we try to tie the cravat of another person do we learn that there are two ways of combining sight and touch perceptions. Let any one try for the first time to write or draw while looking at the image of his hand and paper in a mirror, and he will be utterly bewil dered. But a very short training will teach him to undo in this respect the associations of his previous lifetime. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 183 Prisms show this in an even more striking way. If the eyes be armed with spectacles containing slightly prismatic glasses with their bases turned, for example, towards the right, every object looked at will be apparently translocated to the left ; and the hand put forth to grasp any such object will make the mistake of passing beyond it on the left side. But less than an hour of practice in wearing such spectacles rectifies the judgment so that no more mistakes are made. In fact the new-formed associations are already so strong, that when the prisms are first laid aside again the opposite error is committed, the habits of a lifetime violated, and the hand now passed to the right of every object which it seeks to touch. The primitive chaos thus subsists to a great degree through life so far as our immediate sensibility goes. We feel our various objects and their bignesses, together or in succession ; but so soon as it is a question of the order and relations of many of them at once our intuitive apprehension remains to the very end most vague and incomplete. Whilst we are attending to one, or at most to two or three objects, all the others lapse, and the most we feel of them is that they still linger on the outskirts and can be caught again by turning in a certain way. Nevertheless throughout all this confusion we conceive of a world spread out in a perfectly fixed and orderly fashion, and we believe in its existence. The question is : How do this conception and this belief arise ? How is the chaos smoothed and straightened out ? Mainly by two operations : Some of the experiences are apprehended to exist out- and alongside of each other, and others are apprehended to interpenetrate each other, and to occupy the same room. In this way what was incoherent and irrelative ends by being coherent and definitely related ; nor is it hard to trace the principles, by which the mind is guided in this arrangement of its perceptions, in detail. In the first place, following the great intellectual law of economy, we simplify, unify, and identify as much as we possibly can. Whatever sensible data can be attended to together we locate together. Their several extents seem one extent. The place at which each appears is held to be the same with the place 184 PSYCHOLOGY. at which the others appear. They become, in short, so many properties of ONE AND THE SAME EEAL THING. This is the first and great commandment, the fundamental ' act ' by which our world gets spatially arranged. In this coalescence in a ' thing,' one of the coalescing sensations is held to be the thing, the other sensations are taken for its more or less accidental properties, or modes of appearance.* The sensation chosen to be the thing essen tially is the most constant and practically important of the lot ; most often it is hardness or weight. But the hardness or weight is never without tactile bulk ; and as we can always see something in our hand when we feel something there, we equate the bulk felt with the bulk seen, and thence forward this common bulk is also apt to figure as of the essence of the ' thing.' Frequently a shape so figures, sometimes a temperature, a taste, etc. ; but for the most part temperature, smell, sound, color, or whatever other phenom ena may vividly impress us simultaneously with the bulk felt or seen, figure among the accidents. Smell and sound impress us, it is true, when we neither see nor touch the thing ; but they are strongest when we see or touch, so we locate the source of these properties within the touched or seen space, whilst the properties themselves we regard as overflowing in a weakened form into the spaces filled by other things. In all this, it will be observed, the sense-data whose spaces coalesce into one are yielded by different sense- organs. Such data have no tendency to displace each other from consciousness, but can be attended to together all at once. Often indeed they vary concomitantly and reach a maximum together. We may be sure, therefore, that the general rule of our mind is to locate IN each other all sensa tions which are associated in simultaneous experience, and do not interfere with each other's perception. t * Cf. Lipps on ' Complication, ' Grundtatsachen, etc., p. 579. f Ventriloquism shows this very prettily. The ventriloquist talks with out moving his lips, and at the same time draws our attention to a doll, a box, or some other object. We forthwith locate the voice within this object. On the stage an actor ignorant of music sometimes has to sing, or play on the guitar or violin. He goes through the motions before our eyes, whilst in the orchestra or elsewhere the music is performed. But because as we listen we see the actor, it is almost impossible not to hear the music as if coming from where he sits or stands. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 185 Different impressions on the same sense-organ do interfere with each other's perception, and cannot well be attended to at once. Hence we do not locate them in each other's spaces, but arrange them in a serial order of exteriority, each alongside of the rest, in a space larger than that which any one sensation brings. This larger space, however, is an object of concep tion rather than of direct intuition, and bears all the marks of being constructed piecemeal by the mind. The blind man forms it out of tactile, locomotor, and auditory experi ences, the seeing man out of visual ones almost exclusively. As the visual construction is the easiest to understand, let us consider that first. Every single visual sensation or ' field of view ' is limited. To get a new field of view for our object the old one must disappear. But the disappearance may be only partial. Let the first field of view be A B C. If we carry our attention to the limit C, it ceases to be the limit, and becomes the centre of the field, and beyond it appear fresh parts where there were none before : * ABC changes, in short, to C D E. But although the parts A B are lost to sight, yet their image abides in the memory ; and if we think of our first object A B C as having existed or as still existing at all, we must think of it as it was originally presented, namely, as spread out from C in one direction just as C D E is spread out in another. A B and D E can never coalesce in one place (as they could were they objects of different senses) because they can never be perceived at once : we must lose one to see the other. So (the letters standing now for ' things ') we get to conceive of the successive fields of things after the analogy of the several things which we /\ Q perceive in a single field. They must be out- and along side of each other, and we conceive that their juxtaposed spaces must make a larger space. A B C -f- C D E must, in short, be imagined to exist in the form of A B C D E or not imagined at all. We can usually recover anything lost from sight by moving our attention and our eyes back in its direction ; and * Cf. Slmiid, in Mind, xm. 340. 186 PSYCHOLOGY. through these constant changes every field of seen things comes at last to be thought of as always having a fringe of other things possible to be seen spreading in all directions round about it. Meanwhile the movements concomitantly with which the various fields alternate are also felt and re membered ; and gradually (through association) this aud that movement come in our thought to suggest this or that extent of fresh objects introduced. Gradually, too, since the objects vary indefinitely in kind, we abstract from their several natures and think separately of their mere extents, of which extents the various movements remain as the only constant introducers and associates. More and more, therefore, do we think of movement and seen extent as mutually involving each other, until at last (with Bain and J. S. Mill) we may get to regard them as synonymous, and say, " What is the meaning of the word extent, unless it be possible movement?"* We forget in this conclusion that (whatever intrinsic extensiveness the movements may appear endowed with), that seen spreadoutness which is the pattern of the abstract extensiveness which we imagine came to us originally from the retinal sensation. The muscular sensations of the eyeball signify this sort of visible spreadoutness, just as this visible spreadoutness may come in later experience to signify the ' real ' bulks, distances, lengths and breadths known to touch and loco motion, t To the very end, however, in us seeing men, the quality, the nature, the sort of thing we mean by exten siveness, would seem to be the sort of feeling which our re tinal stimulations bring. In one deprived of sight the principles by which the notion of real space is constructed are the same. Skin- feelings take in him the place of retinal feelings in giving * See, e.g., Bain's Senses and Intellect, pp. 366-7, 371. f When, for example, a baby looks at Its own moving hand, it sees one object at the same time that it feels another. Both interest its attention, and it locates them together. But the felt object's size is the I more constant size, just as the felt object is, on the whole, the more in teresting and important object ; and so the retinal sensations become re- j garded as its signs and have their 'real space- values ' interpreted in] tangible terms. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 187 the quality of lateral spreadoutness, as our attention passes from one extent of them to another, awakened by an object sliding along. Usually the moving object is our hand ; and feelings of movement in our joints invariably accom pany the feelings in the skin. But the feeling of the skin is what the blind man means by his skin ; so the size of the skin-feelings stands as the absolute or real size, and the size of the joint-feelings becomes a sign of these. Suppose, for example, a blind baby with (to make the description shorter) a blister on his toe, exploring his leg with his finger-tip and feeling a pain shoot up sharply the instant the blister is touched. The experiment gives him four different kinds of sensation — two of them protracted, two sudden. The first pair are the movement-feeling in the joints of the upper limb, and the movement-feeling on the skin of the leg and foot. These, attended to together, have their extents identified as one objective space the hand moves through the same space in which the leg lies. The second pair of objects are the pain in the blister, and the peculiar feeling the blister gives to the finger. Their spaces also fuse ; and as each marks the end of a peculiar movement-series (arm moved, leg stroked), the movement-spaces are emphatically identified with each other at that end. Were there other small blisters dis tributed down the leg, there would be a number of these emphatic points ; the movement-spaces would be iden tified, not only as totals, but point for point. * *The incoherence of the different primordial sense-spaces inter »e is often made a pretext for denying to the primitive bodily feelings any spatial quality at all. Nothing is commoner than to hear it said : "Babies have originally no spatial perception ; for when a baby's toe aches he does not place the pain in the toe. He makes no definite movements of defence, and may be vaccinated without being held." The facts are true enough ; but the interpretation is all wrong. What really happens is that the baby does not place his ' toe ' in the pain ; for he knows nothing of his ' toe ' as yet. He has not attended to it as a visual object ; he has not handled it with his fingers ; nor have its normal organic sensations or contacts vet become interesting enough to be discriminated from the whole massive feeling of the foot, or even of the leg to which it belongs. In short, the toe is neither a member of the babe's optical space, of his hand-movement space, nor an independent member of his leg-and-foot space. It has ac tually no mental existence yet save as this little pain-space. What wonder, 188 PSYCHOLOGY. Just so with spaces beyond the body's limits. Continu ing the joint-feeling beyond the toe, the baby hits another object, which he can still think of when he brings his hand back to its blister again. That object at the end of that joint-feeling means a new place for him, and the more such objects multiply in his experience the wider does the space of his conception grow. If, wandering through the woods to-day by a new path, I find myself suddenly in a glade which affects my senses exactly as did another I reachedx last week at the end of a different walk, I believe the two! Identical affections to present the same persisting glade, \ and infer that I have attained it by two differing roads. The spaces walked over grow congruent by their extremi ties ; though apart from the common sensation which those extremities give me, I should be under no necessity of con necting one walk with another at all. The case in no whit differs when shorter movements are concerned. If, moving first one arm and then another, the blind child gets the same kind of sensation upon the hand, and gets it again as often as he repeats either process, he judges that he has touched the same object by both motions, and concludes that the motions terminate in a common place. From place to place marked in this way he moves, and adding the places moved through, one to another, he builds up his no tion of the extent of the outer world. The seeing man's process is identical ; only his units, which may be succes sive bird's-eye views, are much larger than in the case of the blind. then, if the pain seem a little space-world all by itself? But let the pain once associate itself with these other space -worlds, and its space will be come part of their space. Let the baby feel the nurse stroking the limb and awakening the pain every time her finger passes towards the toe ; let him look on and see her finger on the toe every time the pain shoots up ; let him handle his foot himself and get the pain whenever the toe comes into his fingers or his mouth ; let moving the leg exacerbate the pain, — and all is changed. The space of the pain becomes identified with that part of each of the other spaces which gets felt when it awakens ; and by their identity with it these parts are identified with each other, and grow systematically connected as members of a larger extensive whole. TEE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 189 FEELINGS IN JOINTS AND FEELINGS IN MUSCLES. 1. Feelings of Movement in Joints. I have been led to speak of feelings which arise in joints. As these feelings have been too much neglected in Psychology hitherto, in entering now somewhat minutely into their study I shall probably at the same time freshen the interest of the reader, which under the rather dry ab stractions of the previous pages may presumably have flagged. When, by simply flexing my right forefinger on its meta- carpal joint, I trace with its tip an inch on the palm of my left hand, is my feeling of the size of the inch purely and simply a feeling in the skin of the palm, or have the mus cular contractions of the right hand and forearm anything to do with it ? In the preceding pages I have constantly assumed spatial sensibility to be an affair of surfaces. At first starting, the consideration of the ' muscular sense ' as a space-measurer was postponed to a later stage. Many writers, of whom the foremost was Tli^m&sjirown, in his Lectures on the Philosophy of the Human Mind, and of whom the latest is no less a Psychologist than Prof. Delboeuf,* hold that the consciousness of active muscular motion,!) aware of its own amount, is the fons et origo of all spatiaM measurement. It would seem to follow, if this theory were true, that two skin-feelings, one of a large patch, one of a small one, possess their difference of spatiality, not as an immediate element, but solely by virtue of the fact that the large one, to get its points successively excited, demands more muscular contraction than the small one does. Fixed associations with the several amounts of muscular contrac tion required in this particular experience would thus ex- *'Pourquoi les Sensations visuelles sont elles etendues?' in Revue Philosophique, iv. 167. — As the proofs of this chapter are being corrected, I receive the third ' Heft ' of Miinsterberg's Beitra'ge zur Experimentellen. Psychologic, in which that vigorous young psychologist reaffirms (if I understand him after so hasty a glance) more radically than ever the doc trine that muscular sensation proper is our one means of measuring exten sion. Unable to reopen the discussion here, I am in duty bound to call the attention of the reader to Herr M.'s work. 190 PSYCHOLOGY. plain the apparent sizes of the skin-patches, which sizes would consequently not be primitive data but derivative re sults. It seems to me that no evidence of the muscular measure ments in question exists; but that all the facts may be ex plained by surface-sensibility, provided we take that of the joint-surfaces also into account. The most striking argument, and the most obvious one, which an upholder of the muscular theory is likely to pro duce is undoubtedly this fact : if, with closed eyes, we trace figures in the air with the extended forefinger (the motions may occur from the metacarpal-, the wrist-, the elbow-, or the shoulder-joint indifferently), what we are conscious of in each case, and indeed most acutely conscious of, is the geometric path described by the finger-^. Its angles, its subdivisions, are all as distinctly felt as if seen by the eye ; and yet the surface of the finger-tip receives no impression at all.* But with each variation of the figure, the muscular contractions vary, and so do the feelings which these yield. Are not these latter the sens.ible data that make us aware of the lengths and directions we discern in the traced line ? Should we be tempted to object to this supposition of the advocate of perception by muscular feelings, that we have learned the spatial significance of these feelings by reiterated experiences of seeing what figure is drawn when each special muscular grouping is felt, so that in the last resort the muscular space feelings would be derived from retinal- surf ace feelings, our opponent might immediately hush us by pointing to the fact that in persons born blind the phenomenon in question is even more perfect than ir ourselves. If we suggest that the blind may have originally traced the figures on the cutaneous surface of cheek, thigh, or palm, and may now remember the specific figure which each pres ent movement formerly caused the skin- surf ace to per ceive, he may reply that the delicacy of the motor percep- * Even if the figure be drawn on a board instead of in the air, the vari ations of contact on the finger's surface will be much simpler than the pe culiarities of the traced figure itself. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 191 tion far exceeds that of most of the cutaneous surfaces ; that, in fact, we can feel a figure traced only in its differen tials, so to speak, — a figure which we merely start to trace by our finger-tip, a figure which, traced in the same way on our finger-tip by the hand of another, is almost if not wholly unrecognizable. The champion of the muscular sense seems likely to be triumphant until we invoke the articular cartilages, as in ternal surfaces whose sensibility is called in play by every movement we make, however delicate the latter may be. To establish the part they play in our geometrizing, it is necessary to review a few facts. It has long been known by medical practitioners that, in patients with cutaneous anaesthesia of a limb, whose muscles also are insensible to the thrill of the faradic current, a very accurate sense of the way in which the limb may be flexed or extended by the hand of another may be preserved.* On the other hand, we may have this sense of movement impaired when the tac tile sensibility is well preserved. That the pretended feeling of outgoing innervation can play in these cases no part, is obvious from the fact that the movements by which the limb changes its position are passive ones, imprinted on it by the experimenting physician. The writers who have sought a rationale of the matter have consequently been driven by way of exclusion to assume the articular surfaces to be the seat of the perception in question, f That the joint-surfaces are sensitive appears evident from the fact that in inflammation they become the seat of excru ciating pains, and from the perception by everyone who lifts weights or presses against resistance, that every in crease of the force opposing him betrays itself to his con sciousness principally by the starting-out of new feelings or the increase of old ones, in or about the joints. If the structure and mode of mutual application of two articular surfaces be taken into account, it will appear that, granting the surfaces to be sensitive, no more favorable mechanical * See for example Duchenne, Electrisation localised, pp. 727, 770, Ley- den; Virchow's Archiv, Bd. XLVII. (1869). t E.g., Eulenburg, Lehrb. d. Nervenkrankheiten (Berlin), 1878, i. 3. 192 PSYCHOLOGY. conditions could be possible for the delicate calling of the sensibility into play than are realized in the minutely grad uated rotations and firmly resisted variations of pressure involved in every act of extension or flexion. Nevertheless it is a great pity that we have as yet no direct testimony, no expressions from patients with healthy joints accident ally laid open, of the impressions they experience when the cartilage is pressed or rubbed. The first approach to direct evidence, so far as I know, is contained in the paper of Lewinski,* published in 1879. This observer had a patient the inner half of whose leg was anaesthetic. When this patient stood up, he had a curious illusion about the position of his limb, which dis appeared the moment he lay down again : he thought him self knock-kneed. If, as Lewinski says, we assume the inner half of the joint to share the insensibility of the corre sponding part of the skin, then he ought to feel, when the joint-surfaces pressed agamsi each other in the act of standing, the outer half of the joint most strongly. But this is the feeling he would also get whenever it was by any chance sought to force his leg into a knock-kneed attitude. Lewinski was led by this case to examine the feet of cer tain ataxic patients with imperfect sense of position. He found in every instance that when the toes were flexed and draivn upon at the same time (the joint-surfaces drawn asunder) all sense of the amount of flexion disappeared. On the contrary, when he pressed a toe in, whilst flexing it, the patient's appreciation of the amount of flexion was much improved, evidently because the artificial increase of articular pressure made up for the pathological insensibil ity of the parts. Since Lewinski's paper an important experimental re search by A. Goldscheider f has appeared, which completely establishes our point. This patient observer caused his fingers, arms, and legs to be passively rotated upon their various joints in a mechanical apparatus which registered both the velocity of movement impressed and the amount * ' Ueber den Kraftsinn/ Virchow's Archiv, Bd. LXXVII. 134. f Archiv f. (Anat. u) Physiologic (1889), pp. 369, 540. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 193 of angular rotation. No active muscular contraction took place. The minimal felt amounts of rotation were in all cases surprisingly small, being much less than a single angular de gree in all the joints except those of the fingers. Such dis placements as these, the author says (p. 490), can hardly be detected by the eye. The point of application of the force which rotated the limb made no difference in the result. Kotations round the hip- joint, for example, were as deli cately felt when the leg was hung by the heel as when it was hung by the thigh whilst the movements were per formed. Anaesthesia of the skin produced by induction-cur rents also had no disturbing effect on the perception, nor did the various degrees of pressure of the moving force upon the skin affect it. It became, in fact, all the more distinct in proportion as the concomitant pressure-feelings were eliminated by artificial anaesthesia. When the joints themselves, however, were made artificially anaesthetic the perception of the movement grew obtuse and the angular rotations had to be much increased before they were per ceptible. All these facts prove according to Herr Gold- scheider, that the joint surfaces and these alone are the start ing point of the impressions by ivhich the movements of our members are immediately perceived. Applying this result, which seems invulnerable, to the case of the tracing finger-tip, we see that our perception of the latter gives no countenance to the theory of the mus cular sense. We indubitably localize the finger-tip at the suc cessive points of its path by means of the sensations which we receive from our joints. But if this is so, it may be asked, why do we feel the figure to be traced, not within the joint itself, but in such an altogether different place ? And why do we feel it so much larger than it really is ? I will answer these questions by asking another : Why do we move our joints at all ? Surely to gain something more valuable than the insipid joint-feelings themselves. And these more interesting feelings are in the main pro duced upon the skin of the moving part, or of some other part over which it passes, or upon the eye. With move ments of the fingers we explore the configuration of all real objects with which we have to deal, our own body as well as 194 PSYCHOLOGY. foreign things. Nothing that interests us is located in the joint ; everything that interests us either is some part of our skin, or is something that we see as we handle it. The cutaneously felt and the seen extents come thus to figure as the important things for us to concern ourselves with. Every time the joint moves, even though we neither see, nor feel cutaneously, the reminiscence of skin-events and sights which formerly coincided with that extent of move ment, ideally awaken as the movement's import, and the mind drops the present sign to attend to the import alone. The joint-sensation itself, as such, does not disappear in the process. A little attention easily detects it, with all its fine peculiarities, hidden beneath its vaster suggestions ; so that really the mind has two space-perceptions before it, congruent in form but different in scale and place, either of which exclusively it may notice, or both at once, — the joint-space which it feels and the real space which it means. The joint-spaces serve so admirably as signs because of their capacity for parallel variation to all the peculiarities of external motion. There is not a direction in the real world nor a ratio of distance which cannot be matched by some direction or extent of joint-rotation. Joint- feelings, like all feelings, are roomy. Specific ones are contrasted inter se as different directions are contrasted within the same extent. If I extend my arm straight ont at the shoulder, the rotation of the shoulder- joint will give me one feeling of movement ; if then I sweep the arm forward, the same joint will give me another feeling of movement. Both these movements are felt to happen in space, and differ in specific quality. Why shall not the specificness of the quality just consist in the feeling of a peculiar direc tion ? * Why may not the several joint-feelings be so many perceptions of movement in so many different directions ? That we cannot explain why they should is no presumption that they do not, for we never can explain why any sense- organ should awaken the sensation it does. * Direction in its ' first intention,' of course ; direction with which so far we merely become acquainted, and about which we know nothing save perhaps its difference from another direction a moment ago experienced in the same way ! THE PKRCEPTTON OF SPACE. 195 But if the joint-feelings are directions and extents, standing in relation to each other, the task of association in interpreting their import in eye- or skin-terms is a good deal simplified. Let the movement be, of a certain joint, derive its absolute space-value from the cutaneous feeling it is always capable of engendering ; then the longer movement jbcd of the same joint will be judged to have a greater space-value, even though it may never have wholly merged with a skin-experience. So of differences of direction : so much joint- difference = so much skin-difference ; therefore, more joint-difference = more skin-difference. In fact, the joint-feeling can excellently serve as a map on a reduced scale, of a reality which the imagination can identify at its pleasure with this or that sensible extension simultaneously knoivn in some other way. When the joint-feeling in itself acquires an emotional interest, — which happens whenever the joint is inflamed and painful, — the secondary suggestions fail to arise, and the movement is felt where it is, and in its intrinsic scale oi magnitude.* The localization of the joint-feeling in a space simulta neously known otherwise (i.e. to eye or skin), is what is commonly called the extradition or eccentric projection of the feeling. In the preceding chapter I said a good deal on this subject ; but we must now see a little more closely just what happens in this instance of it. The content of the joint- fueling, to begin with, is an object, and is in itself a place. I >r it to be placed, say in the elbow, the elbow as seen or han- dlea must already have become another object for the mind, * I have said hardly anything about associations with visual space in the foregoing account, because I wished to represent a process which the blind and the seeing man might equally share. It is to be noticed that the space suggested to the imagination when the joint moves, and pro jected to the distance of the finger-tip, is not represented as any specific skin-tract. What the seeing man imagines is a visible path; what the blind man imagines is rather a generic image, an abstraction from many skin- spaces whose local signs have neutralized each other, and left nothing but their common vastness behind. We shall see as we go on that this generic abstraction of space-magnitude from the various local peculiarities of feel ing which accompanied it when it was for the first time felt, occurs on a considerable scale in the acquired perceptions of blind as well as of seeing men. 196 PSYCHOLOGY. and with its place as thus known, the place which the joint- feeling fills must coalesce. That the latter should be felt ' in the elbow ' is therefore a ' projection ' of it into the place of another object as much as its being felt in the finger-tip or at the end of a cane can be. But when we say ' projec tion ' we generally have in our mind the notion of a there as contrasted with a here. What is the here when we say that the joint-feeling is there ? The ' here ' seems to be the spot which the mind has chosen for its own post of observation, usually some place within the head, but sometimes within the throat or breast — not a rigorously fixed spot, but a region from any portion of which it may send forth its vari ous acts of attention. Extradition from either of these regions is the common law under which we perceive the whereabouts of the north star, of our own voice, of the con tact of our teeth with each other, of the tip of our finger, of the point of our cane on the ground, or of a movement in our elbow- joint. But for the distance betiveen the ' here ' and the ' there ' to be felt, the entire intervening space must be itself an object of per ception. The consciousness of this intervening space is the sine qua non of the joint-feeling's projection to the farther end of it. When it is filled by our own bodily tissues (as where the projection only goes as far as the elbow or fin ger-tip) we are sensible of its extent alike by our eye, by our exploring movements, and by the resident sensations which fill its length. When it reaches beyond the limits of our body, the resident sensations are lacking, but limbs and hand and eye suffice to make it known. Let me, for example, locate a feeling of motion coming from my elbow- joint in the point of my cane a yard beyond my hand. Either I see this yard as I flourish the cane, and the seen end of it then absorbs my sensation just as my seen elbow might absorb it, or I am blind and imagine the cane as an object continuing my arm, either because I have explored both arm and cane with the other hand, or because I have pressed them both along my body and leg. If I project my joint-feeling farther still, it is by a conception rather than a distinct imagination of the space. I think: ' farther,' ' thrice as far/ etc.; and thus get a symbolic image of a distant THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 197 patli at which I point. * But the * absorption ' of the joint- feeling by the distant spot, in whatever terms the latter may be apprehended, is never anything but that coales cence into one 'thing' already spoken of on page 184, of whatever different sensible objects interest our attention at once. 2. feelings of Muscular Contraction. Readers versed in psychological literature will have missed, in our account thus far, the usual invocation of 'the muscular sense.' This word is used with extreme vagueness to cover all resident sensations, whether of motion or position, in our members, and even to designate the supposed feeling of efferent discharge from the brain. We shall later see good reason to deny the existence of the latter feeling. We have accounted for the better part at least of the resident feelings of motion in limbs by the sensibility of the articular surfaces. The skin and ligaments also must have feelings awakened as they are stretched or squeezed in flexion or extension. And I am inclined to think that the sensations of our contracting muscles themselves probably play ve follow a moving object with our gaze, the motion is ' volun tary ' ; when our eyes oscillate to and fro after we have made ourselves dizzy by spinning around, it is ' reflex ' ; and when the eyeball is pushed with the finger, it is ' pas sive.' Now, in all three of these cases we get a feeling from the movement as it effects itself. But the objective perceptions to which the feeling assists us are by no means the same. In the first case we may see a stationary field of view with one moving object in it ; in the second, the total field swimming more or less steadily in one direction ; in the third, a sudden jump or twist of the same total field. The feelings of convergence of the eyeballs permit of the same ambiguous interpretation. When objects are near we converge strongly upon them in order to see them ; when far, we set our optic axes parallel. But the exact degree of convergence fails to be felt ; or rather, being felt, fails to tell us the absolute distance of the object we are regarding. Wheatstone arranged his stereoscope in such a way that the size of the retinal images might change without the con vergence altering ; or conversely, the convergence might change without the retinal image altering. Under these circumstances, he says,t the object seemed to approach or recede in the first case, without altering its size , in the second, to change its size without altering its distance — just * A. W. Volkmaun, Uiitersuckungen, p. 253. f Philosophical Transactions, 1852, p. 4. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 235 the reverse of what might have been expected. Wheatstone adds, however, that ' fixing the attention ' converted each of these perceptions into its opposite. The same perplexity occurs in looking through prismatic glasses, which alter the eyes' convergence. We cannot decide whether the object has come nearer, or grown larger, or both, or neither ; and our judgment vacillates in the most surprising way. We may even make our eyes diverge, and the object will none the less appear at a finite distance. When we look through the stereoscope, the picture seems at no determinate dis tance. These and other facts have led Helmholtz to deny that the feeling of convergence has any very exact value as a distance-measurer.* With the feelings of accommodation it is very much the same. Donders has shown t that the apparent magnifying power of spectacles of moderate convexity hardly depends at all upon their enlargement of the retinal image, but rather oil the relaxation they permit of the muscle of accommoda tion. This suggests an object farther off, and consequently a much larger one, since its retinal size rather increases than diminishes. But in this case the same vacillation of judgment as in the previously mentioned case of converg ence takes place. The recession made the object seem larger, but the apparent growth in size of the object now makes it look as if it came nearer instead of receding. The effect thus contradicts its own cause. Everyone is conscious, on first putting on a pair of spectacles, of a doubt whether the field of view draws near or retreats.:); There is still another deception, occurring in persons ivho have had one eye-muscle suddenly paralyzed. This deception * Physiol. Optik, 649-664. Later this author is led to value converg ence more highly. Arch. f. (Anat. u.) Physiol. (1878), p. 322. f Anomalies of Accommodation and Refraction (New Sydenham Soc. Transl., London, 1864), p. 155. | These strange contradictions have been called by Aubert ' secondary ' deceptions of judgment. See Grundziige d. Physiologischeu Optik (Leip zig, 1876), pp. 601, 615, 627. One of the best examples of them is the small size of the moon as first seen through a telescope. It is larger and brighter, so we see its details more distinctly and judge it nearer. But because we judge it so much nearer we think it must have grown smaller. Cf. Char- pentier in Jahresbericht, x. 430. 236 PSYCHOLOGY. has led Wundt to affirm that the eyeball-feeling proper, the incoming sensation of effected rotation, tells us only of the direction of our eye-movements, but not of their whole ex tent.* For this reason, and because not only Wundt, but many other authors, think the phenomena in these partial paralyses demonstrate the existence of a feeling of innerva tion, a feeling of the outgoing nervous current, opposed to every afferent sensation whatever, it seems proper to note the facts with a certain degree of detail. Suppose a man wakes up some morning with the exter nal rectus muscle of his right eye half paralyzed, what will be the result ? He will be enabled only with great effort to rotate the eye so as to look at objects lying far off to the right. Something in the effort he makes will make him feel as if the object lay much farther to the right than it really is. If the left and sound eye be closed, and he be asked to touch rapidly with his finger an object situated towards his right, he will point the finger to the right of it. T4ie current explanation of the ' something ' in the effort which causes this deception is that it is the sensation of the out going discharge from the nervous centres, the ' feeling of innervation,' to use Wundt's expression, requisite for bring ing the open eye with its weakened muscle to bear upon the object to be touched. If that object be situated 20 degrees to the right, the patient has now to innervate as powerfully to turn the eye those 20 degrees as formerly he did to turn the eye 30 degrees. He consequently believes as before that he has turned it 30 degrees ; until, by a newly-acquired custom, he learns the altered spatial import of all the discharges his brain makes into his right abducens nerve. The ' feeling of innervation,' maintained to exist by this and other observations, plays an immense part in the space-theories of certain philosophers, especial ly Wundt. I shall elsewhere try to show that the observa tions by no means warrant the conclusions drawn from them, and that the feeling in question is probably a wholly fictitious entity. t Meanwhile it suffices to point out that even those who set most store by it are compelled, by the * Revue Philosophique, in. 9, p. 220. f See Chapter XXIV. TEE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 237 readiness with which the translocation of the field of view becomes corrected and further errors avoided, to admit that the precise space-import of the supposed sensation of outgoing energy is as ambiguous and indeterminate as that of any other of the eye-feelings we have considered hitherto. I have now given what no one will call an understate ment of the facts and arguments by which it is sought to banish the credit of directly revealing space from each and every kind of eye-sensation taken by itself. The reader will confess that they make a very plausible show, and most likely wonder whether my own theory of the matter can rally from their damaging evidence. But the case is far from being hopeless ; and the introduction of a discrimi nation hitherto unmade will, if I mistake not, easily vindi cate the view adopted in these pages, whilst at the same time it makes ungrudging allowance for all the ambiguity and illusion on which so much stress is laid by the advo cates of the intellectualist-theory. The Choice of the Visual Reality. We have native and fixed optical space-sensations ; but experience leads us to select certain ones from among them to be the exclusive bearers of reality : the rest become mere signs and suggesters of these. The factor of selection, on which we have already laid so much stress, here as elsewhere is the solving word of the enigma. If Helmholtz, Wundt, and the rest, with an ambiguous retinal sensation before them, meaning now one size and distance, and now another, had not con tented themselves with merely saying : — The size and dis tance are not this sensation, they are something beyond it which it merely calls up, and whose own birthplace is afar —in ' synthesis ' (Wundt) or in ' experience ' (Helmholtz) as the case may be ; if they had gone on definitely to ask and definitely to answer the question, What are the size and distance in their proper selves ? they would not only have escaped the present deplorable vagueness of their space- theories, but they woul'd have seen that the objective spatial attributes ' signified ' are simply and solely certain 238 PS TCEOL OOT. otJier optical sensations noiu absent, but which the present sensations suggest. What, for example, is the slant-legged cross which we think we see on the wall when we project the rectangular after-image high up towards our right or left (Figs. 58 and 59) ? Is it not in very sooth a retinal sensation itself ? An imagined sensation, not a felt one, it is true, but none the less essentially and originally sensational or retinal for that, the sensation, namely, which we should receive if a ' real ' slant-legged cross stood on the wall in front of us and threw its image on our eye. That image is not the one our retina now holds. Our retina now holds the image which a cross of square shape throws when in front, but which a cross of the slant-legged pattern ivould throw, provided it were actually on the wall in the distant place at which we look. Call this actual retinal image the ' square ' image. The square image is then one of the innumerable images the slant-legged cross can throw. Why should another one, and that an absent one, of those innumerable images be picked out to represent exclusively the slant-legged cross's ' true ' shape ? Why should that absent and imagined slant-legged image displace the present and felt square image from our mind? Why, when the objective cross gives us so many shapes, as it varies its position, should we think we feel the true shape only when the cross is directly in front ? And when that question is answered, how can the absent and represented feeling of a slant-legged figure so successfully intrude itself into the place of a presented square one? Before answering either question, let us be doubly sure about our facts, and see how true it is that in our dealings with objects ive always do pick out one of the visual images they yield, to constitute the real form or size. The matter of size has been already touched upon, so that no more need be said of it here. As regards shape, almost all the retinal shapes that objects throw are perspec tive ' distortions.' Square table-tops constantly present two acute and two obtuse angles ; circles drawn on our wall papers, our carpets, or on sheets of paper, usually show like ellipses ; parallels approach as they recede ; human bodies THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 239 are foreshortened ; and the transitions from one to another of these altering forms are infinite and continual. Out of the flux, however, one phase always stands prominent. It is the form the object has when we see it easiest and best : and that is when our eyes and the object both are in what may be called the normal position. In this position our head is upright and our optic axes either parallel or sym metrically convergent ; the plane of the object is perpen dicular to the visual plane ; and if the object is one containing many lines it is turned so as to make them, as far as possible, either parallel or perpendicular to the visual plane. In this situation it is that we compare all shapes with each other ; here every exact measurement and decision is made.* It is very easy to see why the normal situation should have this extraordinary pre-eminence. First, it is the position in which we easiest hold anything we are examining in our hands ; second, it -is a turning-point between all right- and all left-hand perspective views of a given object ; third, it is the only position in which symmetrical figures seem sym metrical and equal angles seem equal ; fourth, it is often that starting-point of movements from which the eye is least troubled by axial rotations, by which superposition f of the retinal images of different lines and different parts of the same line is easiest produced, and consequently by which the eye can make the best comparative measure ments in its sweeps. All these merits single the normal position out to be chosen. No other point of view offers so many aesthetic and practical advantages. Here we be lieve we see the object as it is ; elsewhere, only as it seems. Experience and custom soon teach us, however, that the seeming appearance passes into the real one by continuous gradations. They teach us, moreover, that seeming and being may be strangely interchanged. Now a real circle may slide into a seeming ellipse ; now an ellipse may, by sliding in the same direction, become a seeming circle ; now * The only exception seems to be when we expressly wish to abstract from particulars, and to judge of the general 'effect.' Witness ladies trying on new dresses with their heads inclined and their eyes askance ; or painters in the same attitude judging of the ' values ' in their pictures. \ The importance of Superposition will appear later on. 240 PSYCHOLOGY. a rectangular cross grows slant-legged ; now a slant-legged one grows rectangular. Almost any form in oblique vision may be thus a deriva tive of almost any other in ' primary ' vision ; and we must learn, when we get one of the former appearances, to trans late it into the appropriate one of the ] attei °la AS ; we must learn of what optical 'reality ' ;s optical signs. Having learned this, we do but, obey cuai xu,w of economy or simplification which dominates our whole psychic life, when we attend exclusively to the ' reality ' and ignore as much as our consciousness will let us the ' sign ' by which we came to apprehend it. The signs of each probable real thing being multiple and the thing itself one and fixed, we gain the same mental relief by abandoning the former for the latter that we do when we abandon mental images, with all their fluctuating characters, for the definite and unchangeable names which they suggest. The selection of the several ' normal ' appearances from out of the jungle of our optical experiences, to serve as the real sights of which we shall think, is psychologically a parallel phenom enon to the habit of thinking in words, and has a like use. Both are substitutions of terms few and fixed for terms manifold and vague. Sensations which we Ignore. This service of sensations as mere signs, to be ignored when they have evoked the other sensations which are their significates, was noticed first by Berkeley and remarked in many passages, as the following : ' ' Signs, being little considered in themselves, or for their own sake, but only in their relative capacity and for the sake of those things whereof they are signs, it comes to pass that the mind overlooks them, so as to carry its attention immediately on to the things signified . . . which in truth and strictness are not seen, but only suggested and ap prehended by means of the proper objects of sight which alone are seen." (Divine Visual Language, § 12.) Berkeley of course erred in supposing that the thing suggested was not even originally an object of sight, as the sign now is which calls it up. Reid expressed Berkeley's principle in yet clearer language : " The visible appearances of objects are intended by nature only as signs or indications, and the mind passes instantly to the things sig- THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 241 nified, without making the least reflection upon the sign, or even per ceiving that there is any such thmg. . . . The mind has acquired aeon- firmed and inveterate habit of inattention to them (the signs). For they no sooner appear than, quick as lightning, the thing signified suc ceeds and engrosses all our regard. They have no name in language ; and although we are conscious of them when they pass through the mind, yet their passage is so quick and so familiar that it is absolutely unheeded ; nor do they leave any footsteps of themselves, either in the memory or imagination." (Inquiry, chap. v. §§ 2, 3.) If we review the facts we shall find every grade of non- attention between the extreme form of overlooking men tioned by Keid (or forms even more extreme still) and com plete conscious perception of the sensation present. Some times it is literally impossible to become aware of the latter. Sometimes a little artifice or effort easily leads us to discern it together, or in alternation, with the 'object' it reveals. Sometimes the present sensation is held to be the object or to reproduce its features in undistorted shape, and then, of course, it receives the mind's full glare. The deepest inattention is to subjective optical sensa tions, strictly so called, or those which are not signs of outer objects at all. Helmholtz's treatment of these phe nomena, muscce volitantes, negative after-images, double images, etc., is very satisfactory. He says : " We only attend with any ease and exactness to our sensations in so far forth as they can be utilized for the knowledge of outward things ; and we are accustomed to neglect all those portions of them which have no significance as regards the external world. So much is this the case that for the most part special artifices and practice are required for the observation of these latter more subjective feelings. Although it might seem that nothing should be easier than to be conscious of one's own sensations, experience nevertheless shows that often enough either a special talent like that showed in eminent degree by Purkinje, or acci dent or theoretic speculation, are necessary conditions for the discovery of subjective phenomena. Thus, for example, the blind spot on the retina was discovered by Mariotte by the theoretic way ; similarly by me the existence of ' summation '-tones in acoustics. In the majority of cases accident is what first led observers whose attention was espe cially exercised on subjective phenomena to discover this one or that ; only where the subjective appearances are so intense that they inter fere with the perception of objects are they noticed by all men alike. But if they have once been discovered it is for the most part easy for subsequent observers who place themselves in proper conditions and bend their attention in the right direction to perceive them. But in 242 PSYCHOLOGY. many cases — for example, in the phenomena of the blind spot, in the discrimination of over-tones and combination-tones from the ground- tone of musical sounds, etc. — such a strain of the attention is required, even with appropriate instrumental aids, that most persons fail. The very after-images of bright objects are by most men perceived only under exceptionally favorable conditions, and it takes steady practice to see the fainter images of this kind. It is a commonly recurring ex perience that persons smitten with some eye-disease which impairs vision suddenly remark for the first time the muscce volitantes which all through life their vitreous humor has contained, but which they now firmly believe to have arisen since their malady ; the truth being that the latter has only made them more observant of all their visual sensa tions. There are also cases where one eye has gradually grown blind, and the patient lived for an indefinite time without knowing it, until, through the accidental closure of the healthy eye alone, the blindness of the other was brought to attention. "Most people, when first made aware of binocular double images, are uncommonly astonished that they should never have noticed them before, although all through their life they had been in the habit of see ing singly only those few objects which were about equally distant with the point of fixation, and the rest, those nearer and farther, which con stitute the great majority, had always been double. "We must then learn to turn our attention to our particular sensa tions, and we learn this commonly only for such sensations as are means of cognition of the outer world. Only so far as they serve this end have our sensations any importance for us in ordinary life. Subjective feelings are mostly interesting only to scientific investigators ; were they remarked in the ordinary use of the senses, they could only cause disturbance. Whilst, therefore, we reach an extraordinary degree of firmness and security in objective observation, we not only do not reach this where subjective phenomena are concerned, but we actually attain in a high degree the faculty of overlooking these altogether, and keep ing ourselves independent of their influence in judging of objects, even in cases where their strength might lead them easily to attract our at tention." (Physiol. Optik, pp. 431-2.) Even where the sensation is not merely subjective, as in the cases of which Helmholtz speaks, but is a sign of some thing outward, we are also liable, as Reid says, to overlook its intrinsic quality and attend exclusively to the image of the * thing ' it suggests. But here everyone caw easily notice the sensation itself if he will. Usually we see a sheet of paper as uniformly white, although a part of it may be in shadow. But we can in an instant, if we please, notice the shadow as local color. A man walking towards us does not usually seem to alter his size ; but we can, by setting THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 243 our attention in a peculiar way make him appear to do so. The whole education of the artist consists in his learning to see the presented signs as well as the represented things. No matter what the field of view means, he sees it also as it feels — that is, as a collection of patches of color bounded by lines — the whole forming an optical diagram of whose intrinsic proportions one who is not an artist has hardly a conscious inkling. The ordinary man's attention passes over them to their import ; the artist's turns back and dwells upon them for their own sake. 'Don't draw the thing as it is, but as it looks / ' is the endless advice of every teacher to his pupil ; forgetting that what it ' is ' is what it would also ' look,' provided it were placed in what we have called the ' normal ' situation for vision. In this situation the sensation as ' sign ' and the sensation as ' object ' co alesce into one, and there is no contrast between them. Sensations which seem Suppressed. But a great difficulty has been made of certain peculiar cases which we must now turn to consider. They are cases in which a present sensation, whose existence is supposed to be proved by its outward conditions being there, seems absolutely suppressed or changed by the image of the ' thing ' it suggests. This matter carries us back to what was said on p. 218. The passage there quoted from Helmholtz refers to these cases. He thinks they conclusively disprove the original and intrinsic spatiality of any of our retinal sensations ; for if such a one, actually present, had an immanent and essential space-determination of its own, that might well be added to and overlaid or even momentarily eclipsed by suggestions of its signification, but how could it possibly be altered or completely suppressed thereby ? Of actually present sensations, he says, being suppressed by suggestions of experience— " We have not a single well-attested example. In all those illusions which are provoked by sensations in the absence of their usually excit ing objects, the mistake never vanishes by the better understanding of the object really present, and by insight into the cause of deception. Phosphenes provoked by pressure on the eyeball, by traction on the en trance of the optic nerve, after-images, etc., remain projected into their apparent place in the field of vision, just as the image projected from 244 PSYCHOLOGY. a mirror's surface continues to be seen behind the mirror, although we know that to all these appearances no outward reality corresponds. True enough, we can remove our attention, and keep it removed, from sensations that have no reference to the outer world, those, e.g., of the weaker after-images, and of entoptic objects, etc. . . . But what would become of our perceptions at all if we had the power not only of ignor ing, but of transforming into their opposites, any part of them that differed from that outward experience, the image of which, as that of a present reality, accompanies them in the mind ? " * And again : u On the analogy of all other experience, we should expect that the conquered feelings would persist to our perception, even if only in the shape of recognized illusions. But this is not the case. One does not see how the assumption of originally spatial sensations can explain our optical cognitions, when in the last resort those who believe in these very sensations find themselves obliged to assume that they are over come by our better judgment, based on experience. " These words, coming from such a quarter, necessarily carry great weight. But the authority even of a Helmholtz ought not to shake one's critical composure. And the mo ment one abandons abstract generalities and comes to close quarters with the particulars, I think one easily sees that no such conclusions as those we have quoted follow from the latter. But profitably to conduct the discussion ive must divide the alleged instances into groups. (a) With Helmholtz, color-perception is equally with space- perception an intellectual affair. The so-called simulta neous color-contrast, by which one color modifies another alongside of which it is said, is explained by him as an unconscious inference. In Chapter XYII we discussed the color-contrast problem ; the principles which applied to its solution will prove also applicable to part of the present problem. In my opinion, Hering has definitively proved that, when one color is laid beside another, it modifies the sensation of the latter, not by virtue of any mere mental suggestion, as Helmholtz would have it, but by actually exciting a new nerve -process, to which the modified feeling of color immediately corresponds. The explanation is physiological, not psychological. The transformation of *Physiol. Optik, p. 817. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 245 the original color by the inducing color is due to the dis appearance of the physiological conditions under which the first color was produced, and to the induction, under the new conditions, of a genuine new sensation, with which the ' suggestions of experience ' have naught to do. FIG. 64. That processes in the visual apparatus propagate them selves laterally, if one may so express it, is also shown by the phenomena of contrast which occur after looking upon motions of various kinds. Here are a few examples. If, over the rail of a moving vessel, we look at the water rush ing along the side, and then transfer our gaze to the deck, a band of planks will appear to us, moving in the opposite 246 PSYCHOLOGY. direction to that in which, a moment previously, we had been seeing the water move, whilst on either side of this band another band of planks will move as the water did. Looking at a waterfall, or at the road from out of a car- window in a moving train, produces the same illusion, which may be easily verified in the laboratory by a simple piece of apparatus. A board with a window five or six inches wide and of any convenient length is supported upright on two feet. On the back side of the board, above and below the window, are two rollers, one of which is provided with a crank. An endless band of any figured stuff is passed over these rollers (one of which can be so adjusted on its bearings as to keep the stuff always taut and not liable to slip), and the surface of the front board is also covered with stuff or paper of a nature to catch the eye. Turning the crank now sets the central band in continuous motion, whilst the margins of the field remain really at rest, but after a while appear moving in the contrary way. Stopping the crank results in an illusory appearance of motion in reverse directions all over the field. A disk with an Archimedean spiral drawn upon it, whirled round on an ordinary rotating machine, produces still more startling effects. FIG. 65. "If the revolution is in the direction in which the spiral line Approaches the centre of the disk the entire surface of the latter seems to expand during revolution and to contract after it has ceased ; *nd THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 247 vice versd if the movement of revolution is in the opposite direction. If in the former case the eyes of the observers are turned from the rotat ing disk towards any familiar object — e.g. the face of a friend — the latter seems to contract or recede in a somewhat striking manner, and to expand or approach after the opposite motion of the spiral. " * An elementary form of these motor illusions seems to be the one described by Helmholtz on pp. 568-571 of his Optik, The motion of anything in the field of vision along an acute angle towards a straight line sensibly distorts 1> I ^--""~ 0 H FIG. 66. that line. Thus in Fig. 66 : Let AB be a line drawn on paper, CDE the tracing made over this line by the point of a compass steadily followed by the eye, as it moves. As the compass-point passes from C to D, the line appears to move downwards ; as it passes from D to E, the line appears to move upwards ; at the same time the whole line seems to incline itself in the direction FG during the first half of the compass's movement ; and in the direction HI dur ing its last half ; the change from one inclination to an other being quite distinct as the compass-point passes over D. Any line across which we draw a pencil-point appears to be animated by a rapid movement of its own towards the pencil-point. This apparent movement of both of two things in relative motion to each other, even when one of them is absolutely still, reminds us of the instances quoted * Bowditch and Hall, in Journal of Physiology, vol. in. p. 299. Helm holtz tries to explain this phenomenon by unconscious rotations of the eye ball. But movements of the eyeball can only explain such appearances of movements as are the same over the whole field. In the windowed board one part of the field seems to move in one way, another part in an other. The same is true when we turn from the spiral to look at the wall — the centre of the field alone swells out or contracts, the margin does the reverse or remains at rest. Mach and Dvorak have beautifully proved the impossibility of eye-rotations in this case (Sitzungsber. d. Wiener Akad., Bd. LXI.). See also Bowditch and Hall's paper as above, p. 300. 248 PSYCHOLOGY. from Vierordt on page 188, and seems to take us back to a primitive stage of perception, in which the discriminations we now make when we feel a movement have not yet been made. If we draw the point of a pencil through ' Zollner's pattern' (Fig. 60, p. 232), and follow it with the eye, the whole figure becomes the scene of the most singular apparent unrest, of which Helmholtz has very carefully noted the conditions. The illusion of Zollner's figure van ishes entirely, or almost so, with most people, if they steadily look at one point of it with an unmoving eye ; and the same is the case with many other illusions. Now all these facts taken together seem to show — vaguely it is true, but certainly — that present excitements and after effects of former excitements may alter the result of processes occurring simultaneously at a distance from them in the retina or other portions of the apparatus for optical sensation. In the cases last considered, the moving eye, as it sweeps the fovea over certain parts of the figure, seems thereby to determine a modification in the feeling which the other parts confer, which modification is the figure's 'distortion.' It is true that this statement explains nothing. It only keeps the cases to which it applies from being explained spuri ously. The spurious account of these illusions is that they are intellectual, not sensational, that they are secondary, not primary, mental facts. The distorted figure is said to be one which the mind is led to imagine, by falsely drawing an uncon scious inference from certain premises of which it is not distinctly aware. And the imagined figure is supposed to be strong enough to suppress the perception of whatever real sensations there may be. But Helmholtz, Wundt, Delbceuf, Zollner, and all the advocates of unconscious in ference are at variance with each other when it comes to the question what these unconscious premises and infer ences may be. That small angles look proportionally larger than larger ones is, in brief, the fundamental illusion to which almost all authors would reduce the peculiarity of Fig. 67, as of Figs. 60, 61, 62 (pp. 232, 233). This peculiarity of small angles is by Wundt treated as the case of a filled space seeming larger than an empty one, as in Fig. 68 ; and this, according THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 249 to both Delboauf and Wundt, is owing to the fact that more muscular innervation is needed for the eye to traverse a filled space than an empty one, because the points and lines FIG. 67. in the filled space inevitably arrest and constrain the eye, and this makes us feel as if it were doing more work, i.e. traversing a longer distance.* When, however, we recol- FIG. 68. lect that muscular movements are positively proved to have no share in the waterfall and revolving-spiral illusions, and that it is hard to see how Wundt's and Delboeuf's particular form of muscle-explanation can possibly apply to the com pass-point illusion considered a moment ago, we must con clude that these writers have probably exaggerated, to say the least, the reach of their muscle-explanation in the case * Bulletins de 1'Acad. de Belgique, xxi. 2; Revue Philosophique, vi. pp. 223-5 ; Physiologische Psychologic, 2te Aufl. p. 103. Compare Mttn- aterberg's views, Beitrage, Heft 2, p. 174. 250 PSYCHOLOGY. of the subdivided angles and lines. Never do we get such strong muscular feelings as when, against the course of na ture, we oblige our eyes to be still ; but fixing the eyes on one point of the figure, so far from making that part of the latter seem larger, dispels, in most persons, the illusion of these diagrams altogether. As for Helmholtz, he invokes, to explain the enlarge ment of small angles,* what he calls a « law of contrast ' between directions and distances of lines, analogous to that between colors and intensities of light. Lines cutting another line make the latter seem more inclined away from them than it really is. Moreover, clearly recognizable mag nitudes appear greater than equal magnitudes which we but vaguely apprehend. But this is surely a sensational- istic law, a native function of our seeing-apparatus. Quite as little as the negative after-image of the revolving spiral could such contrast be deduced from any association of ideas or recall of past objects. The principle of contrast is criticised by Wundt, f who says that by it small spaces ought to appear to us smaller, and not larger, than they really are. Helmholtz might have retorted (had not the retort been as fatal to the uniformity of his own principle as to Wundt's) that if the muscle-explanation were true, it ought not to give rise to just the opposite illusions in the skin. We saw on p. 141 that subdivided spaces appear! shorter than empty ones upon the skin. To the instances! there given add this : Divide a line on paper into equal halves, puncture the extremities, and make punctures all along one of the halves ; then, with the finger-tip on the opposite side of the paper, follow the line of punctures ; the empty half will seem much longer than the punctured half. This seems to bring things back to unanalyzable| laws, by reason of which our feeling of size is determined! differently in the skin and in the retina, even when the! objective conditions are the same. Bering's explanation of Zollner's figure is to be found in Hermann's Handb. d. Physiologie, m. 1. p. 579. Lipps t gives another reason * Physiol. Optik, pp. 562-71. f Physiol. Psych., pp. 107-8. Grundtatsachen des Seelenlebens, pp. 526-30. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. why lines cutting another line make the latter seem to bend away from them more than is really the case. If, he says, wo draw (Fig. 69) the line pm upon the line ab, and follow the latter with our eye, we shall, on reaching the point m, tend for a moment to slip off ab and to follow mp, without distinctly realizing that we are not still on the main line. This makes us feel as if the remainder nib of the main line were bent a little away from its original direc tion. The illusion is apparent in the shape of a seeming FIG. 69. approach of the ends 5, 6, of the two main lines. This to my mind would be a more satisfactory explanation of this class of illusions than any of those given by previous au thors, were it not again for what happens in the skin. Considering all the circumstances, I fed justified in dis carding his entire batch of illusions as irrelevant to our pres ent inquiry. Whatever they may prove, they do not prove that our visual percepts of form and movement may not be sensations strictly so called. They much more probably fall into line with the phenomena of irradiation and of color-contrast, and with Vierordt's primitive illusions of movement. They show us, if anything, a realm of sen sations in which our habitual experience has not yet made traces, and which persist in spite of our better knowledge, imsuggestive of those other space-sensations which we all the time know from extrinsic evidence to constitute the real space-determinations of the diagram. Yery likely, if these sensations were as frequent and as practically important as they now are insignificant and rare, we should end by sub stituting their significates — the real space-values of the diagrams — for them. These latter we should then seem to 252 PSYCHOLOGY. see directly, and the illusions would disappear like that of the size of a tooth-socket when the tooth has been out a week. (b) Another batch of cases which we may discard is that of double images. A thoroughgoing anti-sensationalist ought to deny all native tendency to see double images when disparate retinal points are stimulated, because, he should say, most people never get them, but see all things single which experience has led them to believe to be single. " Can a doubleness, so easily neutralized by our knowledge, ever be a datum of sensation at all? " such an anti-sensa tionalist might ask. To which the answer is that it is a datum of sensation, but a datum which, like many other data, must first be discriminated. As a rule, no sensible qualities are dis criminated without a motive.* And those that later we learn to discriminate were originally felt confused. As well pretend that a voice, or an odor, which we have learned to pick out, is no sensation now. One may easily acquire skill in discriminating double images, though, as Hering somewhere says, it is an art of which one cannot become master in one year or in two. For masters like Hering himself, or Le Conte, the ordinary stereoscopic dia grams are of little use. Instead of combining into one solid appearance, they simply cross each other with their doubled Fro. 70. lines. Volkmann has shown a great variety of ways in which the addition of secondary lines, differing in the two * Of. supra, p. 515 if. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 253 fields, helps us to see the primary lines double. The effect is analogous to that shown in the cases which we despatched a moment ago, where given lines have their space-value changed by the addition of new lines, without our being able to say why, except that a certain mutual adhesion of the lines and modification of the resultant feeling takes place by psychophysiological laws. Thus, if in Fig. 70, I and r be crossed by an horizontal line at the same level, and viewed stereoscopically, they appear as a single pair of lines, 5, in space. But if the horizontal be at different levels, as in I', r', three lines appear, as in s'.* Let us then say no more about double images. All that the facts prove is what Yolkmann says,t that, although there may be sets of retinal fibres so organized as to give an impression of two separate spots, yet the excitement of other retinal fibres may inhibit the effect of the first ex citement, and prevent us from actually making the dis crimination. Still farther retinal processes may, however, bring the doubleness to the eye of attention; and, once there, it is as genuine a sensation as any that our life affords.J (c) These groups of illusions being eliminated, either as cases of defective discrimination, or as changes of one space- sensation into another when the total retinal process changes, there remain but tivo other groups to puzzle us. The first is that of the after-images distorted by projection on to oblique planes ; the second relates to the instability of our judgments of relative distance and size by the eye, and includes especially what are known as pseudoscopic illusions. * See Archiv f . Ophthalm. , v. 2, 1 (1859), where many more examples are given. f Untersuchungen, p. 250 ; see also p. 242. j 1 pass over certain difficulties about double images, drawn from the perceptions of a few squinters (e.g. by Schweigger, Klin. Untersuch liber das Schielen, Berlin, 1881 ; by Javal, Annales d'Oculistique, LXXXV. p. 217), because the facts are exceptional at best and very difficult of inter pretation. In favor of the sensationalistic or nativistic view of one such case, see the important paper by Von Kries, Archiv f. Ophthalm., xxiv. 4, p. 117. 254 PSYCHOLOGY. The phenomena of the first group were described on page 232. A. W. Yolkmann has studied them with his accustomed clearness and care. * Even an imaginarily inclined wall, in a picture, will, if an after-image be thrown upon it, distort the shape thereof, and make us see a form of which our after-image would be the natural projection on the retina, were that form laid upon the wall. Thus a signboard is painted in perspective on a screen, and the eye, after steadily looking at a rectangular cross, is turned to the painted signboard. The after-image appears as an oblique-legged cross upon the signboard. It is the converse phenomenon of a perspective drawing like Fig. 71, in which FIG. 71. really oblique-legged figures are seen as rectangular crosses. The unstable judgments of relative distance and size were also mentioned on pp. 231-2. Whatever the size may be of the retinal image which an object makes, the object is seen as of its own normal size. A man moving towards us is not sensibly perceived to grow, for example ; and my finger, of which a single joint may more than conceal him from my view, is nevertheless seen as a much smaller object than the man. As for distances, it is often possible to make the farther part of an object seem near and the nearer part far. A human profile in intaglio, looked at steadily with one eye, or even both, soon appears irresistibly as a bas- relief. The inside of a common pasteboard mask, painted like the outside, and viewed with one eye in a direct light, also looks convex instead of hollow. So strong is the illu- * Physiologische Untersuclmngen im Gebiete der Optik, v. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 255 sion, after long fixation, that a friend who painted such a mask for me told me it soon became difficult to see how to apply the brush. Bend a visiting-card across the middle, so that its halves form an angle of 90° more or less ; set it upright on the table, as in Fig. 72, and view it with one eye. FIG. 72. You can make it appear either as if it opened towards you or away from you. In the former case, the angle ab lies upon the table, b being nearer to you than a ; in the latter case ab seems vertical to the table — as indeed it really is with a nearer to you than b* Again, look,with either one or * Cf. E. Mach, Beitrage zur Analyse der Einptindungen, p. 87. 256 PSYCHOLOGY. two eyes, at the opening of a wine-glass or tumbler (Fig. 73), held either above or below the eye's level. The retinal image of the opening is an oval, but we can see the oval in either of two ways, — as if it were the perspective view of a> circle whose edge b were farther from us than its edge a (in which case we should seem to be looking down on the circle), or as if its edge a were the more distant edge (in which case we should be looking up at it through the b side of the glass). As the manner of seeing the edge changes, the glass itself alters its form in space and looks straight or seems bent towards or from the eye,* according as the latter is placed beneath or above it. Plane diagrams also can be conceived as solids, and that in more than one way. Figs. 74, 75, 76, for example, are am- FTG. 74. FIG. 75. FIG. biguous perspective projections, and may each of them re mind us of two different natural objects. Whichever of these * Cf. V. Egger, Revue Pbilos., xx. 488. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 257 objects we conceive clearly at the moment of looking at the figure, we seem to see in all its solidity before us. A little prac tice will enable us to flap the figures, so to speak, backwards and forwards from one object to the other at will. We need only attend to one of the angles represented, and imagine it either solid or hollow — pulled towards us out of the plane of the paper, or pushed back behind the same — and the whole figure obeys the cue and is instantaneously trans formed beneath our gaze.* The peculiarity of all these cases is the ambiguity of the perception to which the fixed retinal impression gives rise. With our retina excited in exactly the same way, whether by after-image, mask or diagram, we see now this object and now that, as if the retinal image per se had no essential space-import. Surely if form and length were originally retinal sensations, retinal rectangles ought not to become acute or obtuse, and lines ought not to alter their relative lengths as they do. If relief were an optical feeling, it ought not to flap to and fro, with every optical con dition unchanged. Here, if anywhere, the deniers of space- sensation ought to be able to make their final stand, t It must be confessed that their plea is plausible at first sight. But it is one thing to throw out retinal sensibility altogether as a space-yielding function the moment we find an ambiguity in its deliverances, and another thing to examine candidly the conditions which may have brought the ambiguity about. The former way is cheap, wholesale, shallow; the latter difficult and complicated, but full of instruction in the end. Let us try it for ourselves. In the case of the diagrams 72, 73, 74, 75, 76, the real object, lines meeting or crossing each other on a plane, is * Loeb (Pfliiger's Archiv, XL. 274) has proved that muscular changes of adaptation in the eye for near and far distance are what determine the form of the relief. f The strongest passage in Helmholtz's argument against sensations of space is relative to these fluctuations of seen relief: "Ought one not to conclude that if sensations of relief exist at all, they must be so faint and vague as to have no influence compared with that of past experience? Ought we not to believe that the perception of the third dimension may have arisen without them, since we now see it taking place as well againtt them as with them?" (Physiol. Optik, p. 817.) 258 PSYCHOLOGY. replaced by an imagined solid which we describe as seen, fieally it is not seen but only so vividly conceived as to approach a vision of reality. We feel all the while, however, that the solid suggested is not solidly there. The reason why one solid may seem more easily suggested than another, and why it is easier in general to perceive the diagram solid than flat, seems due to probability '* Those lines have countless times in our past experience been drawn on our retina by solids for once that we have seen them flat on paper. And hundreds of times we have looked down upon the upper surface of parallelepipeds, stairs and glasses, for once that we have looked upwards at their bottom — hence we see the solids easiest as if from above. Habit or probability seems also to govern the illusion of the intaglio profile, and of the hollow mask. We have never seen a human face except in relief — hence the case with which the present sensation is overpowered. Hence, too, the obstinacy with which human faces and forms, and other extremely familiar convex objects, refuse to appear hollow when viewed through Wheatstone's pseudoscope. Our perception seems wedded to certain total ways of seeing certain objects. The moment the object is suggested at all, it takes possession of the mind in the fulness of its stereotyped habitual form. This explains the suddenness of the transformations when the perceptions change. The object shoots back and forth completely from this to that familiar thing, and doubtful, indeterminate, and composite things are excluded, apparently because we are unused to their existence. W^hen we turn from the diagrams to the actual folded visiting-card and to the real glass, the imagined form seems fully as real as the correct one. The card flaps over ; the glass rim tilts this way or that, as if some inward spring suddenly became released in our eye. In these changes the actual retinal image receives different complements from the mind. But the remarkable thing is that the complement * Cf. E. Mach, Beitrage, etc., p. 90, and the preceding chapter of the present work, p. 86 ff. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 259 and the image combine so completely that the twain are one flesh, as it were, and cannot be discriminated in the result. If the complement be, as we have called it (on pp. 237-8), a set of imaginary absent eye-sensations, they seem no whit less vividly there than the sensation which the eye now receives from without. The case of the after-images distorted by projection upon an oblique plane is even more strange, for the imagined perspective figure, lying in the plane, seems less to combine with the one a moment previously seen by the eye than to suppress it and take its place.* The point needing explana tion, then, in all this, is how it comes to pass that, when imagined sensations are usually so inferior in vivacity to real ones, they should in these few experiences prove to be almost or quite their match. The mystery is solved when we note the class to which all these experiences belong. They are * perceptions ' of definite 'things,' definitely situated in tridimensional space. The mind uniformly uses its sensations to identify things by. The sensation is invariably apperceived by the idea, name, or ' normal ' aspect (p. 238) of the thing. The peculiarity of the optical signs of things is their extraordinary mutability. A * thing ' which we follow with the eye, never doubting of its physical identity, will change its retinal image inces santly. A cross, a ring, waved about in the air, will pass through every conceivable angular and elliptical form. All the while, however, as we look at them, we hold fast to the perception of their ' real ' shape, by mentally combining the pictures momentarily received with the notion of peculiar positions in space. It is not the cross and ring pure and simple which we perceive, but the cross so held, the ring so hdd. From the day of our birth we have sought every hour of our lives to correct the apparent form of things, and trans- * I ought to say that I seem always able to see the cross rectangular at will. But this appears to come from an imperfect absorption of the rectangular after-image by the inclined plane at which the eyes look. The cross, with me, is apt to detach itself from this and then look square. I get the illusion better from the circle, whose after-image becomes in various ways elliptical on being projected upon the different surfaces of the room, and cannot then be easily made to look circular again. 260 PSYCHOLOGY. late it into the real form by keeping note of the way they are placed or held. In no other class of sensations does this incessant correction occur. What wonder, then, that the notion ' so placed ' should invincibly exert its habitual corrective effect, even when the object with which it com bines is only an after-image, and make us perceive the latter under a changed but more ' real ' form ? The * real ' form is also a sensation conjured up by memory ; but it is one so probable, so habitually conjured up when we have just this combination of optical experiences, that it partakes of the invincible freshness of reality, and seems to break through that law which elsewhere condemns reproductive processes to being so much fainter than sensations. Once more, these cases form an extreme. Somewhere, in the list of our imaginations of absent feelings, there must be found the vividest of all. These optical reproductions of real form are the vividest of all. It is foolish to reason from cases lower in the scale, to prove that the scale can contain no such ex treme cases as these ; and particularly foolish since we can definitely see why these imaginations ought to be more vivid than any others, whenever they recall the forms of habitual and probable things. These latter, by incessantly repeated presence and reproduction, will plough deep grooves in the nervous system. There will be developed, to correspond to them, paths of least resistance, of unstable equilibrium, liable to become active in their totality when any point is touched off. Even when the objective stimulus is imperfect, we shall still see the full convexity of a human face, the correct inclination of an angle or sweep of a curve, or the distance of two lines. Our mind will be like a poly hedron, whose facets are the attitudes of perception in which it can most easily rest. These are worn upon it by habitual objects, and from one of these it can pass only by tumbling over into another.* Bering has well accounted for the sensationally vivid character of these habitually reproduced forms. He says, * In Chapter XVIII, p. 74, I gave a reason why imaginations ought not to be as vivid as sensations. It should be borne in mind that that reason does not apply to these complemental imaginings of the real shape of things actually before our eyes. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 261 after reminding us that every visual sensation is correlated to a physical process in the nervous apparatus : ** If this psychophysical process is aroused, as usually happens, by light-rays impinging on the retina, its form depends not only on the na ture of these rays, but on the constitution of the entire nervous appa ratus which is connected with the organ of vision, and on the state in which it finds itself. The same stimulus may excite widely different sensations according to this state. u The constitution of the nervous apparatus depends naturally in part upon innate predisposition ; but the ensemble of effects wrought by stimuli upon it in the course of life, whether these come through the eyes or from elsewhere, is a co-factor of its development. To express it otherwise, involuntary and voluntary experience and exercise assist in determining the material structure of the nervous organ of vision, and hence the ways in which it may react on a retinal image as an outward stimulus. That experience and exercise should be possible at all in vision is a consequence of the reproductive power, or memory, of its nerve-substance. Every particular activity of the organ makes it more suited to a repetition of the same ; ever slighter touches are required to make the repetition occur. The organ habituates itself to the repeated activity. . . . u Suppose now that, in the first experience of a complex sensation produced by a particular retinal image, certain portions were made the special objects of attention. In a repetition of the sensible experience it will happen that notwithstanding the identity of the outward stimulus these portions will be more easily and strongly reproduced ; and when this happens a hundred times the inequality with which the various constituents of the complex sensation appeal to consciousness grows ever greater. "Now in the present state of our knowledge we cannot assert that in both the first and the last occurrence of the retinal image in question the same pure sensation is provoked, but that the mind interprets it differently the last time in consequence of experience ; for the only given things we know are on the one hand the retinal image which is both times the same, and on the other the mental percept which is both times different ; of a third thing, such as a pure sensation, interpolated between image and percept, we know nothing. We ought, therefore, if we wish to avoid hypotheses, simply to say that the nervous apparatus reacts the last time differently from the first, and gives us in conse quence a different group of sensations. " But not only by repetition of the same retinal image, but by that of similar ones, will the law obtain. Portions of the image common to the successive experiences will awaken, as it were, a stronger echo in the nervous apparatus than other portions. Hence it results that repro duction is usually elective : the more strongly reverberating parts of the picture yield stronger feelings than the rest. This may result in the 262 PSYCHOLOGY. latter being quite overlooked and, as it were, eliminated from perception. It may even come to pass that instead of these parts eliminated by elec tion a feeling of entirely different elements comes to consciousness — • elements not objectively contained in the stimulus. A group of sensa tions, namely, for which a strong tendency to reproduction has become, by frequent repetition, ingrained in the nervous system will easily revive as a whole when, not its whole retinal image, but only an essential part thereof, returns. In this case we get some sensations to which no ade quate stimulus exists in the retinal image, and which owe their being solely to the reproductive power of the nervous apparatus. This is complementary (erganzende) reproduction. "Thus a few points and disconnected strokes are sufficient to make us see a human face, and without specially directed attention we fail to note that we see much that really is not drawn on the paper. Attention will show that the outlines were deficient in spots where we thought them complete. . . . The portions of the percept supplied by comple mentary reproduction depend, however, just as much as its other por tions, on the reaction of the nervous apparatus upon the retinal image, indirect though this reaction may, in the case of the supplied portions, be. And so long as they are present, we have a perfect right to call them sensations, for they differ in no wise from such sensations as cor respond to an actual stimulus in the retina. Often, however, they are not persistent ; many of them may be expelled by more close observa tion, but this is not proved to be the case with all. ... In vision with one eye . . . the distribution of parts within the third dimension is essentially the work of this complementary reproduction, i.e. of former experience. . . . When a certain way of localizing a particular group of sensations has become with us a second nature, our better knowl edge, our judgment, our logic, are of no avail. . . . Things actually diverse may give similar or almost identical retinal images; e.g., an object extended in three dimensions, and its flat perspective picture. In such cases it often depends on small accidents, and especially on our will, whether the one or the other group of sensations shall be excited. ... We can see a relief hollow, as a mould, or vice versa; for a relief illuminated from the left can look just like its mould illuminated from the right. Reflecting upon this, one may infer from ttie direction of the shadows that one has a relief before one, and the idea of the relief will guide the nerve-processes into the right path, so that the feeling of the relief is suddenly aroused. . . . Whenever the retinal image is of such a nature that two diverse modes of reaction on the part of the nervous apparatus are, so to speak, equally, or nearly equally, immi nent, it must depend on small accidents whether the one or the other reaction is realized. In these cases our previous knowledge often has a decisive effect, and helps the correct perception to victory. The bare idea of the right object is itself a feeble reproduction which with the help of the proper retinal picture develops into clear and lively sensa tion. But if there be not already in the nervous apparatus a disposi- THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 263 tion to the production of that percept which our judgment tells us is right, our knowledge strives in vain to conjure up the feeling of it ; we then know that we see something to which no reality corresponds, but we see it all the same." * Note that no object not probable, no object which we are not incessantly practised in reproducing, can acquire this vividness in imagination. Objective corners are ever changing their angles to the eyes, spaces their apparent size, lines their distance. But by no transmutation of position in space does an objective straight line appear bent, and only in one position out of an infinity does a broken line look straight. Accordingly, it is impossible by projecting the after-image A B FIG. 77. «>/ a straight line upon two surfaces which make a solid angle with each other to give the line itself a sensible 'kink.' Look with it at the corner of your room: the after-image, which may overlap all three surfaces of the corner, still continues straight. Volkmann constructed a complicated surface of projection like that drawn in Fig. 77, but he found it impossible so to throw a straight after image upon it as to alter its visible form. * Hermann's Handb. der Physiologie. in. 1, p. 565-71. 264 PSYCHOLOGY. One of the situations in which we oftenest see things is spread out on the ground before us. We are incessantly drilled in making allowance for this perspective, and reduc ing things to their real form in spite of optical foreshorten ing. Hence if the preceding explanations are true, we ought to find this habit inveterate. The lower half of the retina, which habitually sees the fartfor half of things spread out on the ground, ought to have acquired a habit of enlarging its pictures by imagination, so as to make them more than equal to those which fall on the upper retinal surface ; and this habit ought to be hard to escape from, even when both halves of the object are equidistant from the eye, as in a vertical line on paper. Delboauf has found, accordingly, that if we try to bisect such a line we place the point of division about -fa of its length too high.* Similarly, a square cross, or a square, drawn on paper, should look higher than it is broad. And that this is actu ally the case, the reader may verify by a glance at Fig. 78. FIG. 78. For analogous reasons the upper and lower halves of the letter S, or of the figure 8, hardly seem to differ. But when turned upside down, as g, g> the upper half looks much the larger, f * Bulletin de 1' Academic de Belgique, 2me Serie, xix. 2. f Wundt seeks to explain all these illusions by the relatively stronger ' feeling of innervation ' needed to move the eyeballs upwards,— a careful study of the muscles concerned is taken to prove this,— and a consequently greater estimate of the distance traversed. It suffices to remark, however, with Lipps, that were the innervation all, a column of S's placed on top of each other should look each larger than the one below it, and a weather cock on a steeple gigantic, neither of which is the case. Only the halves of the same object look different in size, because the customary correction THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 265 Hering has tried to explain our exaggeration of small angles in the same way. We have more to do with right angles than with any others : right angles, in fact, have an altogether unique sort of interest for the human mind. Nature almost never begets them, but we think space by means of them and put them everywhere. Consequently obtuse and acute ones, liable always to be the images of right ones foreshortened, particularly easily revive right ones in memory. It is hard to look at such figures as a, b, c, in Fig. 79, without seeing them in perspective, as a i FIG. 79. approximations, at least, to foreshortened rectangular forms. * At the same time the genuine sensational form of the lines before us can, in all the cases of distortion by sug gested perspective, be felt correctly by a mind able to ab stract from the notion of perspective altogether. Individ uals differ in this abstracting power. Artistic training im proves it, so that after a little while errors in vertical bi section, in estimating height relatively to breadth, etc., be come impossible. In other words, we learn to take the optical sensation before us pure, f for foreshortening bears only on the relations of the parts of special things spread out before us. Cf. Wundt, Physiol. Psych., 2te Aufl. 11. 96-8; Th. Lipps, Grundtatsachen, etc., p. 535. * Hering would partly solve in this way the mystery of Figs. 60, 61, and 67. No doubt the explanation partly applies ; but the strange cessation of the illusion when we fix the gaze fails to be accounted for thereby. f Helmholtz has sought (Physiol. Optik, p. 715) to explain the diverg ence of the apparent vertical meridians of the two retinae, by the manner in which an identical line drawn on the ground before us in the median plane will throw its images on the two eyes respectively. The matter is too technical for description here ; the unlearned reader may be referred for it to J. Le Conte's Sight in the Internat. Scient. Series, p. 198 ff. But, for the benefit of those to whom verbum sat, I cannot help saying that it seems to me that the exactness of the relation of the two meridians— whether diver- 266 PSYCHOLOGY. We may then sum up our study of illusions by saying that they in no wise undermine our view that every spatial determi nation of things is originally given in the shape of a sensation of the eyes. They only show how very potent certain imagined sensations of the eyes may become. These sensations, so far as they bring definite forms to the mind, appear to be retinal exclusively. The move ments of the eyeballs play a great part in educating our perception, it is true ; but they have nothing to do with constituting any one feeling of form. Their function is limited to exciting the various feelings of form, by tracing retinal streaks ; and to comparing them, and measuring them off against each other, by applying different parts of the retinal surface to the same objective thing. Helmholtz's analysis of the facts of our * measurement of the field of vieiv* is, bating a lapse or two, masterly, and seems to prove that the movements of the eye have had some part in bringing our sense of retinal equivalencies about — equivalencies, mind, of different retinal forms and sizes, not forms and sizes themselves. Superposition is the way in which the eve- movements accomplish this result. An object traces the line AB on a peripheral tract of the retina. Quickly we move the eye so that the same object traces the line ah on a central tract. Forthwith, to our mind, AB and ab are judged equivalent. But, as Helmholtz admits, the equiv alence-judgment is independent of the way in which we may feel the form and length of the several retinal pic tures themselves : "The retina is like a pair of compasses, whose points we apply in succession to the ends of several lines to see whether they agree or not in length. All we need know meanwhile about the compasses is that the distance of their points remains unchanged. What that distance is, and what is the shape of the compasses, is a matter of no account."* gent or not, for their divergence differs in individuals and often in one in dividual at diverse times— precludes its being due to the mere habitual falling-oil of the image of one objective line on both. Le Conte, e.g., measures their positiou down to a sixth of a degree, others to tenths. This indicates an organic identity in the sensations of the two retinae, which the experience of median perspective horizontals may roughly have agreed with, but hardly can have engendered. Wundt explains the divergence as usual, by the Innervatiomgefuhl (op. cit. n. 99 if.). * Physiol. Optik, p. 547. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 2(',T Measurement implies a stuff to measure. Retinal sensa tions give the stuff; objective things form the yard-stick ; mo tion does the measuring operation; which can, of course, be well performed only where it is possible to make the same object fall on many retinal tracts. This is practically im possible where the tracts make a wide angle with each other. But there are certain directions in the field of view, certain retinal lines, along which it is particularly easy to make the image of an object slide. The object then be comes a 'ruler' for these lines, as Helmholtz puts it,* making them seem straight throughout if the object looked straight to us in that part of them at which it was most distinctly seen. But all this need of superposition shows how devoid of exact space-import the feelings of movement are per se. As we compare the space-value of two retinal tracts by super posing them successively upon the same objective line, so we also have to compare the space-value of objective angles and lines by superposing them on the same retinal tract. Neither procedure would be required if our eye-movements were apprehended immediately, by pure muscular feeling or innervation, for example, as distinct lengths and direc tions in space. To compare retinal tracts, it would then suffice simply to notice how it feels to move any image over them. And two objective lines could be compared as well by moving different retinal tracts along them as by laying them along the same. It would be as easy to com- * "We can with a short ruler draw a line as long as we please on a plane surface by first drawing one as long as the ruler permits, and then sliding the ruler somewhat along the drawn line and drawing again, etc. If the ruler is exactly straight, we get in this way a straight line. If it is somewhat curved we get a circle. Now, instead of the sliding ruler we use in the field of sight the central spot of distinctest vision impressed with a rinear sensation of sight, which at times may be intensified till it becomes an after-image. We follow, in looking, the direction of this line, and in so doing we slide the line along itself and get a prolongation of its length. On a plane surface we can carry on this procedure on any sort of a straight or curved ruler, but in the field of vision there is for each direction and movement of the eye only one sort of line which it is possible for us to- slide along in its own direction continually." These are what Helmholtz calls the 'circles of direction' of the visual field— lines which he has studied with his usual care. Cf. Physiol. Optih, p. 548 ff. 268 PSYCHOLOGY. pare non-parallel figures as it now is to judge of those which are parallel.* Those which it took the same amount of movement to traverse would be equal, in whatever direc tion the movement occurred. GENERAL SUMMARY. With this we may end our long and, I fear to many readers, tediously minute survey. The facts of vision form a jungle of intricacy ; and those who penetrate deeply into physiological optics will be more struck by our omissions than by our abundance- of detail. But for students who may have lost sight of the forest for the trees, I will re capitulate briefly the points of our whole argument from the beginning, and then proceed to a short historical survey, which will set them in relief. All our sensations are positively and inexplicably exten sive wholes. The sensations contributing to space-perception seem exclusively to be the surface of skin, retina, and joints. 1 Muscular ' feelings play no appreciable part in the genera tion of our feelings of form, direction, etc. The total bigness of a cutaneous or retinal feeling soon becomes subdivided by discriminative attention. Movements assist this discrimination by reason of the peculiarly exciting quality of the sensations which stimuli moving over surfaces arouse. Subdivisions, once discriminated, acquire definite rela tions of position towards each other within the total space. These 'relations' are themselves feelings of the subdivis ions that intervene. When these subdivisions are not the seat of stimuli, the relations are only reproduced in imagi nary form. The various sense-spaces are, in the first instance, inco herent with each other ; and primitively both they and their subdivisions are but vaguely comparable in point of bulk and form. * The education of our space-perception consists largely of two processes — reducing the various sense-feelings to a * Cf. Heriug in Hermann's Handb. der Pnysiol., m. 1, pp. 553-4. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 269 common measure, and adding them together into the single all-including space of the real world. Both the measuring and the adding are performed bj the aid of things. The imagined aggregate of positions occupied by all the actual or possible, moving or stationary, things which we know, is our notion of 'real' space — a very incomplete and vague conception in all minds. The measuring of our space-feelings against each other mainly comes about through the successive arousal of dif ferent ones by the same thing, by our selection of certain ones as feelings of its real size and shape, and by the deg radation of others to the status of being merely signs of these. For the successive application of the same thing to dif ferent space-giving surfaces motion is indispensable, and hence plays a great part in our space-education, especially in that of the eye. Abstractly considered, the motion of the object over the sensitive surface would educate us quite as well as that of the surface over the object. But the self- mobility of the organ 'carrying the surface accelerates im mensely the result. In completely educated space-perception, the present sensation is usually just what Helmholtz (Physiol. Optik, p. 797) calls it, ' a sign, the interpretation of whose mean ing is left to the understanding.' But the understanding is exclusively reproductive and never productive in the pro cess ; and its function is limited to the recall of previous space-sensations with which the present one has been as sociated and which may be judged more real than it. Finally, this reproduction may in the case of certain visual forms be as vivid, or almost so, as actual sensation is. The third dimension forms an original element of all our space-sensations. In the eye it is subdivided by various discriminations. The more distant subdivisions are often shut out altogether, and, in being suppressed, have the effect of diminishing the absolute space-value of the total field of view.* * This shrinkage and expansion of the absolute space-value of the total optical sensation remains to my mind the most obscure part of the whole 270 PSYCHOLOGY. HISTORICAL. Let 118 now close with a brief historical survey. The first achievement of note in the study of space-perception was Berkeley's theory of vision. This undertook to establish two points, first that distance was not a visual but a tactile form of consciousness, suggested by visual signs ; secondly, that there is no one quality or * idea ' common to the sensa tions of touch and sight, such that prior to experience one might possibly anticipate from the look of an object any thing about its felt size, shape, or position, or from the touch of it anything about its look. In other words, that primitively chaotic or semi-chaotic -condition of our various sense-spaces which we have demonstrated, was established for good by Berkeley; and he bequeathed to psychology the problem of describing the manner in which the deliverances are harmonized so as all to refer to one and the same extended world. His disciples in Great Britain have solved this problem after Berkeley's own fashion, and to a great extent as we have done ourselves, by the ideas of the various senses sug gesting each other in consequence of Association. But, either because they were intoxicated with the principle of associa tion, or because in the number of details they lost their general bearings, they have forgotten, as a rule, to state under what sensible form the primitive spatial experiences are found which later became associated with so many other sensible signs. Heedless of their master Locke's precept, that the mind can frame unto itself no one new simple idea, they seem for the most part to be trying to explain the extensive quality itself, account for it, and evolve it, by the mere asso ciation together of feelings which originally possessed it not. They first evaporate the nature of extension by making it tantamount to mere * coexistence,' and then they explain coexistence as being the same thing as succession, provided it subject. It is a real optical sensation, seeming introspectively to have nothing to do with locomotor or other suggestions. It is easy to say that 'the Intellect produces it,' but what does that mean? The investigator who will throw light on this one point will probably clear up other diffi culties as well. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 271 be aii extremely rapid or a reversible succession, Space- perception thus emerges without being anywhere postulated. The only things postulated are unextended feelings and 1 ime. Says Thomas Brown (lecture xxm.) : " I am inclined to re verse exactly the process commonly supposed ; and instead of deriving the measure of time from extension, to derive the knowledge and original measure of extension from time." Brown and both the Mills think that retinal sensations, colors, in their primitive condition, are felt with no extension and that the latter merely becomes inseparably associated with them. John Mill says : " Whatever may be the retinal impression conveyed by a line which bounds two colors, I see no ground for thinking that by the eye alone we could acquire the conception of what we now mean when we say that one of the colors is outside [beside] the other." * Whence does the extension come which gets so insepa rably associated with these non-extended colored sensations ? From the ' sweep and movements ' of the eye — from mus cular feelings. But, as Prof. Bain says, if movement-feel ings give us any property of things, " it would seem to be not space, but time." t And John Mill says that " the idea of space is, at bottom, one of time." | Space, then, is not to be found in any elementary sensation, but, in Bain's words, " as a quality, it has no other origin and no other meaning than the association of these different [non-spatial] motor and sensitive effects." § This phrase is mystical-sounding enough to one who understands association as producing nothing, but only as knitting together things already produced in separate ways. The truth is that the English Associationist school, in trying to show how much their principle can accomplish, have altogether overshot the mark and espoused a kind of theory in respect to space-perception which the general tenor of their philosophy should lead them to abhor. Keally there are but three possible kinds of theory concerning space. Either (1) there is no spatial quality of sensation at all, and * Examination of Hamilton, 3d ed. p. 283. f Senses and Intellect, 3d ed. p. 183. j Exam, of Hamilton, 3d ed. p. 283. § Senses and Intellect, p. 372. 272 PSYCHOLOGY. space is a mere symbol of succession ; or (2) there is an ex tensive quality given immediately in certain particular sen sations ; or, finally, (3) there is a quality produced out of the inward resources of the mind, to envelop sensations which, as given originally, are not spatial, but which, on being cast into the spatial form, become united and orderly. This last is the Kantian view. Stumpf admirably designates it as the * psychic stimulus ' theory, the crude sensations being considered as goads to the mind to put forth its slumbering power. Brown, the Mills, and Bain, amid these possibilities, seem to have gone astray like lost sheep. With the * men tal chemistry ' of which the Mills speak — precisely the same thing as the * psychical synthesis ' of Wundt, which, as we shall soon see, is a principle expressly intended to do what Association can never perform — they hold the third view, but again in other places imply the first. And, be tween the impossibility of getting from mere association anything not contained in the sensations associated and the dislike to allow spontaneous mental productivity, they flounder in a dismal dilemma. Mr. Sully joins them there in what I must call a vague and vacillating way. Mr. Spencer of course is bound to pretend to ' evolve ' all mental qualities out of antecedents different from them selves, so that we need perhaps not wonder at his refusal to accord the spatial quality to any of the several elemen tary sensations out of which our space-perception grows. Thus (Psychology, n. 168, 172, 218) : " No idea of extension can arise from a simultaneous excitation " of a multitude of nerve-terminations like those of the skin or the retina, since this would imply a " knowledge of their relative positions v — that is, "a pre-existent idea of a special extension, which is absurd.11 " No relation between successive states of consciousness gives in itself any idea of extension." " The muscular sensations accompanying motion are quite distinct from the notions of space and time associated with them. '' Mr. Spencer none the less inveighs vociferously against the Kantian position that space is produced by the mind's own resources. And yet he nowhere denies space to be a specific affection of consciousness different from time ! THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 273 Such incoherency is pitiful. The fact is that, at bottom, all these authors are really ' psychical stimulists,' or Kant- ists. The space they speak of is a super- sensational mental product. This position appears to me thoroughly mytho logical. But let us see how it is held by those who know more definitely what they mean. Schopenhauer expresses the Kantian view with more vigor and clearness than any one else. He says : ' ' A man must be forsaken by all the gods to dream that the world we see outside of us, filling space in its three dimensions, moving down the inexorable stream of time, governed at each step by Causality's invariable law? — but in all this only following rules which we may prescribe for it in advance of all experience, — to dream, I say, that such a world should stand there outside of us, quite objectively real with no complicity of ours, and thereupon by a subsequent act, through the instrumentality of mere sensation, that it should enter our head and reconstruct a dupli cate of itself as it was outside. For what a poverty-stricken thing is this mere sensation ! Even in the noblest organs of sense it is nothing more than a local and specific feeling, susceptible within its kind of a few variations, but always strictly subjective and containing in itself noth ing objective, nothing resembling a perception. For sensation of every sort is and remains a process in the organism itself. As such it is limited to the territory inside the skin and can never, accordingly, per se con tain anything that lies outside the skin or outside ourselves. . . . Only when the Understanding ... is roused to activity and brings its sole and only form, the law of Causality, into play, only then does the mighty transformation take place which makes out of subjective sensa tion objective intuition. The Understanding, namely, grasps by means of its innate, a priori, ante-experiential form, the given sensation of the body as an effect which as such must necessarily have a cause. At the same time the Understanding summons to its aid the form of the outer sense which similarly lies already preformed in the intellect (or brain), and which is Space, in order to locate that cause outside of the organ ism. ... In this process the Understanding, as I shall soon show, takes note of the most minute peculiarities of the given sensation in order to construct in the outer space a cause which shall completely account for them. This operation of the Understanding is, however, not one that takes place discursively, reflectively, in abstracto, by means of words and concepts ; but is intuitive and immediate. . . . Thus the Under standing must first create the objective world ; never can the latter, already complete in se, simply promenade into our heads through the senses and organic apertures. For the senses yield us nothing further than the raw material which must be first elaborated into the objective conception of an orderly physical world-system by means of the afore said simple forms of Space, Time, and Causality. . . . Let me show thee 274 PSYCHOLOGY. great chasm between sensation and perception by showing how raw the material is out of which the fair structure is upreared. Only two senses serve objective perception : touch and sight. They alone furnish the data on the basis whereof the Understanding, by the process indicated, erects the objective world. . . . These data in themselves are still no perception ; that is the Understanding's work. If I press with my hand against the table, the sensation I receive has no analogy with the idea of the firm cohesion of the parts of this mass : only when my Under standing passes from the sensation to its cause does it create for itself a body with the properties of solidity, impenetrability, and hardness. When in the dark I lay my hand on a surface, or grasp a ball of three inches diameter, in either case the same parts of the hand receive the impression : but out of the different contraction of the hand in the two cases my Understanding constructs the form of the body whose contact caused the feeling, and confirms its construction by leading me to move my hand over the body. If one born blind handles a cubical body, the sensations of his hand are quite uniform on all sides and in all direc tions.— only the corners press upon a smaller part of his skin. In these sensations, as such, there is nothing whatever analogous to a cube. But from the felt resistance his Understanding infers immediately and intuitively a cause thereof, which now presents itself as a solid body; and from the movements of exploration which the arms made whilst the feelings of the hands remained constant he constructs, in thesp'ace known to him a priori, the body's cubical shape. Did he not bring with him ready-made the idea of a cause and of a space, with the laws thereof, there never could arise, out of those successive feelings in his hand, the image of a cube. If we let a string run through our closed hand, we immediately construct as the cause of the friction and its dura tion in such an attitude of the hand, a long cylindrical body moving uniformly in one direction. But never out of the pure sensation in the hand could the idea of movement, that is, of change of position in space by means of time, arise : such a content can never lie in sensation, nor come out of it. Our Intellect, antecedently to all experience, must bear in itself the intuitions of Space and Time, and therewithal of the possi bility of motion, and no less the idea of Causality, to pass from the empirically given feeling to its cause, and to construct the latter as a so moving body of the designated shape. For how great is the abyss between the mere sensation in the hand and the ideas of causality, materiality, and movement through Space, occurring in Time! The feeling in the hand, even with different contacts and positions, is some thing far too uniform and poor in content for it to be possible to con struct out of it the idea of Space with its three dimensions, of the action of bodies on each other, with the properties of extension, impen etrability, cohesion, shape, hardness, softness, rest, and motion — in short, the foundations of the objective world. This is only possible through Space, Time, and Causality . . . being preformed in the Intellect itself, . . - from whence it again follows that the perception THh! PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 275 of the external world is essentially an intellectual process, a work of the Understanding, to which sensation furnishes merely the occasion, and the data to be interpreted in each particular case." * I call this view mythological, because I am conscious of no such Kantian machine-shop in my mind, and feel no call to disparage the powers of poor sensation in this merci less way. I have no introspective experience of mentally producing or creating space. My space-intuitions occur not in two times but in one. There is not one moment of passive inextensive sensation, succeeded by another of ac tive extensive perception, but the form I see is as immedi ately felt as the color which fills it out. That the higher parts of the mind come in, who can deny ? They add and subtract, they compare and measure, they reproduce and abstract. They inweave the space-sensations with intel lectual relations ; but these relations are the same when they obtain between the elements of the space-system as when they obtain between any of the other elements of which the world is made. The essence of the Kantian contention is that there are not spaces, but Space — one infinite continuous Unit — and that our knowledge of this cannot be a piecemeal sensa tional affair, produced by summation and abstraction. To which the obvious reply is that, if any known thing bears on its front the appearance of piecemeal construction and abstraction, it is this very notion of the infinite unitary space of the world. It is a notion, if ever there was one ; and no intuition. Most of us apprehend it in the barest symbolic abridgment : and if perchance we ever do try to make it more adequate, we just add one image of sensible extension to another until we are tired. Most of us are obliged to turn round and drop the thought of the space in front of us when we think of that behind. And the space represented as near to us seems more minutely subdivisible than that we think of as lying far away. The other prominent German writers on space are also * psychical stimulists.' Herbart, whose influence has been widest, says ' the resting eye sees no space,'t and ascribes * Vierfache Wurzel desSatzes vom zureicheudeii Gruiide, pp. f Pay chol. als Wissenschaft, 8 111. 276 PSYCHOLOGY. visual extension to the influence of movements combining with, the non-spatial retinal feelings so as to form gradated series of the latter. A given sensation of such a series reproduces the idea of its associates in regular order, and its idea is similarly reproduced by any one of them with the order reversed. Out of the fusion of these two con trasted reproductions comes the form of space* — Heaven knows how. The obvious objection is that mere serial order is a genus, and space-order a very peculiar species of that genus ; and that, if the terms of reversible series became by that fact coexistent terms in space, the musical scale, the degrees of warmth and cold, and all other ideally graded series ought to appear to us in the shape of extended corporeal aggre gates, — which they notoriously do not, though we may of course symbolize their order by a spatial scheme. W. Volkmann von Yolkmar, the Herbartian, takes the bull here by the horns, and says the musical scale is spatially ex tended, though he admits that its space does not belong to the real world. t I am unacquainted with any other Her bartian so bold. To Lotze we owe the much-used term 'local sign.' He insisted that space could not emigrate directly into the mind from without, but must be reconstructed by the soul ; and he seemed to think that the first reconstructions of it by the soul must be super-sensational. But why sensa tions themselves might not be the soul's original spatial re constructive acts Lotze fails to explain. « Wundt has all his life devoted himself to the elaboration of a space-theory, of which the neatest and most final ex pression is to be found in his Logik (n. 457-60). He says : "In the eye, space-perception has certain constant peculiarities which prove that no single optical sensation by itself possesses the ex tensive form, but that every where in our perception of space heterogene- * Psychol. als Wissenschaft, § 113. f Lehrbuch d. Psychol., 2te Auflage, Bd. n. p. 66. Volkmann's fifth, chapter contains a really precious collection of historical notices concern ing space-perception theories. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 277 ous feelings combine. If we simply suppose that luminous sensations per se feel extensive, our supposition is shattered by that influence of movement in vision which is so clearly to be traced in many normal errors in the measurement of the field of view. If we assume, on the other hand, that the movements and their feelings are alone possessed of the extensive quality, we make an unjustified hypothesis, for the phenomena compel us, it is true, to accord an influence to movement, but give us no right to call the retinal sensations indifferent, for there are no visual ideas without retinal sensations. If then we wish rigor ously to express the given facts, we can ascribe a spatial constitution only to combinations of retinal sensations with those of movement. " Thus Wundt, dividing theories into * nativistic ' and * genetic,' calls his own a genetic theory. To distinguish it from other theories of the same class, he names it a * theory of complex local signs.' " It supposes two systems of local signs, whose relations— taking the eye as an example — we may think as ... the measuring of the mani fold local-sign system of the retina by the simple local-sign system of the movements. In its psychological nature this is a process of associa tive synthesis : it consists in the fusion of both groups of sensations into a product, whose elementary components are no longer separable from each other in idea. In melting wholly away into the product which they create they become consciously undistinguishable, and the mind apprehends only their resultant, the intuition of space. Thus there obtains a certain analogy between this psychic synthesis and that chemical synthesis which out of simple bodies generates a compound that appears to our immediate perception as a homogeneous whole with •new properties." Now let no modest reader think that if this sounds ob scure to him it is because he does not know the full con text ; and that if a wise professor like Wundt can talk so fluently and plausibly about ' combination ' and ' psychic synthesis,' it must surely be because those words convey a so much greater fulness of positive meaning to the scholar ly than to the unlearned mind. Really it is quite the re verse ; all the virtue of the phrase lies in its mere sound and skin. Learning does but make one the more sensible of its inward unintelligibility. Wundt's ' theory ' is the flim siest thing in the world. It starts by an untrue assump tion, and then corrects it by an unmeaning phrase. Retinal sensations are spatial ; and were they not, no amount of * synthesis ' with equally spaceless motor sensations could PSYCHOLOGY. intelligibly make them so. Wundt's theory is, in short, but an avowal of impotence, and an appeal to the inscru table powers of the soul.* It confesses that we cannot analyze the constitution or give the genesis of the spatial quality in consciousness. But at the same time it says the antecedents thereof are psychical and not cerebral facts. In calling the quality in question a sensational quality, ourj own account equally disclaimed ability to analyze it, but! said its antecedents were cerebral, not psychical — in othetf words, that it was & first psychical thing. This is merely a question of probable fact, which the reader may decide] And now what shall be said of Helmholtz? Can I find fault with a book which, on the whole, I imagine to be one of the four or five greatest monuments of human genius in the scientific line? If truth impels I must fain try, and take the risks. It seems to me that Helmholtz's genius- moves most securely when it keeps close to particular facts. At any rate, it .shows least strong in purely speculative passages, which in the Optics, in spite of many beauties, seem to me fundamentally vacillating and obscure. The 'empiristic' view which Helmholtz defends is that the space-determinations we perceive are in every case pro ducts of a process of unconscious inference, f The infer- .ence is similar to one from induction or analogy. J We al ways see that form before us which habitually would have caused the sensation we now have. § But the latter sensa tion can never be intrinsically spatial, or its intrinsic space- determinations would never be overcome as they are so often by the 'illusory' space-determinations it so often suggests.) Since the illusory determination can be traced to a suggestion of Experience, the ' real ' one must also be such a suggestion : so that all space intuitions are due sole- * Why talk of 'genetic theories '? when we have in the next breath to write as Wundt does: ' ' If then we must regard the intuition of space as a product that simply emerges from the conditions of our mental and physi cal organization, nothing need stand in the way of our designating it asone of the a priori functions with which consciousness is endowed " (Loirik ii. 460.) t P. 430. % Pp. 430, 449. § P. 428. | P. 442. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. ly to Experience.* The only psychic activity required for this is the association of ideas, f But how, it may be asked, can association produce a space- quality not in the things associated ? How can we by induction or analogy infer what we do not already generically know ? Can ' suggestions of experience ' repro duce elements which no particular experience originally contained ? This is the point by which Helmholtz 's ' em- piristic ' theory, as a tfoory, must be judged. No theory is worthy of the name which leaves such a point obscure. Well, Helmholtz does so leave it. At one time he seems to fall back on inscrutable powers of the soul, and to range himself with the ' psychical stimulists.' He speaks of Kant as having made the essential step in the matter in dis tinguishing the content of experience from that form space, course— which is given it by the peculiar faculties of the mind. ;f But elsewhere, again, § speaking of sensa tion alistic theories which would connect spatially determi nate feelings directly with certain neural events, he says it is better to assume only such simple psychic activities as we know to exist, and gives the association of ideas as an instance of what he means. Later, || he reinforces this re mark by confessing that he does not see how any neural process can give rise without antecedent experience to a ready-made (fertige) perception of space. And, finally, in a single momentous sentence, he speaks of sensations of touch as if they might be the original material of our space- percepts — which thus, from the optical point of view, ' may be assumed as given.'^ Of course the eye-man has a right to fall back on the skin-man for help at a pinch. But doesn't this mean that he is a mere eye-man and not a complete psychologist ? In other words, Helmholtz's Optics and the ' empiristic theory ' therein professed must not be understood as attempts at answering the general question of how space-consciousness enters the mind. They simply deny that it enters with the * Pp. 442, 818. f P. 798. Of. also Popular Scientific Lectures, pp. 301-3 J P. 456; see also 428, 441. § P. 797. || P. 812. •|f Bottom of page 797. 280 PSYCHOLOGY. first optical sensations.* Our own account lias affirmed stoutly that it enters then ; but no more than Helmholtz have we pretended to show why. Who calls a thing a first sensation admits he has no theory of its production. Helm holtz, though all the while without an articulate theory, makes the world think he has one. He beautifully traces the immense part which reproductive processes play in our vision of space, and never — except in that one pitiful little sentence about touch — does he tell us just what it is they reproduce. He limits himself to denying that they repro duce originals of a visual sort. And so difficult is the subject, and so magically do catch-words work on the popular-scientist ear, that most likely, had he written ' physiological ' instead of ' nativistic,' and ' spiritualistic ' instead of ' empiristic ' (which synonyms Hering suggests), numbers of his present empirical evolutionary followers would fail to find in his teaching anything worthy of praise. But since he wrote otherwise, they hurrah for him as a sort of second Locke, dealing another death-blow at the old bugaboo of ' innate ideas.' His ' nativistic ' adversary Hering they probably imagine — Heaven save the mark !- to be a scholastic in modern disguise. After Wundt and Helmholtz, the most important anti- sensationalist space-philosopher in Germany is Professor Lipps, whose deduction of space from an order of non- spatial differences, continuous yet separate, is a wonderful piece of subtlety and logic. And yet he has to confess that continuous differences form in the first instance only a logi cal series, which need not appear spatial, and that wher ever it does so appear, this must be accounted a ' fact,' due merely 'to the nature of the soul.' t Lipps, and almost all the anti-sensationalist theorists except Helmholtz, seem guilty of that confusion which Mr. *In fact, to borrow a simile from Prof. G. E. Miiller (Theorie der sinnl. Aufmerksamkeit, p. 38), the various senses bear in the Helinholtzian phi losophy of perception the same relation to the ' object ' perceived by their means that a troop of jolly drinkers bear to the landlord's bill, when no one has any money, but each hopes that one of the rest will pay. fGrundtatsachen des Seelenlebens (1883), pp. 480, 591-2. Psycholo- gische Studien (1885), p. 14. THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE. 281 Shadworth Hodgson lias done so much to clear away, viz., the confounding the analysis of an idea with the means of its production. Lipps, for example, finds that every space we think of can be broken up into positions, and concludes that in some undefined way the several positions must have pre-existed in thought before the aggregate space could have appeared to perception. Similarly Mr. Spencer, de fining extension as an ' aggregate of relations of coexistent position,' says " every cognition of magnitude is a cogni tion of relations of position,"* and " no idea of extension can arise from the simultaneous excitation " of many nerves "unless there is a knowledge of their relative positions. "f Just so Prof. Bain insists that the very meaning of space is scope for movement, J and that therefore distance and mag nitude can be no original attributes of the eye's sensibility. Similarly because movement is analyzable into positions occupied at successive moments by the mover, philoso phers (e.g. Schopenhauer, as quoted above) have repeatedly denied the possibility of its being an immediate sensation. We have, however, seen that it is the most immediate of all our space-sensations. Because it can only occur in a defi nite direction the impossibility of perceiving it without perceiving its direction has been decreed — a decree which the simplest experiment overthrows. § It is a case of what I have called the ' psychologist's fallacy ' : mere acquaint ance with space is treated as tantamount to every sort of knowledge about it, the conditions of the latter are de manded of the former state of mind, and all sorts of mytho logical processes are brought in to help. || As well might one say that because the world consists of all its parts, there- * Psychology, ir. p. 174. \Ibid. p. 168. i Senses and Intellect, 3d ed. pp. 366-75. § Of. Hall and Donaldson in Mind, x. 559. I As other examples of the confusion, take Mr. Sully : " The fallacious assumption that there can be an idea of distance in general, apart from particular distances" (Mind, in. p. 177); and Wundt : "An indefinite localization, which waits for experience to give it its reference to real space, stands in contradiction with the very idea of localization, which means the reference to a determinate point of space " (Physiol. Psych., Ite Aufl. p. 480). 282 PSYCHOLOGY. fore we can only apprehend it at all by having unconsciously summed these up in our head. It is the old idea of our actual knowledge being drawn out from a pre-existent potentiality, an idea which, whatever worth it may meta physically possess, does no good in psychology. My own sensationalistic account has derived most aid and comfort from the writings of Hering, A. W. Volkmann, Stumpf, Leconte, and Schon. All these authors allow ample scope to that Experience which Berkeley's genius saw to be a present factor in all our visual acts. But they give Experience some grist to grind, which the soi-distant ' empiristic ' school forgets to do. Stumpf seems to me the most philosophical and profound of all these writers ; and I owe him much. I should doubtless have owed almost as much to Mr. James Ward, had his article on Psychology in the Encyclopaedia Britannica appeared before my own thoughts were written down. The literature of the question is in all languages very voluminous. I content myself with referring to the bibliography in Helmholtz's and Aubert's works on Physiological Optics for the visual part of the subject, and with naming in a note the ablest works in the English tongue which have treated of the subject in a gen eral way.* * G. Berkeley : Essay towards a new Theory of Vision ; Samuel Bailey : A Review of Berkeley's Theory of Vision (1842) ; J. S. Mill's Review of Bailey, in his Dissertations and Disquisitions, vol. n ; Jas. Ferrier : Re view of Bailey, in 'Philosophical Remains,' vol. n ; A. Bain : Senses and Intellect, 'Intellect,' chap. I ; H. Spencer : Principles of Psychology, pt. vi. chaps, xiv, xvi ; J. S. Mill : Examination of Hamilton, chap, xui (the best statement of the so-called English empiricist position) ; T. K. Abbott : Sight and Touch, 1861 (the first English book to go at all mi nutely into facts; Mr. Abbott maintaining retinal sensations to be originally of space in three dimensions) ; A. C. Fraser : Review of Abbott, in North British Review for Aug. 1864 ; another review in Macmillan's Magazine, Aug. 1866 ; J. Sully : Outlines of Psychology, chap, vi ; J. Ward : En- cyclop. Britannica, 9th Ed., article ' Psychology,' pp. 53-5 ; J. E. Walter: The Perception of Space and Matter (1879).— I may also refer to a ' discus sion ' between Prof. G, Croorn Robertson, Mr. J. Ward, and the present writer, in Mind, vol. xm.— The present chapter is only the filling out with detail of an article entitled 'The Spatial Quale,' which appeared in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy for January 1879 (xin. 64). CHAPTEE XXL* THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. BELIEF. EVERYONE knows the difference between imagining a thing and believing in its existence, between supposing a proposition and acquiescing in its truth. In the case of acquiescence or belief, the object is not only apprehended by the mind, but is held to have reality. Belief is thus th& mental state or function of cognizing reality. As used in the following pages, ' Belief ' will mean every degree of as* surance, including the highest possible certainty and con viction. There are, as we know, two ways of studying every psychic state. First, the way of analysis: What does it consist in? What is its inner nature? Of what sort of mind-stuff is it composed ? Second, the way of history : What are its conditions of production, and its connection with other facts ? Into the first way we cannot go very far. In its inner nature, belief, or the sense of reality, is a sort of feeling more allied to the emotions than to anything else. Mr. Bagehot dis tinctly calls it the ' emotion ' of conviction. I just now spoke of it as acquiescence. It resembles more than any thing what in the psychology of volition we know as con sent. Consent is recognized by all to be a manifestation of our active nature. It would naturally be described by such terms as * willingness ' or the * turning of our dispo sition.' What characterizes both consent and belief is the cessation of theoretic agitation, through the advent of an idea which is inwardly stable, and fills the mind solidly to the exclusion of contradictory ideas. When this is the case, motor effects are apt to follow. Hence the states of * Reprinted, with additions, from ' Mind' for July 1889. 284 PSYCHOLOGY. consent and belief, characterized by repose on the purely intellectual side, are both intimately connected with subse quent practical activity. This inward stability of the mind's content is as characteristic of disbelief as of belief. But we shall presently see that we never disbelieve anything ex cept for the reason that we believe something else which contradicts the first thing.* Disbelief is thus an incidental complication to belief, and need not be considered by itself. The true opposites of belief, psychologically considered, are doubt and inquiry, not disbelief. In both these states the content of our mind is in unrest, and the emotion engen dered thereby is, like the emotion of belief itself, perfectly distinct, but perfectly indescribable in words. Both sorts of emotion may be pathologically exalted. One of the charms of drunkenness unquestionably lies in the deepen ing of the sense of reality and truth which is gained therein. In whatever light things may then appear to us, they seem more utterly what they are, more ' utterly utter ' than when we are sober. This goes to a fully unutterable extreme in the nitrous oxide intoxication, in which a man's very soul will sweat with conviction, and he be all the while unable to tell what he is convinced of at all.t The pathological state opposed to this solidity and deepening has been called the questioning mania ( Grubelsucht by the Germans). It is sometimes found as a substantive affection, paroxysmal or chronic, and consists in the inability to rest in any concep tion, and the need of having it confirmed and explained. * Why do I stand here where I stand ? ' ' Why is a glass a glass, a chair a chair ? ' ' How is it that men are only of the size they are ? Why not as big as houses,' etc., etc.J * Compare this psychological fact with the corresponding logical truth that all negation rests on covert assertion of something else than the thing denied. (See Bradley 's Principles of Logic, bk. i. ch. 3.) f See that very remarkable little work, ' The Anaesthetic Revelation and the Gist of Philosophy,' by Benj. P. Blood (Amsterdam, N. Y., 1874). Compare also Mind, vn. 206. J "To one whose mind is healthy thoughts come and go unnoticed; with me they have to be faced, thought about in a peculiar fashion, and then disposed of as finished, and this often when I am utterly wearied and would be at peace ; but the call is imperative. This goes on to the hiu- THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 285 There is, it is true, another pathological state which is as far removed from doubt as from belief, and which some may prefer to consider the proper contrary of the latter state of mind. I refer to the feeling that everything is hollow, unreal, dead. I shall speak of this state again upon a later page. The point I wish to notice here is sim ply that belief and disbelief are but two aspects of one psychic state. John Mill, reviewing various opinions about belief, comes to the conclusion that no account of it can be given : " What," he says, "is the difference to our minds between thinking of a reality and representing to ourselves an imaginary picture ? I con fess I can see no escape from the opinion that the distinction is ultimate and primordial. There is no more difficulty in holding it to be so than in holding the difference between a sensation and an idea to be primor dial. It seems almost another aspect of the same difference. ... I cannot help thinking, therefore, that there is in the remembrance of a real fact, as distinguished from that of a thought, an element which does not consist ... in a difference between the mere ideas which are present to the mind in the two cases. This element, howsoever we de fine it, constitutes belief, and is the difference between Memory and Imagination. From whatever direction we approach, this difference seems to close our path. When we arrive at it, we seem to have reached, as it were, the central point of our intellectual nature, presupposed and built upon in every attempt we make to explain the more recondite phenomena of our mental being."* drance of all natural action. If I were told that the staircase was on tire and I had only a minute to escape, and the thought arose — ' Have they sent for fire-engines? Is it probable that the man who has the key is on hand ? Is the man a careful sort of person ? Will the key be hanging on a peg? Am I thinking rightly? Perhaps they don't lock the depot '- my foot would be lifted to go down ; I should be conscious to excitement that I was losing my chance ; but I thould be unable to stir until all these absurdities were entertained and disposed of. In the most critical moments of my life, when I ought to have been so engrossed as to leave no room for any secondary thoughts, I have been oppressed by the inability to be at peace. And in the most ordinary circumstances it is all the same. Let me instance the other morning I went to walk. The day was biting cold, but I was unable to proceed except by jerks. Once I got arrested, my feet in a muddy pool. One foot was lifted to go, knowing that it was not good to be standing in water, but there I was fast, the cause of detention being the discussing with myself the reasons why I should not stand in that pool." (T. S. Clouston, Clinical Lectures on Mental Diseases, 1883, p. 43. See niao Berger, in Archiv f. Psychiatric, vi. 217.) * Note to Jas. Mill's Analysis, i. 412-423. 286 PSYCHOLOGY. If the words of Mill be taken to apply to the mere sub jective analysis of belief — to the question, What does it feel like when we have it ? — they must be held, on the whole, to be correct. Belief, the sense of reality, feels like itself — that is about as much as we can say. Prof. Brentano, in an admirable chapter of his Psycho logic, expresses this by saying that conception and belief (which he names judgment) are two different fundamental psychic phenomena. What I myself have called (Yol. I, p. 275) the ' object ' of thought may be comparatively simple, like "Ha! what a pain," or "It-thunders"; or it may be complex, like "Columbus-discovered-America-in-1492," or " There- exists-an-all-wise-Creator-of- the- world." In either case, however, the mere thought of the object may exist as something quite distinct from the belief in its reality. The belief, as Brentano says, presupposes the mere thought : "Every object comes into consciousness in a twofold way, as simply thought of \yorgestellt} and as admitted [anerkannt] or denied. The relation is analogous to that which is assumed by most philosophers (by Kant no less than by Aristotle) to obtain between mere thought and desire. Nothing is ever desired without being thought of; but the desiring is nevertheless a second quite new and peculiar form of rela tion to the object, a second quite new way of receiving it into consciousness. No more is anything judged [i. e., believed or disbelieved] which is not thought of too. But we must insist that, so soon as the object of a thought becomes the object of an assenting or rejecting judgment, our consciousness steps into an entirely new relation to wards it. It is then twice present in consciousness, as thought of, and as held for real or denied ; just as when desire awakens for it, it is both thought and simultaneously desired." (P. 266.) The commonplace doctrine of * judgment ' is that it consists in the combination of * ideas ' by a * copula ' into a ' proposition/ which may be of various sorts, as affir mative, negative, hypothetical, etc. But who does not see that in a disbelieved or doubted or interrogative or condi tional proposition, the ideas are combined in the same identical way in which they are in a proposition which is solidly believed ? The way in which the ideas are combined is a part of the inner constitution of the thought's object or content. That object is sometimes an articulated whole with relations between its parts, amongst which relations, that of predicate THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 287 to subject may be one. But when we have got our object with its inner constitution thus defined in a proposition, then the question comes up regarding the object as a whole : ' Is it a real object ? is this proposition a true proposition or not ? ' And in the answer Yes to this question lies that new psychic act which Brentano calls 'judgment,' but which 1 prefer to call ' belief.' In every proposition, then, so far as it is believed, ques tioned, or disbelieved, four elements are to be distinguished, the subject, the predicate, and their relation (of whatever sort it be) — these form the object of belief — and finally the psychic attitude in which our mind stands towards the proposition taken as a whole — and this is the belief itself.* Admitting, then, that this attitude is a state of conscious ness sui generis, about which nothing more can be said in the way of internal analysis, let us proceed to the second way of studying the subject of belief : Under what circum stances do we, think things real ? We shall soon see how much matter this gives us to discuss. THE VABIOTTS OBDEBS OF BEALITY. Suppose a new-born mind, entirely blank and waiting for experience to begin. Suppose that it begins in the form of a visual impression (whether faint or vivid is im material) of a lighted candle against a dark background, and nothing else, so that whilst this image lasts it consti tutes the entire universe known to the mind in question. Suppose, moreover (to simplify the hypothesis), that the candle is only imaginary, and that no 'original' of it is recognized by us psychologists outside. Will this hallu cinatory candle be believed in, will it have a real existence for the mind ? What possible sense (for that mind) would a suspicion have that the candle was not real ? What would doubt or disbelief of it imply ? When we, the onlooking psycholo gists, say the candle is unreal, we mean something quite definite, viz., that there is a world known to us which is * For an excellent account of the history of opinion on this subject tee A. Marty, in Vierteljahrsch. f. wiss. Phil., vin. 101 if. (1884). 288 PSYCHOLOGY. real, and to which we perceive that the candle does not belong ; it belongs exclusively to that individual mind, has no status anywhere else, etc. It exists, to be sure, in a fashion, for it forms the content of that mind's hallucina tion ; but the hallucination itself, though unquestionably it is a sort of existing fact, has no knowledge of other facts ; and since those other facts are the realities par excellence for us, and the only things we believe in, the candle is simply outside of our reality and belief altogether. By the hypothesis, however, the mind ivhich sees the candle can spin no such considerations as these about it, for of other facts, actual or possible, it has no inkling whatever. That candle is its all, its absolute. Its entire faculty of attention is absorbed by it. It is, it is that ; it is there ; no other possible candle, or quality of this candle, no other possible place, or possible object in the place, no alterna tive, in short, suggests itself as even conceivable ; so how can the mind help believing the candle real ? The suppo sition that it might possibly not do so is, under the sup posed conditions, unintelligible.* This is what Spinoza long ago announced : "Let us conceive a boy," he said, u imagining to himself a horse, and taking note of nothing else. As this imagination involves the ex istence of the horse, and the boy has no perception which annuls its existence, he will necessarily contemplate the horse as present, nor will he be able to doubt of its existence, however little certain of it he may be. I deny that a man in so far as he imagines [percipif] affirms noth ing. For what is it to imagine a winged horse but to affirm that the horse [that horse, namely] has wings ? For if the mind had nothing before it but the winged horse it would contemplate the same as pres ent, would have no cause to doubt of its existence, nor any power of dissenting from its existence, unless the imagination of the winged horse were joined to an idea which contradicted [tollit] its existence." (Ethics, ii. 49, Scholium.) The sense that anything we think of is unreal can only come, then, when that thing is contradicted by some other * We saw near the end of Chapter XIX that a candle-image taking ex clusive possession of the mind in this way would probably acquire the sensational vividness. But this physiological accident is logically im material to the argument in the text, which ought to apply as well to the dimmest sort of mental image as to the brightest sensation. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 289 thing of which we think. Any object which remains uncon- tradicted is ipso facto believed and posited as absolute reality. Now, how comes it that one thing though4; of can be con tradicted by another ? It cannot unless it begins the quar rel by saying something inadmissible about that other. Take the mind with the candle, or the boy with the horse. If either of them say, ' That candle or that horse, even when I don't see it, exists in the outer tvorld,' he pushes into * the outer world ' an object which may be incompatible with everything which he otherwise knows of that world. If so, he must take his choice of which to hold by, the present perceptions or the other knowledge of the world. If he holds to the other knowledge, the present perceptions are contradicted, so far as their relation to that world goes. Can dle and horse, whatever they may be, are not existents in outward space. They are existents, of course ; they are mental objects ; mental objects have existence as mental objects. But they are situated in their own spaces, the space in which they severally appear, and neither of those spaces is the space in which the realities called ' the outer world' exist. Take again the horse with wings. If I merely dream of a horse with wings, my horse interferes with nothing else and has not to be contradicted. That horse, its wings, and its place, are all equally real. That horse exists no other wise than as winged, and is moreover really there, for that place exists no otherwise than as the place of that horse, and claims as yet no connection with the other places of the world. But if with this horse I make an inroad into the world otherwise knoivn, and say, for example, ' That is my old mare Maggie, having grown a pair of wings where she stands in her stall,' the whole case is altered ; for now the horse and place are identified with a horse and place otherwise known, and what is known of the latter objects is incompatible with what is perceived with the former. ' Maggie in her stall with wings ! Never ! ' The wings are unreal, then, visionary. I have dreamed a lie about Mag gie in her stall. The reader will recognize in these two cases the two sorts of judgment called in the logic-books existential and 290 PSYCHOLOGY. attributive respectively. * The candle exists as an outer reality ' is an existential, ' My Maggie has got a pair of wings ' is an attributive, proposition ;* and it follows from what was first said that all propositions, whether attributive or existential, are believed through the very fact of being con ceived, unless they clash with other propositions believed, at the same time, by affirming that their terms are the same with the, terms of these other propositions. A dream-candle has exist ence, true enough ; but not the same existence (existence for itself, namely, or extra mentem meam) which the candles of waking perception have. A dream-horse has wings ; but then neither horse nor wings are the same with any horses or wings known to memory. That we can at any moment think of the same thing which at any former moment we thought of is the ultimate law of our intellectual constitu tion. But when we now think of it incompatibly with our other ways of thinking it, then we must choose which way to stand by, for we cannot continue to think in two contra dictory ways at once. The whole distinction of real and un real, the whole psychology of belief, disbelief, and doubt, is thus grounded on two mental facts— first, that we are liable to think differently of the same ; and second, that ivhen we have done so, we can choose which way of thinking to adhere to and ivhich to disregard. The subjects adhered to become real subjects, the at tributes adhered to real attributes, the existence adhered to real existence ; whilst the subjects disregarded become imaginary subjects, the attributes disregarded erroneous * In both existential and attributive judgments a synthesis is repre sented. The syllable ex in the word Existence, da in the word Dasein, ex press it. ' The candle exists ' is equivalent to ' The candle is over there" And the ' over there ' means real space, space related to other reals. The proposition amounts to saying : ' The candle is in the same space with other reals.' It affirms of the candle a very concrete predicate — namely, this relation to other particular concrete things. Their real existence, as we shall later see, resolves itself into their peculiar relation to ourselves. Existence is thus no substantive quality when we predicate it of any ob ject ; it is a relation, ultimately terminating in ourselves, and at the mo ment when it terminates, becoming a practical relation. But of this more anon., I only wish now to indicate the superficial nature of the distinction between the existential and the attributive proposition. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 291 attributes, and the existence disregarded an existence in no man's land, in the limbo ' where footless fancies dwell.' The real things are, in M. Taine's terminology, the reduc- tives of the things judged unreal. THE MATOTT WORLDS. Habitually and practically we do not count these disre garded things as existents at all. For them Fee victis is the law in the popular philosophy ; they are not even treated as appearances ; they are treated as if they were mere waste, equivalent to nothing at all. To the genuinely philosophic mind, however, they still have existence, though not the same existence, as the real things. As objects of fancy, as errors, as occupants of dreamland, etc., they are in their way as indefeasible parts of life, as undeniable features of the Universe, as the realities are in their way. The total world of which the philosophers must take account is thus composed of the realities plus the fancies and illusions. Two sub-universes, at least, connected by relations which philosophy tries to ascertain ! Eeally there are more than two sub-universes of which we take account, some of us of this one, and others of that. For there are various categories both of illusion and of reality, and alongside of the world of absolute error (i.e., error confined to single individuals) but still within the world of absolute reality (i.e., reality believed by the complete philosopher) there is the world of collective error, there are the worlds of abstract reality, of relative or practical reality, of ideal relations, and there is the supernatural world. The popular mind conceives of all these sub-worlds more or less discon nectedly ; and when dealing with one of them, forgets for the time being its relations to the rest. The complete phi losopher is he who seeks not only to assign to every given object of his thought its right place in one or other of these sub-worlds, but he also seeks to determine the relation of each sub-world to the others in the total world which is. The most important sub-universes commonly discrimi nated from each other and recognized by most of us as existing, each with its own special and separate style of existence, are the following : PS TCHOL OOT. (1) The world of sense, or of physical ' things ' as we instinctively apprehend them, with such qualities as heat, color, and sound, and such ' forces ' as life, chemical affinity, gravity, electricity, all existing as such within or on the surface of the things. (2) The world of science, or of physical things as the learned conceive them, with secondary qualities and ' forces ' (in the popular sense) excluded, and nothing real but solids and fluids and their 'laws' (i.e., customs) of motion.* (3) The world of ideal relations, or abstract truths be lieved or believable by all, and expressed in logical, mathe matical, metaphysical, ethical, or aesthetic propositions. (4) The world of ' idols of the tribe,' illusions or preju dices common to the race. All educated people recognize these as forming one sub-universe. The motion of the sky round the earth, for example, belongs to this world. That motion is not a recognized item of any of the other worlds ; but as an ' idol of the tribe ' it really exists. For certain philosophers * matter * exists only as an idol of the tribe. For science, the ' secondary qualities ' of matter are but * idols of the tribe.' (5) The various supernatural worlds, the Christian heaven and hell, the world of the Hindoo mythology, the world of Swedenborg's visa et audita, etc. Each of these is a consistent system, with definite relations among its own parts. Neptune's trident, e.g., has no status of reality what ever in the Christian heaven ; but within the classic Olym pus certain definite things are true of it, whether one believe in the reality of the classic mythology as a whole or not. The various worlds of deliberate fable may be ranked with these worlds of faith — the world of the Iliad, that of King Lear, of the Pickwick Papers, etc.f * I define the scientific universe here in the radical mechanical way. Practically, it is oftener thought of in a mongrel way and resembles in more points the popular physical world. f It thus comes about that we can say such things as that Ivanhoe did not really marry Rebecca, as Thackeray falsely makes him do. The real Ivanhoe-world is the one which Scott wrote down for us. In that world Ivanhoe does not marry Rebecca. The objects within that world are knit together by perfectly definite relations, which can be affirmed or denied. "Whilst absorbed in the novel, we turn our backs on all other THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 293 (6) The various worlds of individual opinion, as numer ous as men are. (7) The worlds of sheer madness and vagary, also in definitely numerous. Every object we think of gets at last referred to one world or another of this or of some similar list. It settles into our be lief as a common-sense object, a scientific object, an abstract object, a mythological object, an object of some one's mis taken conception, or a madman's object ; and it reaches this state sometimes immediately, but often only after be ing hustled and bandied about amongst other objects until it finds some which will tolerate its presence and stand in relations to it which nothing contradicts. The molecules and ether-waves of the scientific world, for example, simply kick the object's warmth and color out, they refuse to Lave any relations with them. But the world of < idols of the tribe ' stands ready to take them in. Just so the world of classic myth takes up the winged horse ; the world of individual hallucination, the vision of the candle ; the world of abstract truth, the proposition that justice is kingly, though no actual king be just. The various worlds themselves, however, appear (as aforesaid) to most men's minds in no very definitely conceived relation to each other, and our attention, when it turns to one, is apt to drop the others for the time being out of its account. Pro positions concerning the different worlds are made from 1 different points of view'; and in this more or less chaotic state the consciousness of most thinkers remains to the end. Each world whilst it is attended to is real after its own fashion ; only the reality lapses with the attention. THE 'WORLD OP 'PRACTICAL REALITIES.' Each thinker, however, has dominant habits of atten tion ; and these practically elect from among the various worlds some one to be for him the world of ultimate realities. From this world's objects he does not appeal. Whatever worlds, and, for the time, the Ivanhoe-world remains our absolute reality. When we wake from the spell, however, we find a still more real world, which reduces Ivanhoe, and all things connected with him, to the fictive atatus, and relegates them to one of the sub-universes grouped under No. 5. PSYCHOLOGY. positively contradicts them must get into another world or die. The horse, e.g., may have wings to its heart's content, so long as it does not pretend to be the real world's horse — that horse is absolutely wingless. For most men, as we shall immediately see, the ' things of sense ' hold this prerogative position, and are the absolutely real world's nucleus. Other things, to be sure, may be real for this man or for that — things of science, abstract moral relations, things of the Christian theology, or what not. But even for the special man, these things are usually real with a less real reality than that of the things of sense. They are taken less seriously ; and the very utmost that can be said for any one's belief in them is that it is as strong as his * belief in his own senses.' * In all this the everlasting partiality of our nature shows itself, our inveterate propensity to choice. For, in the strict and ultimate sense of the word existence, everything which can be thought of at all exists as some sort of object, whether mythical object, individual thinker's object, or ob ject in outer space and for intelligence at large. Errors, fictions, tribal beliefs, are parts of the whole great Universe which God has made, and He must have meant all these things to be in it, each in its respective place. But for us finite creatures, " 'tis to consider too curiously to consider * The world of dreams is our real world whilst we are sleeping, because our attention then lapses from the sensible world. Conversely, when we wake the attention usually lapses from the dream-world and that becomes unreal. But if a dream haunts us and compels our attention during the day it is very apt to remain figuring in our consciousness as a sort of sub- universe alongside of the waking world. Most people have probably had dreams which it is hard to imagine not to have been glimpses into an actually existing region of being, perhaps a corner of the ' spiritual world.' And dreams have accordingly in all ages been regarded as revelations, and have played a large part in furnishing forth mythologies and creating themes for faith to lay hold upon. The 'larger universe,' here, which helps us to believe both in the dream and in the waking reality which is its immediate reductive, is the total universe, of Nature plus the Super natural. The dream holds true, namely, in one half of that universe ; the waking perceptions in the other half. Even to-day dream-objects figure among the realities in which some ' psychic- researchers ' are seeking to rouse our belief . All our theories, not only those about the supernatural, but our philosophic and scientific theories as well, are like our dreams in rous ing such different degrees of belief in different minds. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 295 so." The mere fact of appearing as an object at all is not enough to constitute reality. That may be metaphysical reality, reality for God ; but what we need is practical reality, reality for ourselves ; and, to have that, an object must not only appear, but it must appear both interesting and important. The worlds whose objects are neither in teresting nor important we treat simply negatively, we brand them as unreal. In the relative sense, then, the sense in which ^e contrast reality with simple unreality, and in which one thing is said to have more reality than another, and to be more be lieved, reality means simply relation to our emotional and active life. This is the only sense which the word ever has in the mouths of practical men. In this sense, whatever ex cites and stimulates our interest is real ; whenever an object so appeals to us that we turn to it, accept it, fill our mind with it, or practically take account of it, so far it is real for us, and we believe it. Whenever, on the contrary, we ignore it, fail to consider it or act upon it, despise it, reject it, forget it, so far it is unreal for us and disbelieved. Hume's account of the matter was then essentially correct, when he said that belief in anything was simply the having the idea of it in a lively and active manner : " I say, then, that belief is nothing but a more vivid, lively, forcible, firm, steady conception of an object than the imagination alone is ever able to attain. ... It consists not in the peculiar nature or order of the ideas, but in the manner of their conception and in their feeling to the mind. I confess that it is impossible perfectly to explain this feel ing or manner of conception. ... Its true and proper name ... is belief, which is a term that everyone sufficiently understands in common life. And in philosophy we can go no farther than assert that belief ia something felt by themind, which distinguishes the idea of the judg ment from the fictions of the imagination.* It gives them more weight and influence ; makes them appear of greater importance ; enforces them in the mind ; gives them a superior influence on the passions, and renders them the governing principle in our actions. " t * Distinguishes realities from unrealities, the essential from the rubbishy and neglectable. f Inquiry concerning Hum. Understanding, sec. v. pt. 2 (slightly trans posed in my quotation). 296 PSYCHOLOGY. Or as Prof. Bain puts it : "In its essential character, belief is a phase of our active nature — otherwise called the Will." * The object of belief, then, reality or real existence, is something quite different from all the other predicates which a subject may possess. Those are properties intellectually or sensibly intuited. When we add any one of them to the subject, we increase the intrinsic content of the latter, we enrich its picture in our mind. But adding reality does not enrich the picture in any such inward way ; it leaves it inwardly as it finds it, and only fixes it and stamps it in to us. " The real," as Kant says, "contains no more than the possible. A hundred real dollars do not contain a penny more than a hundred pos sible dollars. ... By whatever, and by however many, predicates I may think a thing, nothing is added to it if I add that the thing exists. Whatever, therefore, our concept of an object may contain, we must always step outside of it in order to attribute to it existence." t The ' stepping outside ' of it is the establishment either of immediate practical relations between it and ourselves, or of relations between it and other objects with which we have immediate practical relations. Relations of this sort, which are as yet not transcended or superseded by others, are ipso facto real relations, and confer reality upon their objective term. Thefons et origo of oil reality, whether from * Note to Jas. Mill's Analysis, i. 394. f Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Muller, u. 515-17. Hume also : "When, after the simple conception of anything, we would conceive it as existent, we in reality make no addition to, or alteration of, our first idea. Thus, when we affirm that God is existent, we simply form the idea of such a being as He is represented to us ; nor is the existence which we at tribute to Him conceived by a particular idea, which we join to His other qualities, and can again separate and distinguish from them. . . . The be lief of the existence joins no new idea to those which compose the ideas of the object. When I think of God, when I think of Him as existent, and when I believe Him to be existent, my idea of Him neither increases nor diminishes. But as 'tis certain there is a great difference betwixt the sim ple conception of the existence of an object and the belief of it, and as this difference lies not in the facts or compositions of the idea which we con ceive, it follows that it must lie in the manner in which we conceive it." (Treatise of Human Nature, pt. in. sec. 7.) THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 297 the absolute or the practical point of view, is thus subjective, is ourselves. As bare logical thinkers, without emotional re action, we give reality to whatever objects we think of, for they are really phenomena, or objects of our passing thought, if nothing more. But, as thinkers ivith emotional reaction, we give what seems to us a still higher degree of reality to whatever things we select and emphasize and turn to WITH A WILL. These are our living realities; and not only these, but all the other things which are intimately connected with these. Keality, starting from our Ego, thus sheds itself from point to point — first, upon all objects which have an immediate sting of interest for our Ego in them, and next, upon the objects most continuously related with these. It only fails when the connecting thread is lost. A whole system may be real, if it only hang to our Ego by one immediately stinging term. But what contra dicts any such stinging term, even though it be another stinging term itself, is either not believed, or only believed after settlement of the dispute. We reach thus the important conclusion that our own reality, that sense of our own life which ive at every moment pos sess, is the ultimate of ultimates for our belief. ' As sure as I exist ! ' — this is our uttermost warrant for the being of all other things. As Descartes made the indubitable reality of the cogito go bail for the reality of all that the cogito in volved, so we all of us, feeling our own present reality with absolutely coercive force, ascribe an all but equal degree of reality, first to whatever things we lay hold on with a sense of personal need, and second, to whatever farther things continuously belong with these. " Mein Jetzt und Hier," as Prof. Lipps says, " ist der letzte Angelpunkt fur alle Wirklichkeit, also alle Erkenntniss." The world of living realities as contrasted with unreali ties is thus anchored in the Ego, considered as an active and emotional term.* That is the hook from which the rest dangles, the absolute support. And as from a painted * I use the notion of the Ego here, as common-sense uses it. Nothing is prejudged as to the results (or absence of results) of ulterior attempts to analyze the notion. 298 PSYCHOLOGY. hook it has been said that one can only hang a painted chain, so conversely, from a real hook only a real chain can properly be hung. Whatever tilings have intimate and continuous connection with my life are things of whose reality I cannot doubt. Whatever things fail to establish this con nection are things which are practically no better for me than if they existed not at all. In certain forms of melancholic perversion of the sensi bilities and reactive powers, nothing touches us intimately, rouses us, or wakens natural feeling. The consequence is the complaint so often heard from melancholic patients, that nothing is believed in by them as it used to be, and that all sense of reality is fled from life. They are sheathed in india-rubber ; nothing penetrates to the quick or draws blood, as it were. According to Griesinger, " I see, I hear !" such patients say, ' but the objects do not reach me, it is as if there were a wall between me and the outer world !" 4k In such patients there often is an alteration of the cutaneous sen sibility, such that things feel indistinct or sometimes rough and woolly. But even were this change always present, it would not completely ex plain the psychic phenomenon . . . which reminds us more of the altera tion in our psychic relations to the outer world which advancing age on the one hand, and on the other emotions and passions, may bring about. In childhood we feel ourselves to be closer to the world of sensible phenomena, we live immediately with them and in them; an intimately vital tie binds us and them together. But with the ripening of reflec tion this tie is loosened, the warmth of our interest cools, things look differently to us, and we act more as foreigners to the outer world, even though we know it a great deal better. Joy and expansive emotions in general draw it nearer to us again. Everything makes a more lively impression, and with the quick immediate return of this warm recep tivity for sense impressions, joy makes us feel young again. In depress ing emotions it is the other way. Outer things, whether living or in organic, suddenly grow cold and foreign to us, and even our favorite objects of interest feel as if. they belonged to us no more. Under these circumstances, receiving no longer from anything a lively impression, we cease to turn towards outer things, and the sense of inward loneliness grows upon us. . . . Where there is no strong intelligence to control this blase condition, this psychic coldness and lack of interest, the issue of these states in which all seems so cold and hollow, the heart dried up, the world grown dead and empty, is often suicide or the deeper forms of insanity.* * Griesinger, Mental Diseases, $§ 50, 98. The neologism we so often. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 299 THE PARAMOUNT REALITY OF SENSATIONS. But DOW we are met by questions of detail. What does this stirring, this exciting power, this interest, consist in, which some objects have ? which are those * intimate rela tions ' with our life which give reality ? And what things stand in these relations immediately, and what others are so closely connected with the former that (in Hume's lan guage) we ' carry our disposition ' also on to them ? In a simple and direct way these questions cannot be answered at all. The whole history of human thought is but an unfinished attempt to answer them. For what have men been trying to find out, since men were men, but just those things : " Where do our true interests lie — which re lations shall we call the intimate and real ones — which things shall we call living realities and which not ?" A few psychological points can, however, be made clear. Any relation to our mind at all, in the absence of a stronger relation, suffices to make an object real. The barest appeal to our attention is enough for that. Eevert to the begin ning of the chapter, and take the candle entering ifche vacant mind. The mind was waiting for just some such object to make its spring upon. It makes its spring and the candle is believed. But when the candle appears at the same time with other objects, it must run the gauntlet of their rivalry, and then it becomes a question which of the various candi dates for attention shall compel belief. As a rule we be lieve as much as we can. We would believe everything if we only could. When objects are represented by us quite unsystematically they conflict but little with each other, and the number of them which in this chaotic manner we can believe is limitless. The primitive savage's mind is a jungle in which hallucinations, dreams, superstitions, con ceptions, and sensible objects all flourish alongside of each other, unregulated except by the attention turning in this way or in that. The child's mind is the same. It is only as objects become permanent and their relations fixed that hear, that an experience * gives us a realizing sense ' of the truth of some proposition or other, illustrates the dependence of the sense of reality upon excitement. Only what stirs us is ' realized.' 300 PSYCHOLOGY. discrepancies and contradictions are felt and must be set tled in some stable way. As a rule, the success with which a contradicted object maintains itself in our belief is pro portional to several qualities which it must possess. Of these the one which would be put first by most people, because it characterizes objects of sensation, is its — (1) Coerciveness over attention, or the mere power to consciousness : then follow — (2) Liveliness, or sensible pungency, especially in the way of exciting pleasure or pain ; (3) Stimulating effect upon the will, i.e., capacity to arouse active impulses, the more instinctive the better ; (4) Emotional interest, as object of love, dread, admira tion, desire, etc. ; (5) Congruity with certain favorite forms of contempla tion — unity, simplicity, permanence, and the like ; (6) Independence of other causes, and its own causal importance. These characters run into each other. Coerciveness is the result of liveliness or emotional interest. What is lively and interesting stimulates eo ipso the will ; congruity holds of active impulses as well as of contemplative forms ; causal independence and importance suit a certain contemplative demand, etc. I will therefore abandon all attempt at a formal treatment, and simply proceed to make remarks in the most convenient order of exposition. As a whole, sensations are more lively and are judged more real than conceptions ; things met with every hour more real than things seen once ; attributes perceived when awake, more real than attributes perceived in a dream. But, owing to the diverse relations contracted by .the various objects with each other, the simple rule that the lively and permanent is the real is often enough disguised. A con ceived thing may be deemed more real than a certain sen sible thing, if it only be intimately related to other sensible things more vivid, permanent, or interesting than the first one. Conceived molecular vibrations, e.g., are by the physicist judged more real than felt warmth, because so intimately related to all those other facts of motion in the THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 301 world which he has made his special study. Similarly, a rare thing may be deemed more real than a permanent thing if it be more widely related to other permanent things. All the occasional crucial observations of science are examples of this. A rare experience, too, is likely to be judged more real than a permanent one, if it be more in teresting and exciting. Such is the sight of Saturn through a telescope ; such are the occasional insights and illumi nations which upset our habitual ways of thought. But no mere floating conception, no mere disconnected rarity, ever displaces vivid things or permanent things from our belief. A conception, to prevail, must terminate in the world of orderly sensible experience. A rare phenomenon, to displace frequent ones, must belong with others more frequent still. The history of science is strewn with wrecks and ruins of theory — essences and principles, fluids and forces — once fondly clung to, but found to hang together with no facts of sense. And exceptional phenomena solicit our belief in vain until such time as we chance to conceive them as of kinds already admitted to exist. What science means by * verification ' is no more than this, that no object of conception shall be believed which sooner or later has not some permanent and vivid object of sensation for its term. Compare what was said on pages 3-7, above. Sensible objects are thus either our realities or the tests of our realities. Conceived objects must show sensible effects or else be disbelieved. And the effects, even though reduced to relative unreality when their causes come to view (as heat, which molecular vibrations make unreal), are yet the things on which our knowledge of the causes rests. Strange mutual dependence this, in which the appearance needs the reality in order to exist, but the reality needs the appearance in order to be known ! Sensible vividness or pungency is then the vital factor in reality when once the conflict between objects, and the connecting of them together in the mind, has begun. No object which neither possesses this vividness in its own right nor is able to borrow it from anything else has a chance of making headway against vivid rivals, or of rousing in us that re action in which belief consists. On the vivid objects we 302 PS YCHOLOG T. pin, as the saying is, our faitli in all the rest ; and our belief returns instinctively even to those of them from which reflection has led it away. Witness the obduracy with which the popular world of colors, sounds, and smjlls holds its own against that of molecules and vibrations. Let the physicist himself but nod, like Homer, and the world of sense becomes his absolute reality again.* That things originally devoid of this stimulating power should be enabled, by association with other things which have it, to compel our belief as if they had it themselves, is a remarkable psychological fact, which since Hume's time it has been impossible to overlook. "The vividness of the first conception," he writes, "diffuses itself along the relations and is conveyed, as by so many pipes or channels, to every idea that has any communication with the primary one. . . . Superstitious people are fond of the relics of saints and holy men, for the same reason that they seek after types and images, in order to enliven their devotion and give them a more intimate and strong conception of those exemplary lives. . . . Now, 'tis evident one of the best relics a devotee could procure would be the handiwork of a saint, and if his clothes and furniture are ever to be considered in this light, 'tis because they were once at his disposal, and were moved and affected by him; in which respect they are ... connected with him by a shorter train of consequences than any of those from which we learn the reality of his * The way in which sensations are pitted against systematized concep tions, and in which the one or the other then prevails according as the sensations are felt by ourselves or merely known by report, is interestingly illustrated at the present day by the state of public belief about ' spiritual istic ' phenomena. There exist numerous narratives of movement without contact on the part of articles of furniture and other material objects, in the presence of certain privileged individuals called mediums. Such move ment violates our memories, and the whole system of accepted physical 'science.' Consequently those who have not seen it either brand the narratives immediately as lies or call the phenomena ' illusions ' of sense, produced by fraud or due to hallucination. But one who has actually seen such a phenomenon, under what seems to him sufficiently ' test-conditions,' will hold to his sensible experience through thick and thin, even though the whole fabric of ' science ' should be rent in twain. That man would 'be a weak-spirited creature indeed who should allow any fly blown gener alities about ' the liability of the senses to be deceived ' to bully him out of his adhesion to what for him was an indubitable experience of sight. A man may err in this obstinacy, sure enough, in any particular case. But the spirit that animates him is that on which ultimately the very life and health of Science rest. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 303 •existence. This phenomenon clearly proves that a present impression, with a relation of causation, may enliven any idea, and consequently produce belief or assent, according to the precedent definition of it. ... It has been remarked among the Mahometans as well as Christians that those pilgrims who have seen Mecca or the Holy Land are ever after more faithful and zealous believers than those who have not had that advantage. A man whose memory presents him with a lively image of the Red Sea and the Desert and Jerusalem and Galilee can never doubt of any miraculous events which are related either by Moses or the Evangelists. The lively idea of the places passes by an easy transition to the facts which are supposed to have been related to them by contiguity, and increases the belief by increasing the vivacity of the conception. The remembrance of those fields and rivers has the same influence as a new argument. . . . The ceremonies of the Catholic religion may be considered as instances of the same nature. The devotees of that strange superstition usually plead in excuse for the mummeries with which they are upbraided that they feel the good effect of external motions and postures and actions in enlivening their devotion and quickening their fervor, which otherwise would decay, if directed entirely to distant and immaterial objects. We shadow out the objects of our faith, say they, in sensible types and images, and render them more present to us by the immediate presence of these types than it is possible for us to do merely by an intellectual view and contemplation." * Hume's cases are rather trivial ; and the things which associated sensible objects make us believe in are supposed by him to be unreal. But all the more manifest for that is the fact of their psychological influence. Who does not * realize' more the fact of a dead or distant friend's existence, at the moment when a portrait, letter, garment or other material reminder of him is found ? The whole notion of him then grows pungent and speaks to us and shakes us, in a manner unknown at other times. In chil dren's minds, fancies and realities live side by side. But however lively their fancies may be, they still gain help from association with reality. The imaginative child identifies its dramatis personal with some doll or other material object, and this evidently solidifies belief, little as it may resemble what it is held to stand for. A thing not too interesting by its own real qualities generally does the best service here. The most useful doll I ever saw was a large cucumber in the hands of a little Amazonian-Indian * Treatise of Human Nature, bk. i. pt. in. sec. 7. 304 PSYCHOLOGY. girl ; she nursed it and washed it and rocked it to sleep in a hammock, and talked to it all day long — there was no part in life which the cucumber did not play. Says Mr. Tylor : "An imaginative child will make a dog do duty for a horse, or a sol dier for a shepherd, till at last the objective resemblance almost disap pears, and a bit of wood may be dragged about, resembling a ship on the sea or a coach on the road. Here the likeness of the bit of wood to a ship or coach is very slight indeed; but it is a thing, and can be moved about, . . . and is an evident assistance to the child in enabling it to arrange and develop its ideas. ... Of how much use . . . may be seen by taking it away, and leaving the child nothing to play with. . . . In later years and among highly educated people the mental process which goes on in a child's playing with wooden soldiers and horses, though it never disappears, must be sought for in more complex phe nomena. Perhaps nothing in after-life more closely resembles the effect of a doll upon a child than the effect of the illustrations of a tale upon a grown reader. Here the objective resemblance is very indefinite . . . yet what reality is given to the scene by a good picture. . . . Mr. Back house one day noticed in Van Diemen's Land a woman arranging several stones that were flat, oval, and about two inches wide, and marked in various directions with black and red lines. These, he learned, represented absent friends, and one larger than the rest stood for a fat native woman on Flinder's Island, known by the name of Mother Brown. Similar practices are found among far higher races than the ill-fated Tasmanians. Among some North American tribes a mother who has lost a child keeps its memory ever present to her by filling its cradle with black feathers and quills, and carrying it about with her for a year or more. When she stops anywhere, she sets up the cradle and talks to it as she goes about her work, just as she would have done if the dead body had been still alive within it. Here we have an image; but in Africa we find a rude doll representing the child, kept as a memorial. . . . Bastian saw Indian women in Peru who had lost an infant carrying about on their backs a wooden doll to represent it."* To many persons among us, photographs of lost ones seem to be fetishes. They, it is true, resemble ; but the fact that the mere materiality of the reminder is almost as important as its resemblance is shown by the popularity a hundred years ago of the black taffeta ' silhouettes ' which are still found among family relics, and of one of which Fichte could write to his affianced : ' Die Farbe fehlt, das Auge fehlt, es fehlt der himmlische Ausdruck deiner lieblichen * Early Hist, of Mankind, p. 108- TUB PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 305 Zilge ' — and yet go on worshipping it all the same. The opinion so stoutly professed by many, that language is es sential to thought, seems to have this much of truth in it, that all our inward images tend invincibly to attach them selves to something sensible, so as to gain in corporeity and life. Words serve this purpose, gestures serve it, stones, straws, chalk-marks, anything will do. As soon as anyone of these things stands for the idea, the latter seems to be more real. Some persons, the present writer among the number, can hardly lecture without a black-board : the ab stract conceptions must be symbolized by letters, squares or circles, and the relations between them by lines. All this symbolism, linguistic, graphic, and dramatic, has other uses too, for it abridges thought and fixes terms. But one of its uses is surely to rouse the believing reaction and give to the ideas a more living reality. As, when we are told a story, and shown the very knife that did the murder, the very ring whose hiding-place the clairvoyant revealed, the whole thing passes from fairy -land to mother-earth, so here we believe all the more, if only we see that ' the bricks are alive to tell the tale.' So much for the prerogative position of sensations in regard to our belief. But among the sensations themselves all are not deemed equally real. The more practically important ones, the more permanent ones, and the more aesthetically apprehensible ones are selected from the mass, to be believed in most of all ; the others are degraded to the position of mere signs and suggestions of these. This fact has already been adverted to in former chapters.* The real color of a thing is that one color-sensation which it gives us when most favorably lighted for vision. So of its real size, its real shape, etc. — these are but optical sensations selected out of thousands of others, because they have aesthetic characteristics which appeal to our convenience or delight. But I will not repeat what I have already written about this matter, but pass on to our treatment of tactile and muscular sensations, as ' primary * See Vol. I. pp. 285-6; Vol. II. pp. 237 ff. 306 PSYCHOLOGY. qualities,' more real than those ' secondary ' qualities which eye and ear and nose reveal. "Why do we thus so markedly select the tangible to be the real ? Our motives are not far to seek. The tangible qualities are the least fluctuating. "When we get them at all we get them the same. The other qualities fluctuate enormously as our relative position to the object changes. Then, more decisive still, the tactile properties are those most intimately connected with our weal or woe. A dagger hurts us only when in contact with our skin, a poison only when we take it into our mouths, and we can only use an object for our advantage when we have it in our muscular control. It is as tangibles, then, that things concern us most ; and the other senses, so far as their practical use goes, do but warn us of what tangi ble things to expect. They are but organs of anticipa tory touch, as Berkeley has with perfect clearness ex plained.* Among all sensations, the most belief-compelling are those productive of pleasure or of pain. Locke expressly makes the pleasure- or pain-giving quality to be the ultimate human criterion of anything's reality. Discussing (with a supposed Berkeleyan before Berkeley) the notion that all our perceptions may be but a dream, he says : " He may please to dream that I make him this answer . . . that I believe he will allow a very manifest difference between dreaming of being in the fire and being actually in it. But yet if he be resolved to appear so sceptical as to maintain that what I call being actually in the fire is nothing but a dream, and that we cannot thereby certainly know that any such thing as fire actually exists without us, I answer that we, certainly finding that pleasure or pain [or emotion of any sort] follows upon the application of certain objects to us, whose existence we per ceive, or dream that we perceive by our senses, this certainly is as great as our happiness or misery, beyond which we have no concernment to know or to be." f * See Theory of Vision, § 59. f Essay, bk. iv. chap. 2, § 14. In another place: "He that sees a candle burning and hath experimented the force of its flame by putting his finger into it, will little doubt that this is something existing without him, which does 'hirn harm and puts him to great pain. . . . And if our dreamer pleases to try whether the glowing heat of a glass furnace be barely a wandering imagination in a drowsy man's fancy by putting his hand into it, he may, perhaps, be awakened into a certainty greater than THE PERCEPTION OF EEALITT. 307 THE INFLUENCE OF EMOTION AND ACTIVE IMPULSE ON BELIEF. The quality of arousing emotion, of shaking, moving us or inciting us to action, has as much to do with our belief in an object's reality as the quality of giving pleasure or pain. In Chapter XXIV I shall seek to show that our emotions probably owe their pungent quality to the bodily sensations which they involve. Our tendency to believe in emotionally exciting objects (objects of fear, desire, etc.) is thus ex plained without resorting to any fundamentally new prin ciple of choice. Speaking generally, the more a conceived object excites us, the more reality it has. The same object excites us differently at different times. Moral and religious truths come ' home ' to us far more on some occasions than on others. As Emerson says, " There is a difference between one and another hour of life in their authority and subse quent effect. Our faith comes in moments, . . . yet there is a depth in those brief moments which constrains us to ascribe more reality to them than to all other experiences." The ' depth ' is partly, no doubt, the insight into wider sys tems of unified relation, but far more often than that it is the emotional thrill. Thus, to descend to more trivial ex amples, a man who has no belief in ghosts by daylight will temporarily believe in them when, alone at midnight, he feels his blood curdle at a mysterious sound or vision, his heart thumping, and his legs impelled to flee. The thought of falling when we walk along a curbstone awakens no emo tion of dread ; so no sense of reality attaches to it, and we are sure we shall not fall. On a precipice's edge, however, the sickening emotion which the notion of a possible fall engenders makes us believe in the latter's imminent reality, and quite unfits us to proceed. he could wish, that it is something more than bare imagination. So that the evidence is as great as we can desire, being as certain to us as our pleas ure or pain, i.e. happiness or misery; beyond which we have no concern ment, either of knowledge or being. Such an assurance of the existence of things without us is sufficient to direct us in the attaining the good and avoiding the evil which is caused by them, which is the important con cernment we have of being made acquainted with them. " (Ibid, bk. iv. chap. 11, § 8.) 308 PSYCHOLOGY. The greatest proof that a man is sui compos is his ability to suspend belief in presence of an emotionally exciting idea. To give this power is the highest result of education. In untutored minds the power does not exist. Every excit ing thought in the natural man carries credence with it. To conceive with passion is eo ipso to affirm. As Bagehot says : "The Caliph Omar burnt the Alexandrian Library, saying: 'All books which contain what is not in the Koran are dangerous. All which contain what is in it are useless ! ' Probably no one ever had an intenser belief in anything than Omar had in this. Yet it is impossible to imagine it preceded by an argument. His belief in Mahomet, in the Koran, and in the sufficiency of the Koran, probably came to him in spontaneous rushes of emotion ; there may have been little vestiges of argument floating here and there, but they did not justify the strength of the emotion, still less did they create it, and they hardly even excused it. ... Probably, when the subject is thoroughly examined, conviction will be found to be one of the intensest of human emotions, and one most closely connected with the bodily state, . . . accompanied or pre ceded by the sensation that Scott makes his seer describe as the prelude of a prophecy : ' At length the fatal answer came, In characters of living flame — Not spoke in words, nor blazed in scroll, But borne and branded on my soul.' A hot flash seems to burn across the brain. Men in these intense states of mind have altered all history, changed for better or worse the creed of myriads, and desolated or redeemed provinces or ages. Nor is this intensity a sign of truth, for it is precisely strongest in those points in which men differ most from each other. John Knox felt it in his anti- Catholicism ; Ignatius Loyola in his anti-Protestantism; and both, I suppose, felt it as much as it is possible to feel it." * The reason of the belief is undoubtedly the bodily com motion which the exciting idea sets up. * Nothing which I can feel like that can be false.' All our religious and supernatural beliefs are of this order. The surest warrant for immortality is the yearning of our bowels for our dear ones ; for God, the sinking sense it gives us to imagine no such Providence or help. So of our political or pecuniary hopes and fears, and things and persons dreaded and * W. Bagehot, 'The Emotion of Conviction,' Literary Studies, L 412-17. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 309 desired. " A grocer has a full creed as to foreign policy, a young lady a complete theory of the sacraments, as to which neither has any doubt. ... A girl in a country par sonage will be sure that Paris never can be taken, or that Bismarck is a wretch " — all because they have either con ceived these things at some moment with passion, or asso ciated them with other things which they have conceived with passion. M. Kenouvier calls this belief of a thing for no other reason than that we conceive it with passion, by the name of mental vertigo.* Other objects whisper doubt or dis belief ; but the object of passion makes us deaf to all but itself, and we affirm it unhesitatingly. Such objects are the delusions of insanity, which the insane person can at odd moments steady himself against, but which again return to sweep him off his feet. Such are the revelations of mysti cism. Such, particularly, are the sudden beliefs which ani mate mobs of men when frenzied impulse to action is involved. Whatever be the action in point — whether the stoning of a prophet, the hailing of a conqueror, the burn ing of a witch, the baiting of a heretic or Jew, the starting of a forlorn hope, or the flying from a foe — the fact that to believe a certain object will cause that action to explode is a sufficient reason for that belief to come. The motor im pulse sweeps it unresisting in its train. The whole history of witchcraft and early medicine is a commentary on the facility with which anything which chances to be conceived is believed the moment the belief chimes in with an emotional mood. 'The cause of sickness?' When a savage asks the cause of anything he means to ask exclusively * What is to blame ? ' The theoretic curiosity starts from the practical life's demands. Let some one then accuse a necromancer, suggest a charm or spell which has been cast, and no more ' evidence ' is asked for. What evi dence is required beyond this intimate sense of the culprit's responsibility, to which our very viscera and limbs reply ? f * Psychologic Rationnelle, cb. 12. f Two examples out of a thousand : Reid, Inquiry, ch. n. § 9: "I remember, many years ago, a white ox was brought into the country, of so enormous size that people came many 810 PSYCHOLOGY. Human credulity in the way of therapeutics has similar psychological roots. If there is anything intolerable (espe cially to the heart of a woman), it is to do nothing when a miles to see him. There happened, some months after, an uncommon fatality among women in child-bearing. Two such uncommon events, fol lowing one another, gave a suspicion of their connection, and occasioned a common opinion among the country people that the white ox was the cause of this fatality." H. M. Stanley, Through the Dark Continent, 11. 888 : " On the third day of our stay at Mowa, feeling quite comfortable amongst the people, on account of their friendly bearing, I began to write in my note-book the terms for articles, in order to improve my already copious vocabulary of native words. I had proceeded only a few minutes when I observed i strange commotion amongst the people who had been flocking about me, and presently they ran away. In a short time we heard war-cries ringing loudly and shrilly over the table-land. Two hours afterwards a long line of warriors were seen descending the table-land and advancing towards our camp. There may have been between five and six hundred of them. We, on the other hand, had made but few preparations except such as. would justify us replying to them in the event of the actual commence ment of hostilities. But I had made many firm friends among them, and I firmly believed that I should be able to avert an open rupture. When they had assembled at about a hundred yards in front of our camp, Safeui and I walked up towards them and sat down midway. Some half-dozen of the Mowa people came near, and the shauri began. "'What is the matter, my friends?' I asked. ' Why do you come with guns in your hands, in such numbers, as though you were corning to fight ? Fight ? fight us, your friends ! Tut ! this is some great mis take, surely.' "Mundele," replied one of them, . . . 'our people saw you yesterday make marks on some tara-tara [paper]. This is very bad. Our country will waste, our goats will die, our bananas will rot, and our women will dry up. What have we done to you that you should wish to kill us ? We have sold you food and we have brought you wine each day. Your people are allowed to wander where they please without trouble. Why is the Mundele so wicked ? We have gathered together to fight you if you do not burn that tara-tara now before our eyes. If you burn it we go away, and shall be your friends as heretofore.' "I told them to rest there, and left Safeni in their hands as a pledge that I should return. My tent was not fifty yards from the spot, but while going towards it my brain was busy in devising some plan to foil this superstitious madness. M.J note-book contained a vast number of val uable notes. ... I could not sacrifice it to the childish caprice of savages. As I was rummaging my book-box, I came across a volume of Shakespeare [Chandos edition] much worn, and well thumbed, and which was of the same size as my field-book ; its cover was similar also, and it might be passed for the field-book, provided that no one remembered its appearance THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 311 loved one is sick or in pain. To do anything is a relief. Accordingly, whatever remedy may be suggested is a spark on inflammable soil. The mind makes its spring towards action on that cue, sends for that remedy, and for a day at least believes the danger past. Blame, dread, and hope are thus the great belief-inspiring passions, and cover among them the future, the present, and the past. These remarks illustrate the earlier heads of the list on page 292. Whichever represented objects give us sensa tions, especially interesting ones, or incite our motor im pulses, or arouse our hate, desire, or fear, are real enough for us. Our requirements in the way of reality terminate in our own acts and emotions, our own pleasures and pains. These are the ultimate fixities from which, as we formerly observed, the whole chain of our beliefs depends, object hanging to object, as the bees, in swarming, hang to each other until, de proche en proche, the supporting branch, the Self, is reached and held. BELIEF IN OBJECTS OF THEORY. Now the merely conceived or imagined objects which our mind represents as hanging to the sensations (causing them, etc.), filling the gaps between them, and weaving their interrupted chaos into order are innumerable. Whole sys tems of them conflict with other systems, and our choice of too well. I took it to them. ' Is this the tara-tara, friends, that you wish burned? ' " 'Yes, yes, that is it.' " ' Well, take it, and burn it, or keep it.' ' ' M— m. No, no, no. We will not touch it. It is fetish. You must burn it. ' ''I! Well, let it be so. I will do anything to please my good friends of Mowa.' " We walked to the nearest fire. I breathed a regretful farewell to my genial companion, which, during my many weary hours of night, had assisted to relieve my mind when oppressed by almost intolerable woes, and then gravely consigned the innocent Shakespeare to the flames, heap ing the brush fuel over it with ceremonious care. "' A h-h,' breathed the poor deluded natives sighing their relief. . . . ' There is no trouble now.' . . . And something approaching to a cheer was shouted among them, which terminated the episode of the burning of 312 PSYCHOLOGY. which system shall carry our belief is governed by princi ples which are simple enough, however subtle and difficult may be their application to details. The conceived system, to pass for true, must at least include the reality of the sensible objects in it, by explaining them as effects on us, if nothing more. The system which includes the most of them, and definitely ex- plains or pretends to explain the most of them, will, ceteris paribus, prevail It is needless to say how far mankind still is from having excogitated such a system. But the various materialisms, idealisms, and hylozoisms show with what in dustry the attempt is forever made. It is conceivable that several rival theories should equally well include the actual order of our sensations in their scheme, much as the one- fluid and two-fluid theories of electricity formulated all the common electrical phenomena equally well. The sciences are full of these alternatives. Which theory is then to be believed ? That theory will be most generally believed which, besides offering us objects abk to account satisfactorily for our sensible experience, also offers those which are most interesting, those tvhich appeal most 'urgently to our cesthetic, emotional, and active needs. So here, in the higher intellectual life, the same selection among general conceptions goes on which went on among the sensations themselves. ^ First, a word of their relation to our emotional and active needs— and here I can do no better than quote from an article pub lished some years ago :* " A philosophy may be unimpeachable in other respects, but either of two defects will be fatal to its universal acceptance. First, its ulti mate principle must not be one that essentially baffles and disappoints our dearest desires and most cherished powers. A pessimistic principle like Schopenhauer's incurably vicious Will-substance, or Hartmann's wicked jack-at-all-trades, the Unconscious, will perpetually call forth essays at other philosophies. Incompatibility of the future with their desires and active tendencies is, in fact, to most men a source of more fixed disquietude than uncertainty itself. Witness the attempts to overcome the 'problem of evil,' the ' mystery of pain.' There is no problem of 'good.' " But a second and worse defect in a philosophy than that ot < tradicting our active propensities is to give them no Object whatever »• Rationality, Activity,, and Faith' (Princeton Review, July 1882, pp. 64-9). THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 313 to press against. A philosophy whose principle is so incommensurate with our most intimate powers as to deny them all relevancy in univer sal affairs, as to annihilate their motives at one blow, will be even more unpopular than pessimism. Better face the enemy than the eternal Void ! This is why materialism will always fail of universal adoption, however well it may fuse things into an atomistic unity, however clearly it may prophesy the future eternity. For materialism denies reality to the objects of almost all the impulses which we most cherish. The real meaning of the impulses, it says, is something which has no emotional interest for us whatever. But what is called extradition is quite as characteristic of our emotions as of our sense. Both point to an Object as the cause of the present feeling. What an intensely objective reference lies in fear ! In like manner an enraptured man, a dreary- feeling man, are not simply aware of their subjective states ; if they were, the force of their feelings would evaporate. Both believe there is outward cause why they should feel as they do : either 'It is a glad world ! how good is life ! ' or ' What a loathsome tedium is existence ! ' Any philosophy which annihilates the validity of the reference by ex plaining away its objects or translating them into terms of no emo tional pertinency leaves the mind with little to care or act for. This is the opposite condition from that of nightmare, but when acutely brought home to consciousness it produces a kindred horror. In night mare we have motives to act, but no power ; here we have powers, but no motives. A nameless Uriheimliclikeit comes over us at the thought of there being nothing eternal in our final purposes, in the objects of those loves and aspirations which are our deepest energies. The mon strously lopsided equation of the universe and its knower, which we postulate as the ideal of cognition, is perfectly paralleled by the no less lopsided equation of the universe and the doer. We demand in it a character for which our emotions and active propensities shall be a match. Small as we are, minute as is the point by which the Cosmos impinges upon each one of us, each one desires to feel that his reaction at that point is congruous with the demands of the vast whole, that he balances the latter, so to speak, and is able to do what it expects of him. But as his abilities to ' do ' lie wholly in the line of his natural propensities ; as he enjoys reaction with such emotions as fortitude, hope, rapture, admiration, earnestness, and the like ; and as he very unwillingly reacts with fear, disgust, despair, or doubt, —a philosophy which should legitimate only emotions of the latter sort would be sure to leave the mind a prey to discontent and craving. " It is far too little recognized how entirely the intellect is built up of practical interests. The theory of Evolution is beginning to do very good service by its reduction of all mentality to the type of reflex action. Cognition, in this view, is but a fleeting moment, a cross-section at a certain point of what in its totality is a motor phenomenon. In the lower forms of life no one will pretend that cognition is anything more than a guide to appropriate action. The germinal question concerning 314 PSYCHOLOGY. things brought for the first time before consciousness is not the theo retic ' What is that ?' but the practical ' Who goes there ? ' or rather, as Horwicz has admirably put it, 'What is to be done?' — ' Was fang* ich an ? ' iu all our discussions about the intelligence of lower animals the only tebC we use is that of their acting as if for a purpose. Cognition, in short, is incomplete until discharged in act. And although it is true that the iater mental development, which attains its maximum through the hypertrophied cerebrum of man, gives birth to a vast amount of theoretic activity over and above that which is immediately ministerial to practice, yet the earlier claim is only postponed, not effaced, and the active nature asserts its rights to the end. ' ' If there be any truth at all in this view, it follows that however vaguely a philosopher may define the ultimate universal datum, he can not be said to leave it unknown to us so long as he in the slightest degree pretends that our emotional or active attitude towards it should be of one sort rather than another. He who says, ' Life is real, life is earnest,' however much he may speak of the fundamental mysterious- ness of things, gives a distinct definition to that mysteriousness by ascribing to it the right to claim from us the particular mood called seriousness, which means the willingness to live with energy, though energy bring pain. The same is true of him who says that all is vanity. Indefinable as the predicate vanity may be in se, it is clearly enough something which permits anaesthesia, mere escape from suffering, to be our rule of life. There is no more ludicrous incongruity than for agnostics to proclaim with one breath that the substance of things is unknowable, and with the next that the thought of it should inspire us with admiration of its glory, reverence, and a willingness to add our co operative push in the direction towards which its manifestations seem to be drifting. The unknowable may be unfathomed, but if it make such distinct demands upon our activity, we surely are not ignorant of its essential quality. " If we survey the field of history and ask what feature all great periods of revival, of expansion of the human mind, display in common, we shall find, I think, simply this : that each and all of them have said to the human being, ' The inmost nature of the reality is congenial to powers which you possess.' In what did the emancipating message of primitive Christianity consist, but in the announcement that God rec ognizes those weak and tender impulses which paganism had so rudely overlooked ? Take repentance : the man who can do nothing rightly can at least repent of his failures. But for paganism this faculty of re pentance was a pure supernumerary, a straggler too late for the fair. Christianity took it and made it the one power within us which appealed straight to the heart of God. And after the night of the Middle Ages had so long branded with obloquy even the generous impulses of the flesh, and defined the Reality to be such that only slavish natures could com mune with it, in what did the Sursum corda ! of the Renaissance lie but in the proclamation that the archetype of verity in things laid claim THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 315 on the widest activity of our whole aesthetic being? What were Luther's mission and Wesley's but appeals to powers which even the meanest of men might carry with them, faith and self-despair, but which were personal, requiring no priestly intermediation, and which brought their owner face to face with God ? What caused the wild-fire influence of Rousseau but the assurance he gave that man's nature was in harmony with the nature of things, if only the paralyzing cor ruptions of custom would stand from between ? How did Kant and Fichte, Goethe and Schiller, inspire their time with cheer, except by saying, « Use all your powers ; that is the only obedience which the uni verse exacts'? And Carlyle with his gospel of Work, of Fact, of Ve racity, how does he move us except by saying that the universe 'imposes no tasks upon us but such as the most humble can perform ? Emerson's creed that everything that ever was or will be is here in the enveloping Now ; that man has but to obey himself—' He who will rest in what he is, is a part of Destiny '—is in like manner nothing but an exorcism of all scepticism as to the pertinency of one's natural faculties. " In a word, l Son of Man, stand upon thy feet and I will speak unto thee ! ' is the only revelation of truth to which the solving epochs have helped the disciple. But that has been enough to satisfy the greater part of his rational need. In se and per se the universal essence has hardly been more defined by any of these formula than by the agnostic x; but the mere assurance that my powers, such as they are are not irrelevant to it, but pertinent, that it speaks to them and will in some way recognize their reply, that I can be a match for it if I will, and not a footless waif, suffices to make it rational to my feeling m the sense given above. Nothing could be more absurd than to hope for the definitive triumph of any philosophy which should refuse to legitimate, and to legitimate in an emphatic manner, the more powerful of our emotional and practical tendencies. Fatalism, whose solving word in all crises of behavior is * All striving is vain,' will never reign supreme, for the impulse to take life strivingly is indestructible in the race! Moral creeds which speak to that impulse will be widely successful m spite of inconsistency, vagueness, and shadowy determination of expec tancy. Man needs a rule for his will, and will invent one if one be not given him." After the emotional and active needs come the intellec tual and aesthetic ones. The two great aesthetic principles, of richness and of ease, dominate our intellectual as well as our sensuous life. And, ceteris paribus, no system which should not be rich, simple, and harmonious would have a chance of being chosen for belief, if rich, simple, and har monious systems were also there. Into the latter we should unhesitatingly settle, with that welcoming attitude of the will 316 PSYCHOLOGY. in which belief consists. To quote from a remarkable book : " This law that our consciousness constantly tends to the minimum of complexity and to the maximum of definiteness, is of great impor tance for all our knowledge. . . . Our own activity of attention will time determine what we are to know and what we are to believe. If things have more than a certain complexity, not only will our limited powers of attention forbid us to unravel this complexity, but we shall strongly desire to believe the things much simpler than they are. For oui thoughts about them will have a constant tendency to become as simple and definite as possible. Put a man into a perfect chaos of phenomena -sounds, sights, feelings— and if the man continued to exist, and 1 be rational at all, his attention would doubtless soon find for him away to make up some kind of rhythmic regularity, which he would impute to the things about him, so as to imagine that he had discovered some laws of sequence in this mad new world. And thus, in every case where we fancy ourselves sure of a simple law of Nature, we must re member that a great deal of the fancied simplicity may be due, in the given case, nqt to Nature, but to the ineradicable prejudice of our own minds in favor of regularity and simplicity. All our thoughts are de termined, in great measure, by this law of least effort, as it is found exemplified in our activity of attention. ... The aim of the whole process seems to be to reach as complete and united a conception of reality as possible, a conception wherein the greatest fulness of data shall be combined with the greatest simplicity of conception. The effort of consciousness seems to be to combine the greatest richness of content with the greatest definiteness of organization."* The richness is got by including all the facts of sense in the scheme ; the simplicity, by deducing them out of the smallest possible number of permanent and independent primordial entities : the definite organization, by assimi lating these latter to ideal objects between which relations of an inwardly rational sort obtain. What these ideal ob jects and rational relations are will require a separate chapter to show.f Meanwhile, enough has surely been said to justify the assertion made above that no general offhand answer can be given as to which objects mankind shall choose as its realities. The fight is still under way. Our minds are yet chaotic ; and at best we make a mixture and * J. Royce, The Religious Aspect of Philosophy (Boston, 1885), pp 317-57. \ Chapter XXVII. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 317 a compromise, as we yield to the claim of this interest or that, and follow first one and then another principle in turn. It is undeniably true that materialistic, or so-called ' scientific,' conceptions of the universe have so far gratified the purely intellectual interests more than the mere senti mental conceptions have. But, on the other hand, as already remarked, they leave the emotional and active interests cold. The perfect object of belief would be a God or 1 Soul of the World? represented both optimistically and moral- istically (if such a combination could be), and withal so defi nitely conceived as to shoiv us lohy our phenomenal experiences should be sent to us by Him in just the very tuay in which they come. All Science and all History would thus be accounted for in the deepest and simplest fashion. The very room in which I sit, its sensible walls and floor, and the feeling the air and fire within it give me, no less than the ' scientific ' conceptions w^hich I am urged to frame concerning the mode of existence of all these phenomena when my back is turned, would then all be corroborated, not de-realized, by the ultimate principle of my belief. The AVorld-soul sends me just those phenomena in order that I may react upon them ; and among the reactions is the intellectual one of spinning these conceptions. What is beyond the crude experiences is not an alternative to them, but something that means them for me here and now. It is safe to say that, if ever such a system is satisfactorily excogitated, mankind will drop all other systems and cling to that one alone as real. Meanwhile the other systems coexist with the attempts at that one, and, all being alike fragmentary, each has its little audience and day. I have now, I trust, shown sufficiently what the psycho logic sources of the sense of reality are. Certain postulates are given in our nature ; and whatever satisfies those pos tulates is treated as if real.* I might therefore finish the * Prof. Royce puts this well in discussing idealism and the reality of an ' external ' world. " If the history of popular speculation on these topics could be written, how much of cowardice and shuffling would be found in the behavior of the natural mind before the question, ' How dost thou know of an external reality ?' Instead of simply and plainly answering: ' I mean by the external world in the first place something that I accept 318 PSYCHOLOGY. chapter here, were it not that a few additional words will set the truth in a still clearer light. DOUBT. There is hardly a common man who (if consulted) would not say that things come to us in the first instance as ideas; and that if we take them for realities, it is because we add something to them, namely, the predicate of having also ' real existence outside of our thought.' This notion that a higher faculty than the mere having of a conscious con tent is needed to make us know anything real by its means has pervaded psychology from the earliest times, and is the tradition of Scholasticism, Kantism, and Common-sense. Just as sensations must come as inward affections and then be 'extradited ;' as objects of memory must appear at first as presently unrealities, and subsequently be 'projected' backwards as past realities ; so conceptions must be entia rationis till a higher faculty uses them as windows to look beyond the ego, into the real extra-mental world ; — so runs the orthodox and popular account. And there is no question that this is a true account of the way in which many of our later beliefs come to pass. The logical distinction between the bare thought of an object and belief in the object's reality is often a chronological distinction as well. The having and the crediting of an or demand, that I posit, postulate, actively construct on the basis of sense- data,' the natural man gives us all kinds of vague compromise answers. Where shall these endless turnings and twistings have an end? ...... All these lesser motives are appealed to, and the one ultimate motive is neglected. The ultimate motive with the man of every-day life is the will to have an external world. Whatever consciousness contains, reason will persist in spontaneously adding the thought: ' But there shall be something beyond this.' . . . The popular assurance of an external world is ikefsced determination to make one, now and henceforth." (Religious Aspect of Philosophy, p. 304 — the italics are my own.) This immixture of the will appears most flagrantly in the fact that although external matter is doiibted commonly enough, minds external to our own are never doubted. We need them too much, are too essentially social to dispense with them. Semblances of matter may suffice to react upon, but not semblances of communing souls. A psychic solipsism is too hideous a mockery of our wants, and, so far as I know, has never been seriously entertained.-- Chapters ix and x of Prof. Royce's work are on the whole the clearest account of the psychology ef belief with which lam acquainted. THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 319 idea do not always coalesce ; for often we first suppose and then believe ; first play with the notion, frame the hypoth esis, and then affirm the existence, of an object of thought. And we are quite conscious of the succession of the two mental acts. But these cases are none of them primitive cases. They only occur in minds long schooled to doubt by the contradictions of experience. The primitive impulse is to affirm immediately the reality of all that is conceived.* When we do doubt, however, in what does the subsequent resolution of the doubt consist? It either consists in a purely verbal performance, the coupling of the adjectives ' real ' or * outwardly existing ' (as predicates) to the thing originally conceived (as subject) ; or it consists in the per ception in the given case of that for which these adjectives, ab stracted from other similar concrete cases, stand. But what these adjectives stand for, we now know well. They stand for certain relations (immediate, or through intermediaries) to ourselves. Whatever concrete objects have hitherto stood in those relations have been for us ' real,' ' outwardly exist ing.' So that when we now abstractly admit a thing to be ' real' (without perhaps going through any definite percep- * " The leading fact in Belief, according to my view of it, is our Primi tive Credulity. We begin by believing everything ; whatever is, is true. . . . The animal born in the morning of a summer day proceeds upon the fact of daylight ; assumes the perpetuity of that fact. Whatever it is disposed to do, it does without misgivings. If in the morning it began a round of operations continuing for hours, under the full benefit of day light, it would unhesitatingly begin the same round in the evening. Its state of mind is practically one of unbounded confidence ; but, as yet, it does not understand what confidence means. ' ' The pristine assurance is soon met by checks ; a disagreeable experience leading to new insight. To be thwarted and opposed is one of our earliest and most frequent pains. It develops the sense of a distinction between free and obstructed impulses ; the unconsciousness of an open way is ex changed for consciousness ; we are now said properly to believe in what has never been contradicted, as we disbelieve in what has been contradicted. We believe that, after the dawn of day, there is before us a continuance of light ; we do not believe that this light is to continue forever. " Thus, the vital circumstance in belief is never to be contradicted — never to lose prestige. The number of repetitions counts for little in the process: we are as much convinced after ten as after fifty ; we are more convinced by ten unbroken than by fifty for and one against," (Bain ; The Emotions and the Will, pp. 511, 512.) 320 PSYCHOLOGY. tion of its relations), it is as if we said " it belongs in the same world with those other objects." Naturally enough, we have hourly opportunities for this summary process of belief. All remote objects in space or time are believed in this way. When I believe that some prehistoric savage chipped this flint, for example, the reality of the savage and of his act makes no direct appeal either to my sensation, emotion, or volition. What I mean by my belief in it is simply my dim sense of a continuity between the long dead savage and his doings and the present world of which the flint forms part. It is pre-eminently a case for applying our doctrine of the ' fringe ' (see Vol I. p. 258). When I think the savage with one fringe of relationship, I believe in him ; when I think him without that fringe, or with another one (as, e.g., if I should class him with * scientific vagaries ' in general), I disbelieve him. The word ' real ' itself is, in short, a fringe. RELATIONS OF BELIEF AND -WILL. We shall see in Chapter XXV that will consists in nothing but a manner of attending to certain objects, or consenting to their stable presence before the mind. The objects, in the case of will, are those whose existence depends on our thought, movements of our own body for example, or facts which such movements executed in future may make real. Objects of belief, on the contrary, are those which do not change according as we think regarding them. I will to get up early to-morrow morning ; I believe that I got up late yesterday morning; I will that my foreign bookseller in Boston shall procure me a German book and write to him to that effect. I believe that he will make me pay three dollars for it when it comes, etc. Now the im portant thing to notice is that this difference between the objects of will and belief is entirely immaterial, as far as the relation of the mind to them goes. All that the mind does is in both cases the same ; it looks at the object and consents to its existence, espouses it, says 'it shall be my reality.' It turns to it, in short, in the interested active emotional way. The rest is done by nature, which in some cases makes the objects real which we think of in this- THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 321 manner, and in other cases does not. Nature cannot change the past to suit our thinking. She cannot change the stars or the winds ; but she does change our bodies to suit our thinking, and through their instrumentality changes much besides ; so the great practical distinction between objects which we may will or unwill, and objects which we can merely believe or disbelieve, grows up, and is of course one of the most important distinctions in the world. Its roots, how ever, do not lie in psychology, but in physiology ; as the chapter on Volition will abundantly make plain. Will and Belief, in short, meaning a certain relation bettveen objects and the Self, are tivo names for one and the same PSYCHOLOGICAL phenomenon. All the questions which arise concerning one are questions which arise concerning the other. The causes and conditions of the peculiar relation must be the same in both. The free-will question arises as regards belief. If our wills are indeterminate, so must our beliefs be, etc. The first act of free-will, in short, would naturally be to believe in free-will, etc. In Chapter XXYI, I shall mention this again. A practical observation may end this chapter. If belief consists in an emotional reaction of the entire man on an object, how can we believe at will ? We cannot control our emotions. Truly enough, a man cannot believe at will abruptly. Nature sometimes, and indeed not very infre quently, produces instantaneous conversions for us. She suddenly puts us in an active connection with objects of which she had till then left us cold. " I realize for the first time," we then say, " what that means !" This happens often with moral propositions. We have often heard them ; but now they shoot into our lives ; they move us ; we feel their living force. Such instantaneous beliefs are truly enough not to be achieved by will. But gradually our will can lead us to the same results by a very simple method : we need only in cold blood ACT as if the thing in question were real, and keep acting as if it were real, and it will infallibly end by growing into such a connection with our life that it will become real. It will become so knit with habit and emotion that our interests in it will be those which characterize belief. 822 PSYCHOLOGY. Those to whom ' God ' and ' Duty ' are now mere names can make them much more than that, if they make a little sacrifice to them every day. But all this is so well known in moral and religious education that I need say no more.* * Literature. D. Hume : Treatise on Human Nature, part in. §§ vii- x. A. Bain : Emotions and Will, chapter on Belief (also pp. 20 ff). J. Sully: Sensation and Intuition, essay iv. J. Mill: Analysis of Human Mind, chapter xi. Ch. Renouvier : Psychologic Rationnelle, vol. n. pt. ii ; and Esquisse d'une Classification systematique des Doctrines Philosophiques, part vi. J. H. Newman: The Grammar of Assent. J. Venn: Some Characteristics of Belief. V. Brochard : De 1'Erreur, part n. chap, vi, ix ; and Revue Philosophique, xxvm. 1. E. Rabier : Psy chologic, chap xxi, Appendix. OlleLaprune: La Certitude Morale (1881). G. F. Stout: On Genesis of Cognition of Physical Reality, in ' Mind,' Jan. 1890. J. Pikler: The Psychology of the Belief in Objective Existence (London, 1890). — Mill says that we believe present sensations ; and makes our belief in all other things a matter of association with these. So far so good; but as he makes no mention of emotional or volitional reaction, Bain rightly charges him with treating belief as a purely intellectual state. For Bain belief is rather an incident of our active life. When a thing is such as to make us act on it, then we believe it, according to Bain. " But how about past things, or remote things, upon which no reaction of ours is pos sible? And how about belief in things which check action?" says Sully; who considers that we believe a thing only when "the idea of it has an in herent tendency to approximate in character and intensity to a sensation." It is obvious that each of these authors emphasizes a true aspect of the question. My own account has sought to be more complete, sensation, association, and active reaction all being acknowledged to be concerned. The most compendious possible formula perhaps would be that our belief and attention are the same fact. For the moment, what we attend to is reality ; Attention is a motor reaction; and we are so made that sensations force attention from us. On Belief and Conduct see an article by Leslie Stephen, Fortnightly Review, July 1888. A set of facts have been recently brought to my attention which I hardly know how to treat, so I say a word about them in this footnote. I refer to a type of experience which has frequently found a place amongst the ' Yes' answers to the ' Census of Hallucinations,' and which is gener ally described by those who report it as an ' impression of the presence ' of someone near them, although no sensation either of sight, hearing, or touch is involved. From the way in which this experience is spoken of by those who have had it, it would appear to be an extremely definite and positive state of mind, coupled with a belief in the reality of its object quite as strong as any direct sensation ever gives. And yet no sensation seems to be connected with it at all. Sometimes the person whose nearness is thus impressed is a known person, dead or living, sometimes an unknown one. His attitude and situation are often very definitely impressed, and so, some times (though not by way of hearing), are words which he wishes to say. The phenomenon, would seem to be due to a pure conception becoming THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY. 32U saturated with the sort of stinging urgency which ordinarily only sensa tions bring. But I cannot yet persuade myself that the urgency in ques tion consists in concomitant emotional and motor impulses. The ' impres sion ' may come quite suddenly and depart quickly; it may cany no emotional suggestions, and wake no motor consequences beyond those involved in attending to it. Altogether, the matter is somewhat paradoxical, and no conclusion can be come to until more definite data are obtained. Perhaps the most curious case of the sort which I have received is the following. The subject of the observation, Mr. P., is an exceptionally intelligent witness, though the words of the narrative are his wife's. 4 ' Mr. P. has all his life been the occasional subject of rather singular delusions or impressions of various kinds. If I had belief in the existence of latent or embryo faculties, other than the five senses, I should explain them on that ground. Being totally blind, his other perceptions are abnormally keen and developed, and given the existence of a rudimentary sixth sense, it would be only natural that this also should be more acute in him than in others. One of the most interesting of his experiences in this line was the frequent apparition of a corpse some years ago, which may be worth the attention of your Committee on that subject. At the time Mr. P. had a music-room in Boston on Beacon Street, where he used to do severe and protracted practice with little interruption. Now, all one season it was a very familiar occurrence with him while in the midst of work to feel a o^ld draft of air suddenly upon his face, with a prickling sensation at the loots of his hair, when he would turn from the piano, and a figure which he knew to be dead would come sliding under the crack of the door from without, flattening itself to squeeze through and rounding out again to the human form. It was of a middle-aged man, and drew itself along the carpet on hands and knees, but with head thrown back till it reached the sofa, upon which it stretched itself. It remained some moments, but vanished always if Mr. P. spoke or made a decided movement. The most singular point in the occurrence was its frequent repetition. He might expect it on any day between two and four o'clock, and it came always heralded by the same sudden cold shiver, and was invariably the same fig ure which went through the same movements. He afterwards traced the whole experience to strong tea. He was in the habit of taking cold tea, which always stimulates him, for lunch, and on giving up this practice he never saw this or any other apparition again. However, even allowing, as is doubtless true, that the event was a delusion of nerves first fatigued by overwork and then excited by this stimulant, there is one point which is still wholly inexplicable and highly interesting to me. Mr. P. has no memory whatever of sight, nor conception of it. It is impossible for him to form any idea of what we mean by light or color, consequently he has no cognizance of any object which does not reach his sense of hearing or of touch, though these are so acute as to give a contrary impression some times to other people. When he becomes aware of the presence of a person or an object, by means which seem mysterious to outsiders, he can always trace it naturally and legitimately to slight echoes, perceptible only to his keen ears, or to differences in atmospheric pressure, perceptible only to his acute nerves of touch; but with the apparition described, for the only time in his xperience, he was aware of presence, size, and appearance, without 324 PSYCHOLOGY. the use of either of these mediums. The figure never produced the least sound nor came within a number of feet of his person, yet he knew that it was a man, that it moved, and in what direction, even that it wore a full beard, which, like the thick curly hair, was partially gray; also that it was dressed in the style of suit known as 'pepper and salt.' These points were jill perfectly distinct and invariable each time. If asked how he perceived them, he will answer he cannot tell, he simply knew it, and so strongly and so distinctly that it is impossible to shake his opinion as to the exact details of the man's appearance. It would seem that in this delusion of the senses- he really saw, as he has never done in the actual experiences of life, except in the first two years of childhood." On cross-examining Mr. P., I could not make out that there was any thing like visual imagination involved, although he was quite unable to describe in just what terms the false perception was carried on. It seemed to be more like an intensely definite conception than anything else, a con- ception to which the feeling of present reality was attached, but in no such shape as easily to fall under the heads laid down in my text. CHAPTER XXII * REASONING. WE talk of man being the rational animal ; and the tra ditional intellectualist philosophy has always made a great point of treating the brutes as wholly irrational creatures. Nevertheless, it is by no means easy to decide just what is meant by reason, or how the peculiar thinking process called reasoning differs from other thought-sequences which may lead to similar results. Much of our thinking consists of trains of images sug gested one by another, of a sort of spontaneous revery of which it seems likely enough that the higher brutes should be capable. This sort of thinking leads nevertheless to rational conclusions, both practical and theoretical. The links between the terms are either ' contiguity ' or ' similar ity,' and with a mixture of both these things we can hard ly be very incoherent. As a rule, in this sort of irrespon sible thinking, the terms which fall to be coupled together are empirical concretes, not abstractions. A sunset may call up the vessel's deck from which I saw one last summer, the companions of my voyage, my arrival into port, etc.; or it may make me think of solar myths, of Hercules' and Hector's funeral pyres, of Homer and whether he could write, of the Greek alphabet, etc. If habitual contiguities predominate, we have a prosaic mind ; if rare contiguities, or similarities, have free play, we call the person fanciful, poetic, or witty. But the thought as a rule is of matters taken in their entirety. Having been thinking of one, we find later that we are thinking of another, to which we haye been lifted along, we hardly know how. If an abstract * The substance of this chapter, and a good many pages of the text, originally appeared in an article entitled ' Brute and Human Intellect,' in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy for July 1878 (vol. xn. p. 236). 325 326 PSYCHOLOGY. quality figures in the procession, it arrests our attention but for a moment, and fades into something else ; and is never very abstract. Thus, in thinking of the sun-myths, we may have a gleam of admiration at the gracefulness of the primitive human mind, or a moment of disgust at the nar rowness of modern interpreters. But, in the main, we think less of qualities than of whole things, real or possi ble, just as we may experience them. The upshot of it may be that we are reminded of some practical duty : we write a letter to a friend abroad, or we take down the lexicon and study our Greek lesson. Our thought is rational, and leads to a rational act, but it can hardly be called reasoning in a strict sense of the term. There are other shorter flights of thought, single coup lings of terms which suggest one another by association, which approach more to what would commonly be classed as acts of reasoning proper. Those are where a present sign suggests an unseen, distant, or future reality. Where the sign and what it suggests are both concretes which have been coupled together on previous occasions, the inference is common to both brutes and men, being really nothing more than association by contiguity. A and B, dinner-bell and dinner, have been experienced in immediate succes sion. Hence A no sooner falls upon the sense than B is anticipated, and steps are taken to meet it. The whole education of our domestic beasts, all the cunning added by age and experience to wild ones, and the greater part of our human knowingness consists in the ability to make a mass of inferences of this simplest sort. Our ' perceptions/ or recognitions of what objects are before us, are inferences of this kind. We feel a patch of color, and we say ' a dis tant house,' a whiff of odor crosses us, and we say ' a skunk,' a faint sound is heard, and we call it ' a railroad train.' Examples are needless ; for such inferences of sen sations not presented form the staple and tissue of our perceptive life, and our Chapter XIX was full of them, illusory or veracious. They have been called unconscious inferences. Certainly we are commonly unconscious that we are inferring at all. The sign and the signified melt into what seems to us the object of a single pulse of REASONING. 327 thought. Immediate inferences would be a good name for these simple acts of reasoning requiring but two terms,* were it not that formal logic has already appropriated the expression for a more technical use. 'RECEPTS.' In these first and simplest inferences the conclusion may follow so continuously upon the ' sign ' that the latter is not discriminated or attended to as a separate object by the mind. Even now we can seldom define the optical signs which lead us to infer the shapes and distances of the ob jects which by their aid we so unhesitatingly perceive. The objects, too, when thus inferred, are general objects. The dog crossing a scent thinks of a deer in general, or of another dog in general, not of a particular deer or dog. To these most primitive abstract objects Dr. G. J. Bomanes gives the name of recepts or generic ideas, to distinguish them from concepts and general ideas properly so called. f They are not analyzed or defined, but only imagined. u It requires but a slight analysis of our ordinary mental processes to prove that all our simpler ideas are group-arrangements which have been formed spontaneously or without any of that intentionally com paring, sifting, and combining process which is required in the higher departments of ideational activity. The comparing, sifting, and com bining is here done, as it were, for the conscous agent, not by him. Recepts are received ; it is only concepts that require to be conceived. ... If I am crossing a street and hear behind me a sudden shout, I do not require to wait in order to predicate to myself that there is prob ably a hansom-cab just about to run me down : a cry of this kind, and in those circumstances, is so intimately associated in my mind with its * I see no need of assuming more than two terms in this sort of reason ing — first, the sign, and second, the thing inferred from it. Either may be complex, but essentially it is but A calling up B, and no middle term is involved. M. Binet, in his most intelligent little book, La Psychologic du Raisouuement, maintains that there are three terms. The present sensa tion or sign must, according to him, first evoke from the past an image which resembles it and fuses with it, and the things suggested or inferred are always the contiguous associates of this intermediate image, and not of the immediate sensation. The reader of Chapter XIX will see why I do not believe in the ' image ' in question as a distinct psychic fact. f Mental Evolution in Man (1889), chapters in and iv. See especially pp. 68-80, and later 353, 396. 328 PSYCHOLOGY. purpose, that the idea which it arouses need not rise above the level ot a recept ; and the adaptive movements on my part which that idea im mediately prompts are performed without any intelligent reflection. Yet, on the other hand, they are neither reflex actions nor instinctive actions ; they are what may be termed receptual actions, or actions de pending on recepts." * " How far can this kind of unnamed or non-conceptional ideation extend ?" Dr. Romanes asks ; and answers by a variety of examples taken from the life of brutes, for which I must refer to his book. One or two of them, however, I will quote : " Houzeau writes that while crossing a wide and arid plain in Texas, his two dogs suffered greatly from thirst, and that between thirty and forty times they rushed down the hollows to search for water. The hol lows were not valleys, and there were no trees in them, or any other difference in the vegetation ; and as they were absolutely dry, there could have been no smell of damp earth. The dogs behaved as if they knew that a dip in the ground offered them the best chance of finding water, and Houzeau has often witnessed the same behavior in other ani mals. . . . " Mr. Darwin writes : ' When I say to my terrier in an eager voice (and I have made the trial many times), " Hi ! hi ! where is it ? " she at once takes it as a sign that something is to be hunted, and generally first looks quickly all round, and then rushes into the nearest thicket, to scout for any game, but finding nothing she looks up into any neigh- boring tree for a squirrel. Now do not these actions clearly show that she had in her mind a general idea, or concept, that some animal is to be discovered and hunted ? '" f They certainly show this. But the idea in question is of an object about which nothing farther may be articulately known. The thought of it prompts to activity, but to no theoretic consequence. Similarly in the following ex ample : "Water-fowl adopt a somewhat different mode of alighting upon land, or even upon ice, from that which they adopt when alighting upon water; and those kinds which dive from a height (such as terns and gannets) never do so upon land or upon ice. These facts prove that the animals have one recept answering to a solid surface, and an other answering to a fluid. Similarly a man will not dive from a height over hard ground or over ice, nor will he jump into water in the same way as he jumps upon dry land. In other words, like the water-fowl * Loc. cit. p. 50. t P- 52. REASONING. 329 he has two distinct recepts, one of which answers to solid ground, and the other to an unresisting fluid. But unlike the water-fowl he is able to bestow upon each of these recepts a name, and thus to raise them both to the level of concepts. So far as the practical purposes of loco motion are concerned, it is of course immaterial whether or not he thus raises his recepts into concepts ; but ... for many other purposes it is of the highest importance that he is able to do this. " * IN REASONING, WE PICK OUT ESSENTIAL QUALITIES, The chief of these purposes is predication, a theoretic function which, though it always leads eventually to some kind of action, yet tends as often as not to inhibit the imme diate motor response to which the simple inferences of which we have been speaking give rise. In reasoning, A may suggest B ; but B, instead of being an idea which is simply obeyed by us, is an idea which suggests the distinct additional idea C. And where the train of suggestion is one of reasoning distinctively so called as contrasted with mere revery or * associative ' sequence, the ideas bear certain inward relations to each other which we must proceed to examine with some care. The result C yielded by a true act of reasoning is apt to be a thing voluntarily sought, such as the means to a proposed end, the ground for an observed effect, or the effect of an assumed cause. All these results may be thought of as concrete things, but they are not suggested im mediately by other concrete things, as in the trains of simply as sociative thought. They are linked to the concretes which precede them by intermediate steps, and these steps are formed by general characters articulately denoted and ex pressly analyzed out. A thing inferred by reasoning need neither have been an habitual associate of the datum from which we infer it, nor need it be similar to it. It may be a thing entirely unknown to our previous experience, some thing which no simple association of concretes could ever have evoked. The great difference, in fact, between that simpler kind of rational thinking which consists in the con crete objects of past experience merely suggesting each other, and reasoning distinctively so called, is this, that * Loc. cit. p. 74. 330 PSYCHOLOGY. whilst the empirical thinking is only reproductive, reason ing is productive. An empirical, or l rule-of-thumb,' thinker can deduce nothing from data with whose behavior and associates in the concrete he is unfamiliar. But put a reasoner amongst a set of concrete objects which he has neither seen nor heard of before, and with a little time, if he is a good reasoner, he will make such inferences from them as will quite atone for his ignorance. Reasoning helps us out of unprecedented situations — situations for which all our common associative wisdom, all the ' educa tion ' which we share in common with the beasts, leaves us without resource. Let us make this ability to deal with NOVEL data the tech nical differentia of reasoning. This will sufficiently mark it out from common associative thinking, and will immedi ately enable us to say just what peculiarity it contains. It contains analysis and abstraction. Whereas the merely empirical thinker stares at a fact in its entirety, and remains helpless, or gets * stuck,' if it suggests no concomitant or similar, the reasoner breaks it up and notices some one of its separate attributes. This attribute he takes to be the essential part of the whole fact before him. This attribute has properties or consequences which the fact until then was not known to have, but which, now that it is noticed to contain the attribute, it must have. Call the fact or concrete datum S ; the essential attribute M ; the attribute's property P. Then the reasoned inference of P from S cannot be made without M's intermediation. The * essence ' M is thus that third or middle term in the reasoning which a moment ago was pronounced essential, for his original concrete S the reasoner substitutes its abstract property, M. What is true of M, what is coupled with M, then holds true of S, is coupled with S. As M is properly one of the parts of the entire S, reasoning may then be very well defined as the substitution of parts and their implications or consequences for wholes. And the art of the reasoner will consist of two stages : REASONING. 331 First, sagacity* or the ability to discover what part, M, lies embedded in the whole S which is before him ; Second, learning, or the ability to recall promptly M's consequences, concomitants, or implications. t If we glance at the ordinary syllogism — MisP; S isM; . • . S is P * J. Locke, Essay cone. Hum. Understanding, bk. iv. chap. n. § 3. f To be sagacious is to be a good observer. J. S. Mill has a passage which is so much in the spirit of the text that I cannot forbear to quote it. "The observer is not he who merely sees the thing which is before his eyes, but he who sees what parts that thing is composed of. To do this well is a rare talent. One person, from inattention, or attending only in the wrong place, overlooks half of what he sees ; another sets down much more than he sees, confounding it with what he imagines, or with what he infers ; another takes note of the kind of all the circumstances, but being inexpert in estimating their degree, leaves the quantity of each vague and uncertain ; another sees indeed the whole, but makes such an awkward division of it into parts, throwing things into one mass which require to be separated, and separating others which might more conveniently be considered as one, that the result is much the same, sometimes even worse, than if no analysis had been attempted at all. It would be possible to point out what qualities of mind, and modes of mental culture, fit a person for being a good observer : that, however, is a question not of Logic, but of the Theory of Education, in the most en larged sense of the term. There is not properly an Art of Observing. There may be rules for observing. But these, like rules for inventing, are properly instructions for the preparation of one's own mind ; for putting it into the state in which it will be most fitted to observe, or most likely to invent, They are, therefore, essentially rules of self-education, which is a different thing from Logic. They do not teach how to do the thing, but how to make ourselves capable of doing it. They are an art of strengthening the limbs, not an art of using them. The extent and minute ness of observation which may be requisite, and the degree of decomposi tion to which it may be necessary to cany the mental analysis, depend on the particular purpose in view. To ascertain the state of the whole uni verse at any particular moment is impossible, but would also be useless. In making chemical experiments, we do not think it necessary to note the position of the planets ; because experience has shown, as a very superficial experience is sufficient to show, that in such cases that circumstance is not material to the result : and accordingly, in the ages when man believed in the occult influences of the heavenly bodies, it might have been unphilo- sophical to omit ascertaining the precise condition of those bodies at the moment of the experiment." (Logic, bk. m. chap. vn. § 1. Cf. also bk. iv. chap. TI.) 332 PSYCHOLOGY. —we see that the second or minor premise, the 'subsump- tion ' as it is sometimes called, is the one requiring the sa gacity ; the first or major the one requiring the fertility, or fulness of learning. Usually the learning is more apt to be ready than the sagacity, the ability to seize fresh aspects in concrete things, being rarer than the ability to learn old rules ; so that, in most actual cases of reasoning, the minor premise, or the way of conceiving the subject, is the one that makes the novel step in thought. This is, to be sure, not always the case ; for the fact that M carries P with it may also be unfamiliar and now formulated for the first time. The perception that S is M is a mode of conceiving S. The statement that M is P is an abstract or general proposi tion. A word about both is necessary. WHAT IS MEANT BY A MODE OP CONCEIVING. When we conceive of S merely as M (of vermilion merely as a mercury-compound, for example), we neglect all the other attributes which it may have, and attend exclusively to this one. We mutilate the fulness of S's reality. Every reality has an infinity of aspects or properties. Even so simple a fact as a line which you trace in the air may be considered in respect to its form, its length, its direction, and its location. When we reach more complex facts, the number of ways in which we may regard them is literally endless. Vermilion is not only a mercury-compound, it is vividly red, heavy, and expensive, it comes from China, and so on, in infinitum. All objects are well-springs of properties, which are only little by little developed to our knowledge, and it is truly said that to know one thing thoroughly would be to know the whole universe. Mediately or immediately, that one thing is re lated to everything else ; and to know all about it, all its relations need be known. But each relation forms one of its attributes, one angle by which some one may conceive it, and while so conceiving it may ignore the rest of it. A man is such a complex fact. But out of the complexity all that an army commissary picks out as important for his purposes is his property of eating so many pounds a day ; the general, REASONING. 333 of marching so many miles; the chair-maker, of having such a shape ; the orator, of responding to such and such feelings ; the theatre-manager, of being willing to pay just such a price, and no more, for an evening's amusement. Each of these persons singles out the particular side of the entire man which has a bearing on Us concerns, and not till this side is distinctly and separately conceived can the proper practical conclusions for that reasoner be drawn ; and when they are drawn the man's other attributes may be ig nored. All ways of conceiving a concrete fact, if they are true ways at all, are equally true ways. There is no property ABSOLUTELY essential to any one thing. The same property which figures as the essence of a thing on one occasion be comes a very inessential feature upon another. Now that I am writing, it is essential that I conceive my paper as a surface for inscription. If I failed to do that, I should have to stop my work. But if I wished to light a fire, and no other materials were by, the essential way of conceiving the paper would be as combustible material ; and I need then have no thought of any of its other destinations. It is •eally all that it is : a combustible, a writing surface, a thin thing, a hydrocarbonaceous thing, a thing eight inches one way and ten another, a thing just one furlong east of a certain stone in my neighbor's field, an American thing, etc etc ad infinitum. Whichever one of these aspects of its being I temporarily class it under, makes me unjust to the other aspects But as I always am classing it under one aspect or another, I am always -unjust, always partial, always ex clusive. My excuse is necessity— the necessity which my finite and practical nature lays upon me. My thinking is first and last and always for the sake of my doing, and I can only do one thing at a time. A God, who is supposed to drive the whole universe abreast, may also be supposed, without detriment to his activity, to see all parts of it at once and without emphasis. But were our human attention so to disperse itself we should simply stare vacantly at things at large and forfeit our opportunity of doing any particular act. Mr. Warner, in his Adirondack story, shot a bear by aiming, not at his eye or heart, but 'at him gen- 334 PSYCHOLOGY. erally.' But we cannot aim ' generally ' at the universe ; or if we do, we miss our game. Our scope is narrow, and we must attack things piecemeal, ignoring the solid fulness in which the elements of Nature exist, and stringing one after another of them together in a serial way, to suit our little interests as they change from hour to hour. In this, the partiality of one moment is partly atoned for by the different sort of partiality of the next. To me now, writing these words, emphasis and selection seem to be the essence of the human mind. In other chapters other qualities have seemed, and will again seem, more important parts of psy chology. Men are so ingrainedly partial that, for common-sense and scholasticism (which is only common-sense grown artic ulate), the notion that there is no one quality genuinely, -absolutely, and exclusively essential to anything is almost unthinkable. " A thing's essence makes it what it is. With out an exclusive essence it would be nothing in particular, would be quite nameless, we could not say it was this rather than that. What you write on, for example,— why talk of its being combustible, rectangular, and the like, when you know that these are mere accidents, and that what it really is, and was made to be, is just paper and nothing else?" The reader is pretty sure to make some such comment as this. But he is himself merely insisting on an aspect of the thing which suits his own petty purpose, that of naming the thing ; or else on an aspect which suits the manufacturer's purpose, that of producing an article for which there is a vulgar demand. Meanwhile the reality overflows these purposes at every pore. Our usual purpose with it, our commonest title for it, and the properties which this title suggests, have in reality nothing sacramental. They characterize us more than they characterize the thing. But we are so stuck in our prejudices, so petrified intellec tually, that to our vulgarest names, with their suggestions, we ascribe an eternal and exclusive worth. The thing must be, essentially, what the vulgarest name connotes; what less usual names connote, it can be only in an < accidental ' and relatively unreal sense.* * Readers brought up on Popul^Science may think UMrtthemoieciilaii REASONING. 335 Locke undermined the fallacy. But none of his succes sors, so far as I know, have radically escaped it, or seen that the only meaning of essence is teleological, and that classi fication and conception are purely teleological weapons of the mind. The essence of a thing is that one of its properties which is so important for my interests that in comparison with it I may neglect the rest. Amongst those other things which have this important property I class it, after this property I name it, as a thing endowed with this property I conceive it ; and whilst so classing, naming, and conceiv ing it, all other truths about it become to me as naught.* The properties which are important vary from man to man and from hour to hour.f Hence divers appellations and structure of things is their real essence in an absolute sense, and that water is H-O-H more deeply and truly than it is a solvent of sugar or a slaker of thirst. Not a whit ! It is all of these things with equal reality, and the only reason why /or the chemist it is H-O-H primarily, and only secondarily the other things, is that for his purpose of deduction and com pendious definition the H-O-H aspect of it is the more useful one to bear in mind * " We find that we take for granted irresistibly that each kind [of thing] has some character which distinguishes it from other classes. . . . What is the foundation of this postulate ? What is the ground of this assumption that there must exist a definition which we have never seen, and which perhaps no one has seen in a satisfactory form ?....! reply that our con viction that there must needs be characteristic marks by which things can be defined in words is founded upon the assumption of the necessary possi bility of reasoning." (W. Whewell : Hist, of Scientific Ideas, bk. vin. chap i, §9.) f I may quote a passage from an article entitled ' The Sentiment of Rationality,' published in vol. iv of Mind, 1879 : "What is a conception* It is a teleological instrument. It is a partial aspect of a thing which for our purpose we regard as its essential aspect, as the representative of the entire thing. In comparison with this aspect, whatever other properties and qualities the thing may have are unimportant accidents which we may without blame ignore. But the essence, the ground of conception, varies with the end we have in view. A substance like oil has as many different essences as it has uses to different individuals. One man conceives it as a combustible, another as a lubricator, another as a food ; the chemist thinks of it as a hydrocarbon ; the furniture maker as a darkener of wood ; the speculator as a commodity whose market-price to-day is this and to-morrow that. The soap-boiler, the physicist, the •clothes- scourer severally ascribe to it other essences in relation to their needs. Ueberweg's doctrine that the essential quality of a thing is the 336 PSYCHOLOGY. conceptions for the same thing. But many objects of daily use — as paper, ink, butter, horse-car — have properties of such constant unwavering importance, and have such stereo typed names, that we end by believing that to conceive them in those ways is to conceive them in the only true way. Those are no truer ways of conceiving them than any others ; they are only more important ways, more fre quently serviceable ways.* quality of most worth is strictly true ; but Ueberweg has failed to note that the worth is wholly relative to the temporary interests of the conceiver. And, even, when his interest is distinctly denned in his own mind, the discrimination of the quality in the object which has the closest connection with it is a thing which no rules can teach. The only a priori advice that can be given to a man embarking on life with a certain purpose is the somewhat barren counsel : Be sure that in the circumstances that meet you, you attend to the right ones for your purpose. To pick out the right ones is the measure of the man. ' Millions/ says Hartmann, ' stare at the phenomenon before a genialer Kopf pounces on the concept.' The genius is simply he to whom, when he opens his eyes upon the world, the ' right ' characters are the prominent ones. The fool is he who, with the same purposes as the genius, infallibly gets his attention tangled amid the accidents." * Only if one of our purposes were itself truer than another, could one of our conceptions become the truer conception. To be a truer purpose, however, our purpose must conform more to some absolute standard of purpose in things to which our purposes ought to conform. This shows that the whole doctrine of essential characters is intimately bound up with a teleological view of the world. Materialism becomes self-contra dictory when it denies teleology, and yet in the same breath calls atoms, etc., the essential facts. The world contains consciousness as well as atoms— and the one must be written down as just as essential as the other, in the ab sence of any declared purpose regarding them on the creator's part, or in the absence of any creator. As far as we ourselves go, the atoms are worth more for purposes of deduction, the consciousness for purposes of inspira tion. We may fairly write the Universe in either way, thus : ATOMS- producing-consciousness ; or CoNSCiousNESS-produced- by-atoms. Atoms alone, or consciousness alone, are precisely equal mutilations of the truth. If, without believing in a God, I still continue to talk of what the world ' essentially is,' I am just as much entitled to define it as a place in which my nose itches, or as a place where at a certain corner I can get a mess of oysters for twenty cents, as to call it an evolving nebula differentiating and integrating itself. It is hard to say which of the three abstractions is the more rotten or miserable substitute for the world's concrete fulness To conceive it merely as 'God's work' would be a similar mutilation of it, so long as we said not what God, or what kind of work. The only real truth about the world, apart from particular purposes, is the total truth. REASONING. 33? So much for what is implied, when the reasoner con ceives of the fact S before him as a case of which the essence is to be M. One word now as to what is involved in M's having properties, consequences, or implications, and we can go back to the study of the reasoning process again. WHAT IS INVOLVED IN GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. M is not a concrete, or ' self-sufficient,' as Mr. Clay would say. It is an abstract character which may exist, embedded with other characters, in many concretes. Whe ther it be the character of being a writing surface, of being made in America or China, of being eight inches square, or of being in a certain part of space, this is always true of it. Now we might conceive of this being a world in which all such general characters were independent of each other, so that if any one of them were found in a subject S, we never could be sure what others would be found alongside of it. On one occasion there might be P with M, on another Q, and so on. In such a world there would be no general sequences or coexistences, and no universal laws. Each grouping would be sui generis ; from the experience of the past no future could be predicted ; and reasoning, as we shall presently see, would be an impossibility. But the world we live in is not one of this sort. Though many general characters seem indifferent to each other, there remain a number of them which affect constant habits of mutual concomitance or repugance. They involve or imply each other. One of them is a sign to us that the other will be found. They hunt in couples, as it were ; and such a proposition as that M is P, or includes P, or precedes or accompanies P, if it prove to be true in one instance, may very likely be true in every other instance which we meet. This is, in fact, a world in which general laws obtain, in which universal propositions are true, and in which rea soning is therefore possible. Fortunately for us : for since we cannot handle things as wholes, but only by conceiving them through some general character which for the time we call their essence, it would be a great pity if the matter ended there, and if the general character, once picked out au/i in our possession, helped us to no farther advance. In 338 PSYCHOLOGY. Chapter XXVIII we shall have again to consider this har mony between our reasoning faculty and the world in which its lot is cast* To revert now to our symbolic representation of the reasoning process : MisP SisM SisP M is discerned and picked out for the time being to be the essence of the concrete fact, phenomenon, or reality, 8. But M in this world of ours is inevitably conjoined with P ; so that P is the next thing that we may expect to find con joined with the fact S. We may conclude or infer P, through the intermediation of the M which our sagacity began by discerning, when S came before it, to be the essence of the case. Now note that if P have any value or importance for us, M was a very good character for our sagacity to pounce upon and abstract. If, on the contrary, P were of no importance, some other character than M would have been a better essence for us to conceive of 8 by. Psychologically, as a rule, P overshadows the process from the start. We are seeking P, or something like P. But the bare totality of 8 does not yield it to our gaze ; and casting about for some point in 8 to take hold of, which will lead us to P, we hit, if we are sagacious, upon M, because M happens to be just the character which is knit up with P. Had we wished Q instead of P, and were N a property of 8 conjoined with Q, we ought to have ignored M, noticed N, and conceived of 8 as a sort of N exclusively. ^Reasoning is always for a subjective interest, to attain some particular conclusion, or to gratify some special curiosity. It not only breaks up the datum placed before it and conceives it abstractly ; it must conceive it rightly too ; and conceiving it rightly means conceiving it by that one particular abstract character which leads to the one * Compare Lotze, Metaphysik, §§ 58, 67, for some instructive remarks on ways in which the world's constitution might differ from what it actu ally is. Compare also Chapter XXVIII. REASONING. 339 sort of conclusion which it is the reasoner's temporary in terest to attain.* The results of reasoning may be hit upon by accident The stereoscope was actually a result of reasoning; it is conceivable, however, that a man playing with pictures and mirrors might accidentally have hit upon it. Cats have been known to open doors by pulling latches, etc. But no cat, if the latch got out of order, could open the door again, unless some new accident of random fumbling taught her to associate some new total movement with the total phe nomenon of the closed door. A reasoning man, however, would open the door by first analyzing the hindrance. He would ascertain what particular feature of the door was wrong. The lever, e.g., does not raise the latch sufficiently from its slot — case of insufficient elevation — r^ loor bodily on hinges ! Or door sticks at top by friction * •• J; lintel — press it bodily down! Now it is obvious t.. child or an idiot might without this reasoning learn the '/ for opening that particular door. I remember a clock whic the maid-servant had discovered would not go unless it were supported so as to tilt slightly forwards. She had stumbled on this method after many weeks of groping. The reason of the stoppage was the friction of the pendulum- bob against the back of the clock-case, a reason which an educated man would have analyzed out in five minutes. I * Sometimes, it must be confessed, the conceiver's purpose falls short of reasoning and the only conclusion he cares to reach is the bare naming of the datum. " What is that?" is our first question relative to any unknown thing. And the ease with which our curiosity is quenched as soon as we are supplied with any sort of a name to call the object by, is ridiculous enough. To quote from an unpublished essay by a former student of mine, Mr. R. W. Black : " The simplest end which a thing's predicate can serve is the satisfaction of the desire for unity itself, the mere desire that the thing shall be the same with something else. Why, the other day, when I mistook a portrait of Shakespeare for one of Hawthorne, was I not, on psychological principles, as right as if I had correctly named it ? — the two pictures had a common essence, bald forehead, mustache, flowing hair. Simply because the only end that could possibly be served by naming it Hawthorne was my desire to have it so. With reference to any other end that classification of it would not serve. And every unity, every identity, ever)1 classification is rightly called fanciful unless it serves some other end than the mere satisfaction, emotion , or inspiration caught by momentarily believing in it." 340 PSYCHOLOGY. have a student's lamp of which the flame vibrates most un pleasantly unless the collar which bears the chimney be raised about a sixteenth of an inch. I learned the remedy after much torment by accident, and now always keep the collar up with a small wedge. But my procedure is a mere association of two totals, diseased object and remedy. One learned in pneumatics could have named the cause of the disease, and thence inferred the remedy immediately. By many measurements of triangles one might find their area always equal to their height multiplied by half their base, and one might formulate an empirical law to that effect. But a reasoner saves himself all this trouble by seeing that it is the essence (pro hoc vice) of a triangle to be the half of a parallelogram whose area is the height into the entire base. To see this he must invent additional lines ; and the geometer must often draw such to get at the essential prop erty he may require in a figure. The essence consists in some relation of the figure to the new lines, a relation not ob vious at all until they are put in. The geometer's sagacity lies in the invention of the new lines. THUS, THERE ABE TWO GREAT POINTS IN REASONING: First, an extracted character is taken as equivalent to the entire datum from which it comes ; and, Second, the character thus taken suggests a certain conse quence more obviously than it was suggested by the total datum as it originally came. Take them again, successively. 1. Suppose I say, when offered a piece of cloth, " I won't buy that; it looks as if it would fade," meaning merely that something about it suggests the idea of fading to my mind, — my judgment, though possibly correct, is not rea soned, but purely empirical ; but, if I can say that into the color there enters a certain dye which I know to be chemi cally unstable, and that therefore the color will fade, my judg ment is reasoned. The notion of the dye which is one of the parts of the cloth, is the connecting link between the latter and the notion of fading. So, again, an uneducated man will expect from past experience to see a piece of ice melt if placed near the fire, and the tip of his finger look coarse REASONING. 341 if he views it through a convex glass. In neither of these cases could the result be anticipated without full previous acquaintance with the entire phenomenon. It is not a result of reasoning. But a man who should conceive heat as a mode of motion, and liquefaction as identical with increased motion of molecules ; who should know that curved surfaces bend light-rays in special ways, and that the apparent size of anything is connected with the amount of the ' bend ' of its light-rays as they enter the eye,— such a man would make the right inferences for all these objects, even though he had never in his life had any concrete experience of them ; and he would do this because the ideas which we have above supposed him to possess would mediate in his mind between the phenomena he starts with and the conclusions he draws. But these ideas or reasons for his conclusions are all mere extracted portions or circumstances singled out from the mass of characters which make up the entire phenomena. The motions which form heat, the bending of the light-waves, are, it is true, excessively recondite ingredients ; the hidden pendulum I spoke of above is less so ; and the sticking of a door on its sill in the earlier ex ample would hardly be so at all. But each and all agree in this, that they bear a more evident relation to the con clusion than did the immediate data in their full totality. The difficulty is, in each case, to extract from the im mediate data that particular ingredient which shall have this very evident relation to the conclusion. Every phe nomenon or so-called ' fact ' has an infinity of aspects or properties, as we have seen, amongst which the fool, or man with little sagacity, will inevitably go astray. But no matter for this point now. The first thing is to have seen that every possible case of reasoning involves the extrac tion of a particular partial aspect of the phenomena thought about, and that whilst Empirical Thought simply associates phenomena in their entirety, Seasoned Thought couples them by the conscious use of this extract. 2. And, now, to prove the second point : Why are the couplings, consequences, and implications of extracts more 342 PSYCHOLOGY. evident and obvious than those of entire phenomena ? For two reasons. First, the extracted characters are more general than the concretes, and the connections they may have are, therefore, more familiar to us, having been more often met in our experience. Think of heat as motion, and what ever is true of motion will be true of heat ; but we have had a hundred experiences of motion for every one of heat. Think of the rays passing through this lens as bending towards the perpendicular, and you substitute for the com paratively unfamiliar lens the very familiar notion of a par ticular change in direction of a line, of which notion every day brings us countless examples. The other reason why the relations of the extracted characters are so evident is that their properties are so few, compared with the properties of the whole, from which we derived them. In every concrete total the characters and their consequences are so inexhaustibly numerous that we may lose our way among them before noticing the particular consequence it behooves us to draw. But, if we are lucky enough to single out the proper character, we take in, as it were, by a single glance all its possible consequences. Thus the character of scraping the sill has very few suggestions, prominent among which is the suggestion that the scraping will cease if we raise the door ; whilst the entire refractory door suggests an enormous num ber of notions to the mind. Take another example. I am sitting in a railroad-car, waiting for the train to start. It is winter, and the stove fills the car with pungent smoke. The brakeman enters, and my neighbor asks him to " stop that stove smoking/* He replies that it will stop entirely as soon as the car begins to move. "Why so?" asks the passenger. "It always does," replies the brakeman. It is evident from this * always ' that the connection between car moving and smoke stopping was a purely empirical one in the brake- man's mind, bred of habit. But, if the passenger had been an acute reasoner, he, with no experience of what that stove always did, might have anticipated the brakeman's reply, and spared his own question. Had he singled out of all the REASONING. 343 numerous points involved in a stove's not smoking the one special point of smoke pouring freely out of the stove-pipe's mouth, he would, probably, owing to the few associations of that idea, have been immediately reminded of the law that a fluid passes more rapidly out of a pipe's mouth if another fluid be at the same time streaming over that mouth ; and then the rapid draught of air over the stove pipe's mouth, which is one of the points involved in the car's motion, would immediately have occurred to him. Thus a couple of extracted characters, with a couple of their few and obvious connections, would have formed the reasoned link in the passenger's mind between the phenom ena, smoke stopping and car moving, which were only linked as wholes in the brakeman's mind. Such examples may seem trivial, but they contain the essence of the most refined and transcendental theorizing. The reason why physics grows more deductive the more the fundamental properties it as sumes are of a mathematical sort, such as molecular mass or wave-length, is that the immediate consequences of these notions are so few that we can survey them all at once, and promptly pick out those which concern us. Sagacity ; or the Perception of the Essence. To reason, then, we must be able to extract characters, — not any characters, but the right characters for our conclu sion. If we extract the wrong character, it will not lead to that conclusion. Here, then, is the difficulty: How are Characters extracted, and why does it require the advent of a genius in many cases before the fitting character is brought to light ? Why cannot anybody reason as well as anybody else ? Why does it need a Newton to notice the law of the squares, a Darwin to notice the survival of the fittest '? To answer these questions we must begin a new research, and gee how our insight into facts naturally grows. All our knowledge at first is vague. WThen we say that a thing is vague, we mean that it has no subdivisions ab in- tra, nor precise limitations ab extra ; but still all the forms of thought may apply to it. It may have unity, reality, ex ternality, extent, and what not — thinghood, in a word, but 344 PSYCHOLOGY. tliinghood only as a whole.* In tins vague way, probably, does the room appear to the babe who first begins to be conscious of it as something other than his moving nurse. It has no subdivisions in his mind, unless, perhaps, the window is able to attract his separate notice. In this vague way, certainly, does every entirely new experience appear to the adult. A library, a museum, a machine-shop, are mere confused wholes to the uninstructed, but the machin ist, the antiquary, and the bookworm perhaps hardly no tice the whole at all, so eager are they to pounce upon the details. Familiarity has in them bred discrimination. Such vague terms as ' grass,' ' mould,' and ' meat ' do not exist for the botanist or the anatomist. They know too much about grasses, moulds, and muscles. A certain per son said to Charles Kingsley, who was showing him the dis section of a caterpillar, with its exquisite viscera, " Why, I thought it was nothing but skin and squash !" A layman present at a shipwreck, a battle, or a fire is helpless. Dis crimination has been so little awakened in him by expe rience that his consciousness leaves no single point of the complex situation accented aud standing out for him to be gin to act upon. But the sailor, the fireman, and the gen eral know directly at what corner to take up the business. They ' see into the situation ' — that is, they analyze it — with their first glance. It is full of delicately differenced ingre dients which their education has little by little brought to their consciousness, but of which the novice gains no clear idea. How this power of analysis was brought about we saw in our chapters on Discrimination and Attention. We dis sociate the elements of originally vague totals by attending to them or noticing them alternately, of course. But what determines which element we shall attend to first ? There are two immediate and obvious answers : first, our practical or instinctive interests ; and, second, our aesthetic interests. The dog singles out of any situation its smells, and the horse its sounds, bcause they may reveal facts of practical mo ment, and are instinctively exciting to these several crea- * See above, p. 8. REASONING. 345 tures. The infant notices the candle-flame or the window, and ignores the rest of the room, because those objects give him a vivid pleasure. So, the country boy dissociates the blackberry, the chestnut, and the wintergreen, from the vague mass of other shrubs and trees, for their practical uses, and the savage is delighted with the beads, the bits of looking-glass, brought by an exploring vessel, and gives no heed to the features of the vessel itself, which is too much beyond his sphere. These aesthetic and practical interests, then, are the weightiest factors in making particular ingre dients stand out in high relief. What they lay their accent on, that we notice ; but what they are in themselves, we can not say. We must content ourselves here with simply ac cepting them as irreducible ultimate factors in determining the way our knowledge grows. Now, a creature which has few instinctive impulses, or interests, practical or aesthetic, will dissociate few charac ters, and will, at best, have limited reasoning powers ; whilst one whose interests are very varied will reason much better. Man, by his immensely varied instincts, practical wants, and aesthetic feelings, to which every sense contrib utes, would, by dint of these alone, be sure to dissociate vastly more characters than any other animal ; and accord ingly we find that the lowest savages reason incomparably better than the highest brutes. The diverse interests lead, too, to a diversification of experiences, whose accumulation becomes a condition for the play of that law of dissociation by varying concomitants of which I treated in a former chap ter (see Vol I. p. 506). The Help given by Association by Similarity. It is probable, also, that man's superior association by similarity has much to do with those discriminations of character on which his higher flights of reasoning are based. As this latter is an important matter, and as little or noth ing was said of it in the chapter on Discrimination, it be hooves me to dwell a little upon it here. What does the reader do when he wishes to see in what the precise likeness or difference of two objects lies ? He 346 PSYCHOLOGY. transfers his attention as rapidly as possible, backwards and forwards, from one to the other. The rapid alteration in consciousness shakes out, as it were, the points of dif ference or agreement, which would have slumbered forever unnoticed if the consciousness of the objects compared had occurred at widely distant periods of time. What does the scientific man do who searches for the reason or law embedded in a phenomenon '? He deliberately accumu lates all the instances he can find which have any analogy to that phenomenon ; and, by simultaneously filling his mind with them all, he frequently succeeds in detaching from the collection the peculiarity which he was unable to formulate in one alone ; even though that one had been preceded in his former experience by all of those with which he now at once confronts it. These examples show that the mere general fact of having occurred at some time in one's experience, with varying concomitants, is not by itself a sufficient reason for a character to be dissociated now. We need something more ; we need that the varying concomitants should in all their variety be brought into consciousness at once. Not till then will the character in question escape from its adhesion to each and all of them and stand alone. This will immediately be recognized by those who have read Mill's Logic as the ground of Utility in his famous ' four methods of experimental inquiry,' the methods of agreement, of difference, of residues, and of concomitant variations. Each of these gives a list of analogous instances out of the midst of which a sought-for character may roll and strike the mind. Now it is obvious that any mind in which association by similarity is highly developed is a mind which will spon taneously form lists of instances like this. Take a present case A, with a character ra in it. The mind may fail at first to notice this character m at all. But if A calls up C, D, E, and F, — these being phenomena which resemble A in possessing m, but which may not have entered for months into the experience of the animal who now experiences A, why, plainly, such association performs the part of the reader's deliberately rapid comparison referred to above, and of the systematic consideration of like cases by the REASONING. 347 scientific investigator, and may lead to the noticing of m in an abstract way. Certainly this is obvious ; and no conclusion is left to us but to assert that, after the few most powerful practical and aesthetic interests, our chief help towards noticing those special characters of phenom ena, which, when once possessed and named, are used as reasons, class names, essences, or middle terms, is this association by similarity. Without it, indeed, the deliberate procedure of the scientific man would be impossible : he could never collect his analogous instances. But it oper ates of itself in highly-gifted minds without any delibera tion, spontaneously collecting analogous instances, uniting in a moment what in nature the whole breadth of space and time keeps separate, and so permitting a perception of identical points in the midst of different circumstances, which minds governed wholly by the law of contiguity could never begin to attain. FIG. 80 Figure 80 shows this. If m, in the present representa tion A, calls up B, C, D, and E, which are similar to A in possessing it, and calls them up in rapid succession, then m, being associated almost simultaneously with such vary ing concomitants, will * roll out ' and attract our separate notice. 348 PSYCHOLOGY. If so much is clear to the reader, he will be willing to iidmit that the mind in which this mode of association most prevails will, from its better opportunity of extricating characters, be the one most prone to reasoned thinking ; whilst, on the other hand, a mind in which we do not detect reasoned thinking will probably be one in which association by contiguity holds almost exclusive sway. Geniuses are, by common consent, considered to diffei from ordinary minds by an unusual development of associa iion by similarity. One of Professor Bain's best strokes ol work is the exhibition of this truth.* It applies to geniuses in the line of reasoning as well as in other lines. And as the genius is to the vulgarian, so the vulgar human mind is to the intelligence of a brute. Compared with men, it is probable that brutes neither attend to abstract characters, nor have associations by similarity. Their thoughts prob ably pass from one concrete object to its habitual concrete successor far more uniformly than is the case with us. In other words, their associations of ideas are almost exclu sively by contiguity. It will clear up still farther oui understanding of the reasoning process, if we devote a few pages to THE INTELLECTUAL CONTRAST BETWEEN BRUTE AND MAN I will first try to show, by taking the best stories I cai find of animal sagacity, that the mental process involved may as a rule be perfectly accounted for by mere contigu ous association, based on experience. Mr. Darwin, in his 1 Descent of Man,' instances the Arctic dogs, described by Dr. Hayes, who scatter, when drawing a sledge, as soon a& the ice begins to crack. This might be called by some aik exercise of reason. The test would be, Would the most intelligent Eskimo dogs that ever lived act so when placed upon ice for the first time together ? A band of men from the tropics might do so easily. Recognizing cracking to be a sign of breaking, and seizing immediately the partial character that the point of rupture is the point of greatest *See his Study of Character, chap, xv ; also Senses and Intellect, 'Intellect/ chap, n, the latter half. REASONING. 349 Btrain, and that the massing of weight at a given point con centrates there the strain, a Hindoo might quickly infer that scattering would stop the cracking, and, by crying out to his comrades to disperse, save the party from immersion. But in the dog's case we need only suppose that they have individually experienced wet skins after cracking, that they have often noticed cracking to begin when they were huddled, together, and that they have observed it to cease when they scattered. Naturally, therefore, the sound would redintegrate all these former experiences, including that of scattering, which latter they would promptly renew. It would be a case of immediate suggestion or of that ' Logic of Recepts ' as Mr. Eomanes calls it, of which we spoke above on p. 327. A friend of the writer gave as a proof of the almost human intelligence of his dog that he took him one day down to his boat on the shore, but found the boat full of dirt and water. He remembered that the sponge was up at the house, a third of a mile distant ; but, disliking to go back himself, he made various gestures of wiping out the boat and so forth, saying to his terrier, " Sponge, sponge ; go fetch the sponge." But he had little expectation of a result, since the dog had never received the slightest training with the boat or the sponge. Nevertheless, off he trotted to the house, and, to his owner's great surprise and admiration, brought the sponge in his jaws. Sagacious as this was, it required nothing but ordinary contiguous association of ideas. The terrier was only exceptional in the minuteness of his spontaneous observation. Most terriers would have taken no interest in the boat-cleaning operation, nor no ticed what the sponge was for. This terrier, in having picked those details out of the crude mass of his boat-expe rience distinctly enough to be reminded of them, was truly enough ahead of his peers on the line which leads to human reason. But his act was not yet an act of reasoning proper. It might fairly have been called so if, unable to find the sponge at the house, he had brought back a dipper or a mop instead. Such a substitution would have shown that, embedded in the very different appearances of these articles, he had been able to discriminate the identical partial attri- 350 PSYCHOLOGY. bute of capacity to take up water, and had reflected, "For the present purpose they are identical." This, which the dog did not do, any man but the very stupidest could not fail to do. If the reader will take the trouble to analyze the best dog and elephant storier \e knows, he will find that, m most cases, this simple contiguous calling up of one whole by another is quite sufficient to explain the phenomena. Sometimes, it is true, we have to suppose the recognition of a property or character as such, but it is then always a char acter which the peculiar practical interests of the animal may have singled out. A dog, noticing his master's hat on its peg, may possibly infer that he has not gone out. Intelligent dogs recognize by the tone of the master's voice whether the latter is angry or not. A dog will perceive whether you have kicked him by accident or by design, and behave accordingly. The character inferred by him, the particular mental state in you, however it be represented in his mind — it is represented probably by a ' recept ' (p. 327) or set of practical tendencies, rather than by a definite con cept or idea — is still a partial character extracted from the totality of your phenomenal being, and is his reason for crouching and skulking, or playing with you. Dogs, more over, seem to have the feeling of the value of their master's personal property, or at least a particular interest in objects which their master uses. A dog left with his master's coat will defend it, though never taught to do so. I know of a dog accustomed to swim after sticks in the water, but who always refused to dive for stones. Nevertheless, when a fish- basket, which he had never been trained to carry, but mere ly knew as his master's, fell over, he immediately dived after it and brought it up. Dogs thus discern, at any rate so far as to be able to act, this partial character of being valuable^ which lies hidden in certain things.* Stories are told of * Whether the dog has the notion of your being angry or of your prop erty being valuable in any such abstract way as we have these notions is more than doubtful. The conduct is more likely an impulsive result of a conspiracy of outward stimuli ; the beast feels like acting so when these stimuli are present, though conscious of no definite reason why. The distinction of recept and concept is useful here. Some breeds of dogs, REASONING. 351 (togs carrying coppers to pastry-cooks to get buns, and it ia said that a certain dog, if lie gave two coppers, would never e.g. collies, seem instinctively to defend their master's property. The case is similar to that of a dog's barking at people after dark, at whom he would not bark in daylight. I have heard this quoted as evidence of the dog'a reasoning power. It is only, as Chapter III has shown us, the impulsive result of a summation of stimuli, and has no connection with reasoning. In certain stages of the hypnotic trance the subject seems to lapse into the non-analytic state. If a sheet of ruled foolscap paper, or a paper with a fine monotonous ornamental pattern printed on it, be shown to the sub ject, and one of the ruled lines or elements of the pattern be pointed to for an instant, and the paper immediately removed, he will then almost always, when after a short interval the paper is presented to him again, pick out the indicated line or element with infallible correctness. The operator, mean- while, has either to keep his eye fixed upon it, or to make sure of its posi tion by counting, in order not to lose its place. Just so we may remember a friend's house in a street by the single character of its number rather than by its general look. The trance-subject would seem, in these instan ces, to surrender himself to the general look. He disperses his attention impartially over the sheet. The place of the particular lino touched is part of a ' total effect ' which he gets in its entirety, and which would be distort ed if another line were touched instead. This total effect is lost upon the normal looker-on, bent as he is on concentration, analysis, and emphasis. What wonder, then, that, under these experimental conditions, the trance- subject excels him in touching the right line again ? If he has time given him to count the line, he will excel the trance-subject ; but if the time be too short to count, he will best succeed by following the trance-metho 1, ab staining from analysis, and being guided by the ' general look ' of the line's place on the sheet. One is surprised at one's success in this the moment one gives up one's habitually analytic state of mind. Is it too much to say that we have in this dispersion of the attention and subjection to the ' general effect ' something like a relapse into the state of mind of brutes? The trance-subject never gives any other reason for his optical discriminations, save that ' it looks so.' So a man, on a road once traversed inattentively before, takes a certain turn for no reason ex cept that he feels as if it must be right. He is guided by a sum of impres sions, not one of which is emphatic or distinguished from the rest, not one of which is essential, not one of which is conceived, but all of which together drive him to a conclusion to which nothing but that sum- total leads. Are not some of the wonderful discriminations of animals expli cable in the same way ? The cow finds her own stanchions in the long stable, the horse stops at the house he has once stopped at in the monoto nous street, because no other stanchions, no other house, yield impartially all the impressions of the previous experience. The man, however, by seek ing to make some one impression characteristic and essential, prevents the rest from having their effect. So that, if the (for him) essential feature be forgotten or changed, he is too apt to be thrown off altogether, and then the brute or the trance-subject may seem to outstrip him in sagacity. Dr. Romanes's already quoted distinction between ' receptual ' and 552 PSYCHOLOGY. leave without two buns. This was probably mere con tiguous association, but it is possible that the animal noticed the character of duality, and identified it as the same in the coin and the cake. If so, it is the maximum of canine abstract thinking. Another story told to the writer is this : a dog was sent to a lumber-camp to fetch a wedge, with which he was known to be acquainted. After half an hour, not returning, he was sought and found biting and tugging at the handle of an axe which was driven deeply into a stump. The wedge could not be found. The teller of the story thought that the dog must have had a clear perception of the common character of serving to split which was involved in both the instruments, and, from their identity in this respect, inferred their identity for the pur poses required. It cannot be denied that this interpretation is a possible one, but it seems to me far to transcend the limits of ordi nary canine abstraction. The property in question was not one which had direct personal interest for the dog, such as that of belonging to his master is in the case of the coat or the basket. If the dog in the sponge story had re turned to the boat with a dipper it would have been no more remarkable. It seems more probable, therefore, that this wood-cutter's dog had also been accustomed to carry the axe, and now, excited by the vain hunt for the wedge, had discharged his carrying powers upon the former instru ment in a sort of confusion — just as a man may pick up a sieve to carry water in, in the excitement of putting out a fire.* ' conceptual ' thought (published since the body of my text and my note were written) connotes conveniently the difference which I seek to point out. See also his Mental Evolution in Man, p. 197 ff., for proofs of the fact that in a receptual way brutes cognize the mental states of other brutes and men. * This matter of confusion is important and interesting. Since confu sion is mistaking the wrong part of the phenomenon for the whole, whilst reasoning is, according to our definition, based on the substitution of the right part for the whole, it might be said that confusion and reasoning are generically the same process. I believe that they are so, and that the only difference between a muddle-head and a genius is that between ex tracting wrong characters and right ones. In other words, a muddle-head- REASONING. 353 Thus, then, the characters extracted by animals are rery few, and always related to their immediate interests or emotions. That dissociation by varying concomitants, which in man is based so largely on association by similarity, hardly seems to take place at all in the mind of brutes. One total thought suggests to them another total thought, and they find themselves acting with propriety, they know not why. The great, the fundamental, defect of their minds seems to be the inability of their groups of ideas to break across in unaccustomed places. They are enslaved to routine, to cut-and-dried thinking ; and if the most prosaic of human beings could be transported into his dog's mind, he would be appalled at the utter absence of fancy which reigns there.* Thoughts will not be found to call up their similars, but only their habitual successors. Sunsets will not suggest heroes' deaths, but supper-time. This is why man is the only metaphysical animal. To wonder why the universe should be as it is presupposes the notion of its being different, and a brute, which never reduces the actual to fluidity by breaking up its literal sequences in his imagina tion, can never form such a notion. He takes the world simply for granted, and never wonders at it at all. Professor Striimpell quotes a dog-story which is prob ably a type of many others. The feat performed looks like abstract reasoning; but an acquaintance with all the cir cumstances shows it to have been a random trick learned by habit. The story is as follows : 44 1 have two dogs, a small, long-legged pet dog and a rather large watch-dog. Immediately beyond the house-court is the garden, into which one enters through a low lattice-gate which is closed by a latch ed person is a genius spoiled in the making. I think it will be admitted that all eminently muddle-headed persons have the temperament of genius. They are constantly breaking away from the usual consecutions of con cretes. A common associator by contiguity is too closely tied to routine to get muddle-headed. - The horse is a densely stupid animal, as far as everything goes except contiguous association. We reckon him intelligent, partly because he looks so handsome, partly because he has such a wonderful faculty of contiguous association and can be so quickly moulded into a mass of set habits. Had he anything of reasoning intelligence, he would be a less faithful slave than he is. 354 PSYCHOLOGY. ^n the yard-side. This latch is opened by lifting it. Besides this, moreover, the gate is fastened on the garden-side by a string nailed to the gate-post Here, as often as one wished, could the following sight be observed. If the little dog was shut in the garden and he wished to get out, he placed himself before the gate and barked. Immediately the large dog in the court would hasten to him and raise the latch with his nose while the little dog on the garden-side leaped up and, catching the string in his teeth, bit it through ; whereupon the big one wedged his snout between the gate and the post, pushed the gate open, and the little dog slipped through. Certainly reasoning seems here to prevail. In face of it, however, and although the dogs arrived of themselves, and without human aid, at their solution of the gate question, I am able to point out that the complete action was pieced together out of accidental experiences which 'the dogs followed, I might say, unconsciously. While the large dog was young, he was allowed, like the little one, to go into the garden, and therefore the gate was usually not latched, but simply closed. Now if he saw anyone go in, he would follow by thrusting his snout between gate and post, and so pushing the gate open. When he was grown I forbade his being taken in, and had the gate kept latched. But he naturally still tried to follow when anyone entered and tried m the old fashion to open it, which he could no longer do. Now it fell out that once, while making the attempt, he raised his nose higher than usual and hit the latch from below so as to lift it off its hook, and the gate unclosed. From thenceforth he made the same movement of the head when trying to open it, and, of course, with the same result. He now knew how to open the gate when it was latched. ' ' The little dog had been the large one's teacher in many things, especially in the chasing of cats and the catching of mice and moles; so when the little one was heard barking eagerly, the other always has tened to him. If the barking came from the garden, he opened the gate to get inside. But meanwhile the little dog, who wanted to get out the moment the gate opened, slipped out between the big one's legs, and so the appearance of his having come with the intention of letting him out arose. And that it was simply an appearance transpired from the fact that when the little dog did not succeed at once in getting out, the large one ran in and nosed about the garden, plainly showing that he had ex pected to find something there. In order to stop this opening of the gate I fastened a string on the garden-side which, tightly drawn, held the gate firm against the post, so that if the yard dog raised the latch and let go, it would every time fall back on to the hook. And this device was successful for quite a time, until it happened one day that on my return from a walk upon which the little dog had accompanied me I crossed the garden, and in passing through the gate the dog re mained behind, and refused to come to my whistle. As it was begin ning to rain, and I knew how he disliked to get wet, I closed the gate in order to punish him in this manner. But I had hardly reached the house ere he was before the gate, whining and crying most piteously, REASONING. 355 for the rain was falling faster and faster. The big dog, to whom the rain was a matter of perfect indifference, was instantly on hand and tried his utmost to open the gate, but naturally without success. Al most in despair the little dog bit at the gate, at the same time springing into the air in the attempt to jump over it, when he chanced to catch the string in his teeth ; it broke, and the gate flew open. Now he knew the secret and thenceforth bit the string whenever he wished to get out, so that I was obliged to change it. " That the big dog in raising the latch did not in the least know that the latch closed the gate, that the raising of the same opened it, but that he merely repeated the automatic blow with his snout which had once had such happy consequences, transpires from the following : the gate leading to the barn is fastened with a latch precisely like the one on the garden-gate, only placed a little higher, still easily within the dog's reach. Here, too, occasionally the little dog is confined, and when he barks the big one makes every possible effort to open the gate, but it has never occurred to him to push the latch up. The brute cannot draw conclusions, that is, he cannot think. " * Other classical differentia of man besides that of being the only reasoning animal, also seem consequences of his unrivalled powers of similar association. He has, e.g., been called « the laughing animal.' But humor has often been defined as the recognition of identities in things different. When the man in Coriolanus says of that hero that " there is no more mercy in him than there is milk in a male tiger,'* both the invention of the phrase and its enjoyment by the hearer depend on a peculiarly perplexing power to associ ate ideas by similarity. Man is known again as 'the talking animal' ; and lan- * Th Schumann : Journal Daheim, No. 19, 1878. Quoted by Strum- pel] ;: Die Geisteskrafte der Menschen verglichen mit denen der Thiere (Leipzig, 1878), p. 39. Cats are notorious for the skill with which they will open latches, locks, etc. Their feats are usually ascribed to their reason- ing powers. But Dr. Romanes well remarks (Mental Evolution, etc., p. 351, note) that we ought first to be sure that the actions are not due to mere nssociation. A cat is constantly playing with things with her paws ; a trick accidentally hit upon may be retained. Romanes notes the fact that the animals most skilled in this way need not be the most generally intelligent, but those which have the best corporeal members for handling things cat's paws, horse's lips, elephant's trunk, cow's horns. The monkey has 3th the corporeal and the intellectual superiority. And my deprecatory remarks on animal reasoning in the text apply far less to the quadrumana than to quadrupeds. -On the possible fallacies in interpreting animals' minds, compare C. L. Morgan in Mind, xi. 174 (1886) 356 PSYCHOLOGY. guage is assuredly a capital distinction between man and brute. But it may readily be shown how this distinction merely flows from those we have pointed out, easy disso ciation of a representation into its ingredients, and associa tion by similarity. Language is a system of signs, different from the things signified, but able to suggest them. No doubt brutes have a number of such signs. When a dog yelps in front of a door, and his master, understand ing his desire, opens it, the dog may, after a certain number of repetitions, get to repeat in cold blood a yelp which was at first the involuntary interjectional expression of strong emotion. The same dog may be taught to ' beg ' for food, and afterwards come to do so deliberately when hungry. The dog also learns to understand the signs of men, and the word ' rat ' uttered to a terrier suggests exciting thoughts of the rat-hunt. If the dog had the varied im pulse to vocal utterance which some other animals have, he would probably repeat the word ' rat ' whenever he spontaneously happened to think of a rat-hunt — he no doubt does have it as an auditory image, just as a parrot calls out different words spontaneously from its repertory, and having learned the name of a given dog will utter it on the sight of a different dog. In each of these separate cases the particular sign may be consciously noticed by the ani mal, as distinct from the particular thing signified, and will thus, so far as it goes, be a true manifestation of language. But when we come to man we find a great difference. He has a deliberate intention to apply a sign to everything. The linguistic impulse is with him generalized and systematic. For things hitherto unnoticed or unfelt, he desires a sign before he has one. Even though the dog should possess his ' yelp ' for this thing, his ' beg ' for that, and his audi tory image 'rat' for a third thing, the matter with him rests there. If a fourth thing interests him for which no sign happens already to have been learned, he remains tran quilly without it and goes no further. But the man postu lates it, its absence irritates him, and he ends by inventing it This GENERAL PUHPOSE constitutes, I take it, the peculiarity of human speech, and explains its prodigious development. REASONING. 357 How, then, does the general purpose arise ? It arises as soon as the notion of a sign as such, apart from any par ticular import, is born ; and this notion is born by dis sociation from the outstanding portions of a number of concrete cases of signification. The ' yelp,' the ' beg,' the * rat,' differ as to their several imports and natures. They agree only in so far as they have the same use — to be signs, to stand for something more important than themselves. The dog whom this similarity could strike would have grasped the sign per se as such, and would probably thereupon become a general sign-maker, or speaker in the human sense. But how can the similarity strike him? Not without the juxtaposition of the similars (in virtue of the law we have laid down (p. 506), that in order to be segregated an experience must be repeated with varying concomitants) — not unless the 'yelp' of the dog at the moment it occurs recalls to him his ' beg,' by the delicate bond of their subtle similarity of use — not till then can this thought flash through his mind : " Why, yelp and beg, in spite of all their unlikeness, are yet alike in this : that they are actions, signs, which lead to important boons. Other boons, any boons, may then be got by other signs !" This reflection made, the gulf is passed. Animals probably never make it, because the bond of similarity is not delicate enough. Each sign is drowned in its import, and never awakens other signs and other imports in jux taposition. The rat-hunt idea is too absorbingly interest ing in itself to be interrupted by anything so uncontiguoua to it as the idea of the ' beg for food,' or of ' the door-open yelp,' nor in their turn do these awaken the rat-hunt idea. In the human child, however, these ruptures of contigu ous association are very soon made ; far off cases of sign- using arise when we make a sign now ; and soon language is launched. The child in each case makes the discovery for himself. No one can help him except by furnishing him with the conditions. But as he is constituted, the con ditions will sooner or later shoot together .into the result* * There are two other conditions of language in the human being, addi tional to association by similarity, that assist its action, or rather pave the way for it. These are: first, the great natural loquacity; and, second, the 358 PSYCHOLOGY. The exceedingly interesting account which Dr. Howe gives of the education of his various blind-deaf mutes illus trates this point admirably. He began to teach Laura Bridgman by gumming raised letters on various familiar articles. The child was taught by mere contiguity to pick out a certain number of particular articles when made to feel the letters. But this was merely a collection of par ticular signs, out of the mass of which the general purpose of signification had not yet been extracted by the child's mind. Dr. Howe compares his situation at this moment to that of one lowering a line to the bottom of the deep sea in which Laura's soul lay, and waiting until she should spon taneously take hold of it and be raised into the light. The moment came, ' accompanied by a radiant flash of intelli gence and glow of joy '; she seemed suddenly to become aware of the general purpose imbedded in the different de tails of all these signs, and from that moment her education went on with extreme rapidity. Another of the great capacities in which man has been said to differ fundamentally from the animal is that of pos- great imitativeness of man. The first produces the original reflex inter- jectioual sign; the second (as Bleek has well shown) fixes it, stamps it, and ends by multiplying the number of determinate specific signs which are a requisite preliminary to the general conscious purpose of sign-making, which I have called the characteristic human element in language. The way in which imitativeness fixes the meaning of signs is this: When a pri meval man has a given emotion, he utters his natural interjection; or when (to avoid supposing that the reflex sounds are exceedingly determinate by nature) a group of such men experience a common emotion, and one takes the lead in the cry, the others cry like him from sympathy or imitative- ness. Now, let one of the group hear another, who is in presence of the experience, utter the cry; he, even without the experience, will repeat the cry from pure imitativeness. But, as he repeats the sign, he will be re minded by it of his own former experience. Thus, first, he has the sign with the emotion; then, without it; then, with it again. It is " dissociated by change of concomitants "; he feels it as a separate entity and yet as hav ing a connection with the emotion. Immediately it becomes possible for him to couple it deliberately with the emotion, in cases where the latter would either have provoked no interjectional cry or not the same one. In a word, his mental procedure tends to fix this cry on that emotion; and when this occurs, in many instances, he is provided with a stock of signs, like the yelp, beg, rat of the dog, each of -which suggests a determinate image. On this stock, then, similarity works in the way above explained. REASONING. 359 sessing self-consciousness or reflective knowledge of him self as a thinker. But this capacity also flows from our criterion, for (without going into the matter very deeply) we may say that the brute never reflects on himself as a thinker, because he has never clearly dissociated, in the full concrete act of thought, the element of the thing thought of and the operation by which he thinks it. They remain always fused, conglomerated — just as the interjec- tional vocal sign of the brute almost invariably merges in his mind with the thing signified, and is not independently attended to in se* Now, the dissociation of these two elements probably occurs first in thb child's mind on the occasion of some error or false expectation which would make him experience the shock of difference between merely imagining a thing and getting it. The thought experienced once with the concomitant reality, and then without it or with opposite concomitants, reminds the child of other cases in which the same provoking phenomenon occurred. Thus the general ingredient of error may be dissociated and noticed per se, and from the notion of his error or wrong thought to that of his thought in general the transition is easy. The brute, no doubt, has plenty of instances of error and disappointment in his life, but the similar shock is in him most likely al ways swallowed up in the accidents of the actual case. An expectation disappointed may breed dubiety as to the reali zation of that particular thing when the dog next expects it. But that disappointment, that dubiety, while they are present in the mind, will not call up other cases, in which the material details were different, but this feature of pos- * See the ' Evolution of Self-consciousness ' in ' Philosophical Discus sions,' by Chauncey Wright (New York: Henry Holt & Co. , 1877). Dr. Ro, manes, in the book from which I have already quoted, seeks to show that the ' consciousness of truth as truth ' and the deliberate intention to predi cate (which are the characteristics of higher human reasoning) presuppose a consciousness of ideas as such, as things distinct from their objects ; and that this consciousness depends on our having made signs for them by language. My text seems to me to include Dr. Romanes's facts, and formu lates them in what to me is a more elementary way, though the reader who wishes to understand the matter better should go to his clear and patient exposition also. 360 PSYCHOLOGY. sible error was the same. The brute will, therefore, stop short of dissociating the general notion of error per se, and a fortiori will never attain the conception of Thought itself as such. We may then, we think, consider it proven that the most elementary single difference between the human mind and that of brutes lies in this deficiency on the brute's part to associate ideas by similarity — characters, the abstraction of which depends on this sort of association, must in the brute always remain drowned, swamped in the total phenomenon which they help constitute, and never used to reason from. If a char acter stands out alone, it is always some obvious sensible quality like a sound or a smell which is instinctively excit ing and lies in the line of the animal's propensities ; or it is some obvious sign which experience has habitually coupled with a consequence, such as, for the dog, the sight of his master's hat on and the master's going out. DIFFERENT ORDERS OF HUMAN GENIUS. But, now, since nature never makes a jump, it is evident that we should find the lowest men occupying in this respect an intermediate position between the brutes and the highest men. And so we do. Beyond the analogies which their own minds suggest by breaking up the literal sequence of their experience, there is a whole world of analogies which they can appreciate when imparted to them by their betters, but which they could never excogitate alone. This answers the question why Darwin and Newton had to be waited for so long. The flash of similarity between an apple and the moon, between the rivalry for food in nature and the rivalry for man's selection, was too recondite to have occurred to any but exceptional minds. Genius, then, as has been already said, is identical with the possession of similar association to an extreme degree. Professor Bain says : " This I count the leading fact of genius. I consider it quite impossible to afford any explanation of intellectual originality except on the supposition of unusual energy on this point." Alike in the arts, in literature, in practical affairs, and in science, association by similarity is the prime condition of success. REASONING. 361 But as, according to our view, there are two stages in reasoned thought, one where similarity merely operates to call up cognate thoughts, and another farther stage, where the^ bond of identity between the cognate thoughts is noticed; so minds of genius may be divided into tivo main sorts, those ivho notice the bond and those who merely obey it. The first are the abstract reasoners, properly so called, the men of science, and philosophers— the analysts, in a word ; the latter are the poets, the critics— the artists, in a ^ word, the men of intuitions. These judge rightly, classify cases, characterize them by the most striking ana logic epithets, but go no further. At first sight it might seem that the analytic mind represented simply a higher intellectual stage, and that the intuitive mind represented an arrested stage of intellectual development ; but the dif ference is not so simple as this. Professor Bain has said that a man's advance to the scientific stage (the stage of noticing and abstracting the bond of similarity) may often be due to an absence of certain emotional sensibilities. The sense of color, he says, may no less determine a mind away from science than it determines it toward painting. There must be a penury in one's interest in the details of particu lar forms in order to permit the forces of the intellect to be concentrated on what is common to many forms.* In other words, supposing a mind fertile in the suggestion of analogies, but, at the same time, keenly interested in the particulars of each suggested image, that mind would be far less apt to single out the particular character which called up the analogy than one whose interests were less generally lively. A certain richness of the sesthetic nature may, therefore, easily keep one in the intuitive stage. All the poets are examples of this. Take Homer : " Ulysses, too, spied round the house to see if any man were still alive and hiding, trying to get away from gloomy death. He found hem all fallen in the blood and dirt, and in such number as the fish the fishermen to the low shore, out of the foaming sea drag with their meshy nets. These all, sick for the ocean water, are strewn around the sands, while the blazing sun takes their life from them So the suitors lay strewn round on one another." Or again : * Study of Character, p. 317. 362 PSYCHOLOGY. "And as when a Mseonian or a Carian woman stains ivory with purple to be a cheek-piece for horses, and it is kept in the chamber, and many horsemen have prayed to bear it off ; but it is kept a treasure for a king, both a trapping for his horse and a glory to the driver — in such wise were thy stout thighs, Menelaos, and legs and fair ankles stained with blood."* A man in whom all the accidents of an analogy rise up as vividly as this, may be excused for not attending to the ground of the analogy. But he need not on that account be deemed intellectually the inferior of a man of drier mind, in whom the ground is not as liable to be eclipsed by the general splendor. Karely are both sorts of intellect, the splendid and the analytic, found in conjunction, Plato among philosophers, and M. Taine, who cannot quote a child's saying without describing the ' voix chantante, etonnee, heureuse' in which it is uttered, are only excep tions whose strangeness proves the rule. An often-quoted writer has said that Shakespeare pos sessed more intellectual power than any one else that ever lived. If by this he meant the power to pass from given premises to right or congruous conclusions, it is no doubt true. The abrupt transitions in Shakespeare's thought astonish the reader by their unexpectedness no less than they delight him by their fitness. Why, for instance, does the death of Othello so stir the spectator's blood and leave him with a sense of reconcilement? Shakespeare himself could very likely not say why ; for his invention, though rational, was not ratiocinative. Wishing the curtain to fall upon a reinstated Othello, that speech about the turbaned Turk suddenly simply flashed across him as the right end of all that went before. The dry critic who comes after can, however, point out the subtle bonds of identity that guided Shakespeare's pen through that speech to the death of the Moor. Othello is sunk in ignominy, lapsed from his height at the beginning of the play. What better way to rescue him at last from this abasement than to make him for an instant identify himself in memory with the old Othello of better days, and then execute justice on his pres ent disowned body, as he used then to smite all enemies of * Translated by my colleague, Professor G. H. Palmer. REASONING. 363 the State ? But Shakespeare, whose mind supplied these means, could probably not have told why they were so effective. But though this is true, and though it would be absurd in an absolute way to say that a given analytic mind was superior to any intuitional one, yet it is none the less true that the former represents the higher stage. Men, taken historically, reason by analogy long before they have learned to reason by abstract characters. Association by similarity and true reasoning may have identical results. If a philos opher wishes to prove to you why you should do a certain thing, he may do so by using abstract considerations exclu sively ; a savage will prove the same by reminding you of a similar case in which you notoriously do as he now pro poses, and this with no ability to state the point in which the cases are similar. In all primitive literature, in all savage oratory, we find persuasion carried on exclusively by parables and similes, and travellers in savage countries readily adopt the native custom. Take, for example, Dr. Livingstone's argument with the negro conjuror. The mis sionary was trying to dissuade the savage from his fetichistic ways of invoking rain. "You see," said he, "that, after all your operations, sometimes it rains and sometimes it does not, exactly as when you have not operated at all." " But," replied the sorcerer, "it is just the same with you doctors; you give your remedies, and sometimes the patient gets well and sometimes he dies, just as when you do nothing at all." To that the pious missionary replied : " The doctor does his duty, after which God performs the cure if it pleases Him." " Well," rejoined the savage, " it is just so with me. I do what is necessary to procure rain, after which God sends it or withholds it according to His pleasure." * This is the stage in which proverbial philosophy reigns supreme. " An empty sack can't stand straight" will stand for the reason why a man with debts may lose his honesty ; and " a bird in the hand is worth two in the bush" will serve to back up one's exhortations to prudence. Or we answer the question : " Why is snow white ?" by saying, " For the * Quoted by Renouvier, Critique Philosophique, October 19, 1879. 364 PSYCHOLOGY. same reason that soap-suds or whipped eggs are white"- in other words, instead of giving the reason for a fact, we give another example of the same fact. This offering a simi lar instance, instead of a reason, has often been criticised as one of the forms of logical depravity in men. But mani festly it is not a perverse act of thought, but only an in complete one. Furnishing parallel cases is the necessary first step towards abstracting the reason imbedded in them all. As it is with reasons, so it is with words. The first words are probably always names of entire things and en tire actions, of extensive coherent groups. A new experi ence in the primitive man can only be talked about by him in terms of the old experiences which have received names. It reminds him of certain ones from among them, but the points in which it agrees with them are neither named nor dissociated. Pure similarity must work before the abstraction can work which is based upon it. The first adjectives will therefore probably be total nouns embody ing the striking character. The primeval man will say,, not ' the bread is hard,' but ' the bread is stone' ; not ' the face is round,' but * the face is moon' ; not ' the fruit is sweet,' but 'the fruit is sugar-cane.' The first words are thus neither particular nor general, but vaguely concrete ; just as we speak of an ' oval ' face, a ' velvet ' skin, or an 'iron' will, without meaning to connote any other attributes of the adjective-noun than those in which it does resemble the noun it is used to qualify. After a while certain of these adjectively-used nouns come only to signify the particular quality for whose sake they are oftenest used ; the entire thing which they originally meant receives another name, and they become true abstract and general terms. Oval, for example, with us suggests only shape. The first abstract qualities thus formed are, no doubt, qualities of one and the same sense found in different objects — as big, sweet ; next analogies between different senses, as ' sharp ' of taste, ' high ' of sound, etc. ; then analogies of motor combinations, or form ot relation, as simple, confused, difficult, reciprocal, relative, spontane ous, etc. The extreme degree of subtlety in analogy is REASONING. 365 reached in such cases as when we say certain English art critics' writing reminds us of a close room in which pastilles have been burning, or that the mind of certain Frenchmen is like old Roquefort cheese. Here language utterly fails to hit upon the basis of resemblance. Over immense departments of our thought we are still, all of us, in the savage state. Similarity operates in us, but abstraction has not taken place. We know what the pres ent case is like, we know what it reminds us of, we have an intuition of the right course to take, if it be a practical mat ter. But analytic thought has made no tracks, and we can not justify ourselves to others. In ethical, psychological, and aesthetic matters, to give a clear reason for one's judg ment is universally recognized as a mark of rare genius. The helplessness of uneducated people to account for their likes and dislikes is often ludicrous. Ask the first Irish girl why she likes this country better or worse than her home, and see how much she can tell you. But if you ask your most educated friend why he prefers Titian to Paul Veronese, you will hardly get more of a reply ; and you will probably get absolutely none if you inquire why Beethoven reminds him of Michael Angelo, or how it comes that a bare figure with unduly flexed joints, by the latter, can so suggest the moral tragedy of life. His thought obeys a nexus, but cannot name it. And so it is with all those judg ments of experts, which even though unmotived are so valu able. Saturated with experience of a particular class of materials, an expert intuitively feels whether a newly-re ported fact is probable or not, whether a proposed hypoth esis is worthless or the reverse. He instinctively knows that, in. a novel case, this and not that will be the promising course of action. The well-known story of the old judge advising the new one never to give reasons for his decisions, " the decisions will probably be right, the reasons will surely be wrong," illustrates this. The doctor will feel that the patient is doomed, the dentist will have a premonition that the tooth will break, though neither can articulate a reason for his foreboding. The reason lies imbedded, but not yet laid bare, in all the countless previous cases dimly sug gested by the actual one, all calling up the same conclusion, 366 PSYCHOLOGY. which the adept thus finds himself swept on to, he knows not how or why. A physiological conclusion remains to be drawn. If the principles laid down in Chapter XIV are true, then it fol lows that the great cerebral difference between habitual and reasoned thinking must be this : that in the former an entire system of cells vibrating at any one moment discharges in its totality into another entire system, and that the order of the discharges tends to be a constant one in time ; whilst in the latter a part of the prior system still keeps vibrating in the midst of the subsequent system, and the order— which part this shall be, and what shall be its concomitants in the. subsequent system — has little tendency to fixedness in time. This physical selection, so to call it, of one part to vibrate persistently whilst the others rise and subside, we found, in the chapter in question, to be the basis of similar association. (See especially pp. 578-81.) It would seem to be but a minor degree of that still more urgent and importunate localized vibration which we can easiest conceive to underlie the mental fact of interest, attention, or dissociation. In terms of the brain-process, then, all these mental facts resolve themselves into a single peculi arity: that of indeterminateness of connection between the different tracts, and tendency of action to focalize itself, so to speak, in small localities which vary infinitely at different times, and from which irradiation may pro ceed in countless shifting ways. (Compare figure 80, p. 347.) To discover, or (what more befits the present stage of nerve-physiology) to adumbrate by some possible guess, on what chemical or molecular-mechanical fact this instable equilibrium of the human brain may depend, should be the next task of the physiologist who ponders over the passage from brute to man. Whatever the physical peculiarity in question may be, it is the cause why a man, whose brain has it, reasons so much, whilst his horse, whose brain lacks it, reasons so little. We can but bequeath the problem to abler hands than our own. But, meanwhile, this mode of stating the matter suggests a couple of other inferences. The first is brief. If focali- REASONING. 36? zation of brain-activity be the fundamental fact of reasonable thought, we see why intense interest or concentrated pas sion makes us think so much more truly and profoundly. The persistent focalization of motion in certain tracts is the cerebral fact corresponding to the persistent domination in consciousness of the important feature of the subject. When not 'focalized,' we are scatter-brained; but when thoroughly impassioned, we never wander from the point None but congruous and relevant images arise. When roused by indignation or moral enthusiasm, how trenchant are our reflections, how smiting are our words ! The whole network of petty scruples and by-considerations which, at ordinary languid times, surrounded the matter like a cob web, holding back our thought, as Gulliver was pinned to the earth by the myriad Lilliputian threads, are dashed through at a blow, and the subject stands with its essential and vital lines revealed. The last point is relative to the theory that what was acquired habit in the ancestor may become congenital ten dency in the offspring. So vast a superstructure is raised upon this principle that the paucity of empirical evidence for it has alike been matter of regret to its adherents, and of triumph to its opponents. In Chapter XXVIII we shall see what we may call the whole beggarly array of proof. In the human race, where our opportunities for observation are the most complete, we seem to have no evidence what ever which would support the hypothesis, unless it possibly be the law that city-bred children are more apt to be near-sighted than country children. In the mental world we certainly do not observe that the children of great travellers get their geography lessons with unusual ease, or that a baby whose ancestors have spoken German for thirty generations will, on that account, learn Italian any the less easily from its Italian nurse. But if the con siderations we have been led to are true, they explain perfectly well why this law should not be verified in the human race, and why, therefore, in looking for evidence on the subject, we should confine ourselves exclusively to lower animals. In them fixed habit is the essential and 368 PSYCHOLOGY. characteristic law of nervous action. The brain grows to the exact modes in which it has been exercised, and the in heritance of these modes — then called instincts — would have in it nothing surprising. But in man the negation of all fixed modes is the essential characteristic. He owes his whole pre-eminence as a reasoner, his whole human quality of intellect, we may say, to the facility with which a given mode of thought in him may suddenly be broken up into elements, which recombine anew. Only at the price of in heriting no settled instinctive tendencies is he able to settle every novel case by the fresh discovery by his reason of novel principles. He is, par excellence, the educable animal. If, then, the law that habits are inherited were found exem plified in him, he would, in so far forth, fall short of his human perfections ; and, when we survey the human races, we actually do find that those which are most instinctive at the outset are those which, on the whole, are least educated in the end. An untutored Italian is, to a great extent, a man of the world ; he has instinctive perceptions, tendencies to behavior, reactions, in a word, upon his environment, which the untutored German wholly lacks. If the latter be not drilled, he is apt to be a thoroughly loutish personage ; but, on the other hand, the mere absence in his brain of definite innate tendencies enables him to advance by the de velopment, through education, of his purely reasoned think ing, into complex regions of consciousness that the Italian may probably never approach. We observe an identical difference between men as a whole and women as a whole. A young woman of twenty re acts with intuitive promptitude and security in all the usual circumstances in which she may be placed.* Her likes * Social and domestic circumstances, that is, not material ones. Per ceptions of social relations seem very keen in persons whose dealings with the material world are confined to knowing a few useful objects, princi pally animals, plants, and weapons. Savages and boors are often as tact ful and astute socially as trained diplomatists. In general, it is provable that the consciousness of how one stands with other people occupies a rela tively larger and larger part of the mind, the lower one goes in the scale of culture. Woman's intuitions, so fine in the sphere of personal relations, are seldom first-rate in the way of mechanics. All boys teach themselves how a clock goes ; few girls. Hence Dr. Whately's jest, "Woman is the unreasoning animal, and pokes the fire from on top!" REASONING. 369 and dislikes are formed ; her opinions, to a great extent, the same that they will be through life. Her character is, in fact, finished in its essentials. How inferior to her is a boy of twenty in all these respects ! His character is still gelat inous, uncertain what shape to assume, ' trying it on ' in every direction. Feeling his power, yet ignorant of the manner in which he shall express it, he is, when compared with his sister, a being of no definite contour. But this absence of prompt tendency in his brain to set into particu lar modes is the very condition which insures that it shall ultimately become so much more efficient than the woman's. The very lack of preappointed trains of thought is the ground on which general principles and heads of classifi cation grow up ; and the masculine brain deals with new and complex matter indirectly by means of these, in a manner which the feminine method of direct intuition, ad mirably and rapidly as it performs within its limits, can vainly hope to cope with. In looking back over the subject of reasoning, one feels how intimately connected it is with conception ; and one realizes more than ever the deep reach of that principle of selection on which so much stress was laid towards the close of Chapter IX. As the art of reading (after a certain stage in one's education) is the art of skipping, so the art of being wise is the art of knowing what to overlook. The first effect on the mind of growing cultivated is that processes once multiple get to be performed by a single act. Lazarus has called this the progressive ' condensation ' of thought. But in the psychological sense it is less a condensation than a loss, a genuine dropping out and throwing overboard of conscious content. Steps really sink from sight. An ad vanced thinker sees the relations of his topics in such masses and so instantaneously that when he comes to explain to younger minds it is often hard to say which grows the more perplexed, he or the pupil. In every uni versity there are admirable investigators who are notori ously bad lecturers. The reason is that they never spon taneously see the subject in the minute articulate way in which the student needs to have it offered to his slow 370 PSYCHOLOGY. reception. They grope for the links, but the links dc not €ome. Bowditch, who translated and annotated Laplace's Mecanique Celeste, said that whenever his author prefaced a proposition by the words 'it is evident,' he knew that many hours of hard study lay before him. When two minds of a high order, interested in kindred subjects, come together, their conversation is chiefly re- markable for the summariness of its allusions and the rapidity of its transitions. Before one of them is half through a sentence the other knows his meaning and replies. Such genial play with such massive materials, such an easy flashing of light over far perspectives, such careless indifference to the dust and apparatus that ordi narily surround the subject and seem to pertain to its essence, make these conversations seem true feasts for gods to a listener who is educated enough to follow them at all. His mental lungs breathe more deeply, in an atmos phere more broad and vast than is their wont. On the other hand, the excessive explicitness and short-windedness of an ordinary man are as wonderful as they are tedious to the man of genius. But we need not go as far as the ways of genius. Ordinary social intercourse will do. There the charm of conversation is in direct proportion to the possi bility of abridgment and elision, and in inverse ratio to the need of explicit statement. With old friends a word stands for a whole story or set of opinions. With new-comers everything must be gone over in detail. Some persons have a real mania for completeness, they must express every step. They are the most intolerable of companions, and although their mental energy may in its way be great, they always strike us as weak and second-rate. In short, the essence of plebeianism, that which separates vulgarity from aristocracy, is perhaps less a defect than an excess, the constant need to animadvert upon matters which for the aristocratic temperament do not exist. To ignore, to disdain to consider, to overlook, are the essence of the * gentleman.' Often most provokingly so ; for the things ignored may be of the deepest moral consequence. But in the very midst of our indignation with the gentleman, we have a consciousness that his preposterous inertia and neg* REASONING. 371 ativeness in the actual emergency is, somehow or other, •allied with his general superiority to ourselves. It is not only that the gentleman ignores considerations relative to conduct, sordid suspicions, fears, calculations, etc., which the vulgarian is fated to entertain ; it is that he is silent where the vulgarian talks ; that he gives nothing but results where the vulgarian is profuse of reasons ; that he does not explain or apologize ; that he uses one sentence instead of twenty ; and that, in a word, there is an amount of intersti tial thinking, so to call it, which it is quite impossible to get him to perform, but which is nearly all that the vul garian mind performs at all. All this suppression of the secondary leaves the field clear, — for higher flights, should they choose to come. But even if they never came, what thoughts there were would still manifest the aristocratic type and wear the well-bred form. So great is our sense of harmony and ease in passing from the company of a phi- listine to that of an aristocratic temperament, that we are almost tempted to deem the falsest views and tastes as held by a man of the world, truer than the truest as held by a common person. In the latter the best ideas are choked, obstructed, and contaminated by the redundancy of their paltry associates. The negative conditions, at least, of an atmosphere and a free outlook are present in the former. I may appear to have strayed from psychological an alysis into aesthetic criticism. But the principle of selec tion is so important that no illustrations seem redundant which may help to show how great is its scope. The upshot of what I say simply is that selection implies rejec tion as well as choice ; and that the function of ignoring, of inattention, is as vital a factor in mental progress as the function of attention itself. CHAPTER XXIII. THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT. THE reader will not have forgotten, in the jungle of purely inward processes and products through which the last chapters have borne him, that the final result of them all must be some form of bodily activity due to the escape of the central excitement through outgoing nerves. The whole neural organism, it will be remembered, is, physio logically considered, but a machine for converting stimuli into reactions ; and the intellectual part of our life is knit up with but the middle or * central ' portion of the machine's operations. Let us now turn to consider the final or emer gent operations, the bodily activities, and the forms of con sciousness connected therewithal. Every impression which impinges on the incoming nerves produces some discharge down the outgoing ones, whether we be aware of it or not. Using sweeping terms and ignoring exceptions, we might say that every possible feel ing produces a movement, and that the movement is a movement of the entire organism, and of each and all its parts. What happens patently when an explosion or a flash of lightning startles us, or when we are tickled, happens latently with every sensation which we receive. The only reason why we do not feel the startle or tickle in the case of insignificant sensations is partly its very small amount, partly our obtuse- ness. Professor Bain many years ago gave the name of the Law of Diffusion to this phenomenon of general discharge, and expressed it thus : " According as an impression is ac companied with Feeling, the aroused currents diffuse them selves over the brain, leading to a general agitation of the moving organs, as well as affecting the viscera." 372 THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT. 373 In cases where the feeling is strong the law is too famil iar to require proof. As Prof. Bain says : " Each of us knows in our own experience that a sudden shock of feeling is accompanied with movements of the body generally, and with other effects. When no emotion is present, we are quiescent ; a slight feeling is accompanied with slight manifestations ; a more intense shock has a more intense outburst. Every pleasure and every pain, and every mode of emotion, has a definite wave of effects, which our observation makes known to us ; and we apply the knowledge to infer other men's feelings from their outward display. . . . The organs first and promi nently affected, in the diffused wave of nervous influence, are the mov ing members, and of these, by preference, the features of the face (with the ears in animals), whose movements constitute the expression of the countenance. But the influence extends to all the parts of the moving system, voluntary and involuntary ; while an important series of effects are produced on the glands and viscera— the stomach, lungs, heart , kid neys, skin, together with the sexual and mammary organs. . . . The circumstance is seemingly universal, the proof of it does not require a citation of instances in detail ; on the objectors is thrown the burden of adducing unequivocal exceptions to the law. " * There are probably no exceptions to the diffusion of every impression through the nerve-centres. The effect of the wave through the centres may, however, often be to interfere with processes, and to diminish tensions already existing there ; and the outward consequences of such inhibitions may be the arrest of discharges from the inhibited regions and the checking of bodily activities already in process of occurrence. When this happens it probably is like the draining or siphoning of certain chan nels by currents flowing through others. When, in walk ing, we suddenly stand still because a sound, sight, smell, or thought catches our attention, something like this occurs. But there are cases of arrest of peripheral activity which depend, not on central inhibition, but on stimulation of centres which discharge outgoing currents of an inhibitory sort. Whenever we are startled, for example, our heart momentarily stops or slows its beating, and then palpitates with accelerated speed. The brief arrest is due to an out going current down the pneumogastric nerve. This nerve, when stimulated, stops or slows the heart-beats, and this * Emotions and Will, pp. 4, 5. 374 PSYCHOLOGY. particular effect of startling fails to occur if the nerve be cut. In general, however, the stimulating effects of a sense- impression preponderate over the inhibiting effects, so that we may roughly say, as we began by saying, that the wave of discharge produces an activity in all parts of the body. The task of tracing out all the effects of any one incoming sensation has not yet been performed by physiologists. Kecent years have, however, begun to enlarge our informa tion ; and although I must refer to special treatises for the full details, I can briefly string together here a number of separate observations which prove the truth of the law of diffusion. First take effects upon the circulation. Those upon the heart we have just seen. Haller long ago recorded that the blood from an open vein flowed out faster at the beat of a drum.* In Chapter III. (p. 98) we learned how instan taneously, according to Mosso, the circulation in the brain is altered by changes of sensation and of the course of thought. The effect of objects of fear, shame, and anger upon the blood-supply of the skin, especially the skin of the face, are too well known to need remark. Sensations of the higher senses produce, according to Couty and Char- pentier, the most varied effects upon the pulse-rate and blood-pressure in dogs. Fig. 81, a pulse-tracing from these authors, shows the tumultuous effect on a dog's heart of hearing the screams of another dog. The changes of blood-pressure still occurred when the pneumogastric nerves were cut. showing the vaso-motor effect to be direct and not dependent on the heart. When Mosso invented that simple instrument, the plethysmograph, for recording the fluctuations in volume of the members of the body, what most astonished him, he says, "in the first experiments which he made in Italy, was the extreme unrest of the blood-vessels of the hand, which at every smallest emotion, whether during waking or during sleep, changed their vol ume in surprising fashion." t Figure 82 (from Fere $ * Of. Fere . Sensation et Mouvement (1887), p. 56. f La Paura (1884), p. 117. Compare Fere : Sensation et Mouvement, chap. xvn. J Revue Philosophique, xxiv. 570. THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT. 375 X 376 PSYCHOLOGY. shows the way in which the pulse of one subject was modified by the exhibition of a red light lasting from the moment marked a to that marked b. FIG. 82. The effects upon respiration of sudden sensory stimuli are also too well known to need elaborate comment. We ' catch our breath ' at every sudden sound. We * hold our breath ' whenever our attention and expectation are strongly Fio. 83.- Respiratory curve of B: a, with eyes open; 6, with eyes closed. engaged, and we sigh when the tension of the situation is relieved. When a fearful object is before us we pant and cannot deeply inspire ; when the object makes us angry it is, on the contrary, the act of expiration which is hard. I subjoin a couple of figures from Fere which explain them- THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT. selves. They show the effects of light upon the breathing of two of his hysteric patients.* Fio. 84.-Respiratory curve of L: a, with yellow light; 6, with green light; c, with red light. The red has the strongest effect. On the sweat-glands, similar consequences of sensorial stimuli are observed. Tarchanoff, testing the condition of the sweat-glands by the power of the skin to start a gal- * Revue Phil., xxiv. pp. 566-7.— For further information about the rela tions between the brain and respiration, see Danilewsky's Essay in the Bio- logisches Centralblatt, u. 690. 378 PSYCHOLOGY. vanic current through electrodes applied to its surface,, found that " nearly every kind of nervous activity, from the simplest sensations and impressions, to voluntary motions and the highest forms of mental exertion, is accompanied by an increased activity in the glands of the skin."* On the pupil observations are recorded by Sanders which show that a transitory dilatation follows every sensorial stimulus applied during sleep, even if the stimulus be not strong enough to wake the subject up. At the moment of awak ing there is a dilatation, even if strong light falls on the eye.f The pupil of children can easily be observed to dilate enormously under the influence of fear. It is said to dilate in pain and fatigue ; and to contract, on the contrary, in rage. As regards effects on the abdominal viscera, they unques tionably exist, but very few accurate observations have been made4 The bladder, bowels, and uterus respond to sensations, even indifferent ones. Mosso and Pellicani, in their plethys- mographic investigations on the bladder of dogs, found all sorts of sensorial stimuli to produce reflex contractions of this organ, independent of those of the abdominal walls. They call the bladder ' as good an sesthesiometer as the iris,' and refer to the not uncommon reflex effects of psy chic stimuli in the human female upon this organ. § M. Fere has registered the contractions of the sphincter ani which even indifferent sensations will produce. In some pregnant women the foatus is felt to move after almost every sensorial excitement received by the mother. The only natural explanation is that it is stimulated at such moments by reflex contractions of the womb.[ That the glands are affected in emotion is patent enough in the case of the tears of grief, the dry mouth, moist skin, or diar- * Quoted from the report of Tarchanoff's paper (in Pflilger's Archiv, XL vi. 46) in the American Journal of Psych. , n. 652. f Archiv f. Psychiatrie, vn. 652 ; ix. 129. | Sensation et Mouvement, 57-8. § R. Accad. dei Lincei (1881-2). I follow the report in Hofmann F. Schwalbe's Jahresbericht, x. n. 93. || Cf. Fere, Sensation et Mouvement, chap. xiv. THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT. 379 rhoaa of fear, the biliary disturbances which sometimes follow upon rage, etc. The watering of the mouth at the sight of succulent food is well known. It is difficult to follow the smaller degrees of all these reflex changes, but it can hardly be doubted that they exist in some degree, even where they cease to be traceable, and that all our sensations have some visceral effects. The sneezing pro duced by sunshine, the roughening of the skin (gooseflesh) which certain strokings, contacts, and sounds, musical or non-musical, provoke, are facts of the same order as the shuddering and standing up of the hair in fear, only of less degree. Effects on Voluntary Muscles. Every sensorial stimulus not only sends a special discharge into certain particular muscles dependent on the special nature of the stimulus in question — some of these special discharges we have studied in Chapter XI, others we shall examine under the heads of Instinct and Emotion — but it innervates the muscles generally. M. Fere has given very curious experimental proofs of this. The strength of contraction of the subject's hand was measured by a self -registering dynamometer. Ordinarily the maximum strength, under simple experimen tal conditions, remains the same from day to day. But if simultaneously with the contraction the subject received a sensorial impression, the contraction was sometimes weak ened, but more often increased. This reinforcing effect has received the name of dynamogeny. The dynamogenic value of simple musical notes seems to be proportional to their loud- ness and height. Where the notes are compounded into sad strains, the muscular strength diminishes. If the strains are gay, it is increased.— The dynamogenic value of colored lights varies with the color. In a subject* whose normal strength was expressed by 23, it became 24 when a blue light was *The figures given are from an hysterical subject, and the differences are greater than normal. M. Fere considers that the unstable nervous system of the'hysteric (' ces grenouilles de la psychologic ') shows the law on a quantitatively exaggerated scale, without altering the qualitative rela tions. The effects remind us a little of the influence of sensations upon minimal sensations of other orders discovered by Urbantschitsch, and re ported on page 29 of this volume. PSYCHOLOGY. thrown on the eyes, 28 for green, 30 for yellow, 35 for orange, and 42 for red. Ked is thus the most exciting color. Among tastes, sweet has the lowest value, next comes salt, then bitter, and finally sour, though, as M. Fere remarks, such a sour as acetic acid excites the nerves of pain and smell as well as of taste. The stimulating effects of tobacco- smoke, alcohol, beef-extract (which is innutritions), etc., etc., may be partly due to a dynamogenic action of this sort.— Of odors, that of musk seems to have a peculiar dynamo genic power. Fig. 85 is a copy of one of M. Fere's dyna- mographic tracings, which explains itself. The smaller contractions are those without stimulus ; the stronger ones are due to the influence of red rays of light. FIG. 85. Everyone is familiar with the patellar reflex, or jerk up wards of the foot, which is produced by smartly tapping the tendon below the knee-pan when the leg hangs over the other knee. Drs. "Weir Mitchell and Lombard have found that when other sensations come in simultaneously with the tap, the jerk is increased.* Heat, cold, pricking, itching, or faradic stimulation of the skin, sometimes strong optical impressions, music, all have this dynamogenic effect, which also results whenever voluntary movements are set up in other parts of the body, simultaneously with the tap.t These ' dynamogenic ' effects, in which one stimulation * Mitchell in (Philadelphia) Medical News (Feb. 13 and 20, 1886); Lom bard in American Journal of Psychology (Oct. 1887). f Prof. H. P. Bowditch has made the interesting discovery that if the reinforcing movement be as much as 0.4 of a second late, the reinforce ment fails to occur, and is transformed into a positive inhibition of the knee-jerk for retardations of between 0.4' and 1.7'. The knee-jerk fails to be modified at all by voluntary movements made later than 1.7' after the patellar ligament is tapped (see Boston Med. and Surg. Journ., May ff\ 1888). THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT. 381 simply reinforces another already under way, must not be confounded with reflex acts properly so called, in which new activities are originated by the stimulus. All instinctive performances and manifestations of emotion are reflex acts. But underneath those of which we are conscious there seem to go on continually others smaller in amount, which probably in most persons might be called fluctuations of muscular tone, but which in certain neurotic subjects can be demonstrated ocularly. M. Fere figures some of them in the article to which I have already referred.* Looking back over all these facts, it is hard to doubt the truth of the law of diffusion, even where verification is be yond reach. A process set up anywhere in the centres reverber ates every 'ivhere, and in some way or other affects the organism throughout, making its activities either greater or less. We are brought again to the assimilation which was expressed on a previous page of the nerve-central mass to a good con ductor charged with electricity, of which the tension can not be changed anywhere without changing it everywhere. Herr Schneider has tried to show, by an ingenious and suggestive zoological review,t that all the special movements which highly evolved animals make are differentiated from the two originally simple movements, of contraction and ex pansion, in which the entire body of simple organisms takes part. The tendency to contract is the source of all the self-protective impulses and reactions which are later de veloped, including that of flight. The tendency to expand splits up, on the contrary, into the impulses and instincts of an aggressive kind, feeding, fighting, sexual intercourse, etc. Schneider's articles are well worth reading, if only for the careful observations on animals which they embody. I cite them here as a sort of evolutionary reason to add to the mechanical a priori reason why there ought to be the diffusive wave which our a posteriori instances have shown to exist. I will now proceed to a detailed study of the more im- * Revue Phil., xxiv. 572 ff. f In the Viertel jahrschrift filr wiss. Philos. , m. 294. 332 PSYCHOLOGY. portant classes of movement consequent upon cerebro- mental change. They may be enumerated as — 1) Instinctive or Impulsive Performances ; 2) Expressions of Emotion ; and 3) Voluntary Deeds; and each shall have a chapter to itsell CHAPTER XXIV * INSTINCT. INSTINCT is usually defined as the faculty of acting in such a way as to produce certain ends, without foresight of the ends, and without previous education in the performance. That instincts, as thus defined, exist on an enormous scale in the animal kingdom needs no proof. They are the functional correlatives of structure. With the presence of a certain organ goes, one may say, almost always a native aptitude for its use. ' ' Has the bird a gland for the secretion of oil ? She knows instinc tively how to press the oil from the gland, and apply it to the feather. Has the rattlesnake the grooved tooth and gland of poison ? He knows without instruction how to make both structure and function most ef fective against his enemies. Has the silk- worm the function of secret ing the fluid silk ? At the proper time she winds the cocoon such as she has never seen, as thousands before have done ; and thus without in struction, pattern, or experience, forms a safe abode for herself in the period of transformation. Has the hawk talons ? She knows by in stinct how to wield them effectively against the helpless quarry, "f A very common way of talking about these admirably definite tendencies to act is by naming abstractly the pur pose they subserve, such as self-preservation, or defence, or care for eggs and young — and saying the animal has an in stinctive fear of death or love of life, or that she has an in stinct of self-preservation, or an instinct of maternity and the like. But this represents the animal as obeying ab stractions which not once in a million cases is it possible it <;an have framed. The strict physiological way of interpret- * This chapter has already appeared (almost exactly as now printed) in the form of magazine articles in Scribner's Magazine and in the Popular Science Monthly for 1887. t P. A. Chadbourne : Instinct, p. 28 (New York, 1872). 384 PSYCHOLOGY. ing the facts leads to far clearer results. The actions we call instinctive all conform to the general reflex type ; they are called forth by determinate sensory stimuli in contact with the animal's body, or at a distance in his environment. The cat runs after the mouse, runs or shows fight before the dog, avoids falling from walls and trees, shuns fire and water, etc., not because he has any notion either of life or of death, or of self, or of preservation. He has probably at tained to no one of these conceptions in such a way as to re act definitely upon it. He acts in each case separately, and simply because he cannot help it; being so framed that when that particular running thing called a mouse appears in his field of vision he must pursue ; that when that par ticular barking and obstreperous thing called a dog appears there he must retire, if at a distance, and scratch if close by ; that he must withdraw his feet from water and his face from flame, etc. His nervous system is to a great extent a preorganized bundle of such reactions — they are as fatal as sneezing, and as exactly correlated to their special excitants as it is to its own. Although the naturalist may, for his own convenience, class these reactions under general heads, he must not forget that in the animal it is a particular sensation or perception or image which calls them forth. At first this view astounds us by the enormous number of special adjustments it supposes animals to possess ready- made in anticipation of the outer things among which they are to dwell. Can mutual dependence be so intricate and go so far ? Is each thing born fitted to particular other things, and to them exclusively, as locks are fitted to their keys? Undoubtedly this must be believed to be so. Each nook and cranny of creation, down to our very skin and entrails, has its living inhabitants, with organs suited to the place, to devour and digest the food it harbors and to meet the dangers it conceals ; and the minuteness of adap tation thus shown in the way of structure knows no bounds. Even so are there no bounds to the minuteness of adapta tion in the way of conduct which the several inhabitants display. The older writings on instinct are ineffectual wastes of words, because their authors never came down to this defi- INSTINCT. 385 nite and simple point of view, but smothered everything in vague wonder at the clairvoyant and prophetic power of the animals — so superior to anything in man — and at the beneficence of God in endowing them with such a gift. But God's beneficence endows them, first of all, with a nervous system ; and, turning our attention to this, makes instinct immediately appear neither more nor less wonderful than all the other facts of life. Every instinct is an impulse. "Whether we shall call such impulses as blushing, sneezing, coughing, smiling, or dodg ing, or keeping time to music, instincts or not, is a mere matter of terminology. The process is the same through out. In his delightfully fresh and interesting work, Der Thierische Wille, Herr G. H. Schneider subdivides im pulses (Triebe) into sensation-impulses, perception-im pulses, and idea-impulses. To crouch from cold is a sen sation-impulse ; to turn and follow, if we see people run ning one way, is a perception-impulse ; to cast about for cover, if it begins to blow and rain, is an imagination-im pulse. A single complex instinctive action may involve successively the awakening of impulses of all three classes. Thus a hungry lion starts to seek prey by the awakening in him of imagination coupled with desire ; he begins to stalk it when, on eye, ear, or nostril, he gets an impression of its presence at a certain distance ; he springs upon it, either when the booty takes alarm and flees, or when the distance is sufficiently reduced ; he proceeds to tear and devour it the moment he gets a sensation of its contact with his claws and fangs. Seeking, stalking, springing, and devour ing are just so many different kinds of muscular contrac tion, and neither kind is called forth by the stimulus ap propriate to the other. Schneider says of the hamster, which stores corn in its hole: " If we analyze the propensity of storing, we find that it consists of three impulses : First, an impulse to pick up the nutritious object, due to perception ; second, an impulse to carry it off into the dwelling-place, due to the idea of this latter ; and third, an impulse to lay it down there, due to the sight of the place. It lies in the nature of the ham ster that it should never see a full ear of corn without feeling a desire 386 PSYCHOLOGY. to strip it ; it lies in its nature to feel, as soon as its cheek-pouches are filled, an irresistible desire to hurry to its home ; and finally, it lies in its nature that the sight of the storehouse should awaken the impulse to empty the cheeks" (p. 208). In certain animals of a low order the feeling of having executed one impulsive step is such an indispensable part of the stimulus of the next one, that the animal cannot make any variation in the order of its performance. Now, why do the various animals do what seem to us such strange things, in the presence of such outlandish stimuli ? Why does the hen, for example, submit herself to the tedium of incubating such a fearfully uninteresting set of objects as a nestful of eggs, unless she have some sort of a prophetic inkling of the result? The only answer is ad hominem. We can only interpret the instincts of brutes by what we know of instincts in ourselves. Why do men al ways lie down, when they can, on soft beds rather than on hard floors? Why do they sit round the stove on a cold day? Why, in a room, do they place themselves, ninety- nine times out of a hundred, with their faces towards its middle rather than to the wall ? Why do they prefer saddle of mutton and champagne to hard-tack and ditch-water ? Why does the maiden interest the youth so that everything about her seems more important and significant than any thing else in the world ? Nothing more can be said than that these are human ways, and that every creature likes its own ways, and takes to the following them as a matter of course. Science may come and consider these ways, and find that most of them are useful. But it is not for the sake of their utility that they are followed, but because at the moment of following them we feel that that is the only appropriate and natural thing to do. Not one man in a billion, when taking his dinner, ever thinks of utility. He eats because the food tastes good and makes him want more. If you ask him why he should want to eat more of what tastes like that, instead of revering you as a philoso pher he will probably laugh at you for a fool. The con nection between the savory sensation and the act it awakens is for him absolute and selbstverstdndlichy an ' a priori syn- INSTINCT. 3b7 thesis ' of the most perfect sort, needing no proof but its own evidence. It takes, in short, what Berkeley calls a mind debauched by learning to carry the process of making the natural seem strange, so far as to ask for the why of any instinctive human act. To the metaphysician alone can such questions occur as : Why do we smile, when pleased, and not scowl? Why are we unable to talk to a crowd as we talk to a single friend? Why does a particular maiden turn our wits so upside-down ? The common man can only say, " Of course we smile, of course our heart pal pitates at the sight of the crowd, of course we love the maiden, that beautiful soul clad in that perfect form, so palpably and flagrantly made from all eternity to be loved !" And so, probably, does each animal feel about the par ticular things it tends to do in presence of particular ob jects. They, too, are a priori syntheses. To the lion it is the lioness which is made to be loved ; to the bear, the she- bear. To the broody hen the notion would probably seem monstrous that there should be a creature in the world to whom a nestful of eggs was not the utterly fascinating and precious and never-to-be-too-much-sat-upon object which it is to her.* Thus we may be sure that, however mysterious some animals' instincts may appear to us, our instincts will appear no less mysterious to them. And we may conclude that, to the animal which obeys it, every impulse and every step of every instinct shines with its own sufficient light, and seema at the moment the only eternally right and proper thing to do. ^ It is done for its own sake exclusively. What volup- *"It would be very simple-minded to suppose that bees follow their queen, and protect her and care for her, because they are aware that with out her the hive would become extinct. The odor or the aspect of their queen is manifestly agreeable to the bees— that is why they love her so. Does not all true love base itself on agreeable perceptions much more than on representations of utility ?" (G. H. Schneider, Der Thierische Wille, p. 187.) A priori, there is no reason to suppose that any sensation might not in some animal cause any emotion and any impulse. To us it seems un natural that an odor should directly excite anger or fear; or a color, lust. Yet there are creatures to which some smells are quite as frightful as any sounds, and very likely others to which color is as much a sexual irritant as form. 388 PSYCHOLOGY. tuous thrill may not shake a fly, when she at last discovers the one particular leaf, or carrion, or bit of dung, that out of all the world can stimulate her ovipositor to its dis charge ? Does not the discharge then seem to her the only fitting thing ? And need she care or know anything about the future maggot and its food ? Since the egg-laying instincts are simple examples to con sider, a few quotations about them from Schneider may be serviceable : "The phenomenon so often talked about, so variously interpreted, so surrounded with mystification, that an insect should always lay her eggs in a spot appropriate to the nourishment of her young, is no more marvellous than the phenomenon that every animal pairs with a mate capable of bearing posterity, or feeds on materials capable of affording him nourishment. . . . Not only the choice of a place for laying the eggs, but all the various acts for depositing and protecting them, are occasioned by the perception of the proper object, and the relation of this perception to the various stages of maternal impulse. When the burying beetle perceives a carrion, she is not only impelled to approach it and lodge her eggs in it, but also to go through the movements re quisite for burying it; just as a bird who sees his hen-bird is impelled to caress her, to strut around her, dance before her, or in some other way to woo her; just as a tiger, when he sees an antelope, is impelled to stalk it, to pounce upon it, and to strangle it. When the tailor-bee cuts out pieces of rose-leaf, bends them, carries them into a caterpillar- or mouse-hole in trees or in the earth, covers their seams again with other pieces, and so makes a thimble-shaped case — when she fills this with honey and lays an egg in it, all these various appropriate expres sions of her will are to be explained by supposing that at the time when the eggs are ripe within her, the appearance of a suitable caterpillar- or mouse-hole and the perception of rose-leaves are so correlated in the insect with the several impulses in question, that the performances fol low as a matter of course when the perceptions take place. . . . " The perception of the empty nest, or of a single egg, seems in birds to stand in such a close relation to the physiological functions of ovipa- ration, that it serves as a direct stimulus to these functions, while the perception of a sufficient number of eggs has just the opposite effect. It is well known that hens and ducks lay more eggs if we keep remov ing them than if we leave them in the nest. The impulse to sit arises, as a rule, when a bird sees a certain number of eggs in her nest. If this number is not yet to be seen there, the ducks continue to lay, although they perhaps have laid twice as many eggs as they are accus tomed to sit upon. . . . That sitting, also, is independent of any idea of purpose and is a pure perception-impulse is evident, among other things, INSTINCT. 389 from the fact that many birds, e.g. wild ducks, steal eggs from each other. . . . The bodily disposition to sit is, it is true, one condi tion [since broody hens will sit where there are no. eggs], but the perception of the eggs i? the other condition of the activity of the incubating impulse. The propensity of the cuckoo and of the cow-bird to lay their eggs in the nests of other species must also be interpreted as a pure perception-impulse. These birds have no bodily disposition to become broody, and there is therefore in them no connec' tion between the perception of an egg and the impulse to sit upon it. Eggs ripen, however, in their oviducts, and the body tends to get rid of them. And since the two birds just named do not drop their eggs any where on the ground, but in nests, which are the only places where they may preserve the species, it might easily appear that such preservation of the species was what they had in view, and that they acted with full consciousness of the purpose. But this is not so. ... The cuckoo is simply excited by the perception of quite determinate sorts of nest, which already contain eggs, to drop her own into them, and throw the others out, because this perception is a direct stimulus to these acts. It is impossible that she should have any notion of the other bird com- ing and sitting on her egg." * INSTINCTS NOT ALWAYS BLIND OB INVAKIABLB. Remember that nothing is said yet of the origin of in stincts, but only of the constitution of those that exist fully formed. How stands it with the instincts of mankind ? Nothing is commoner than the remark that Man differs from lower creatures by the almost total absence of instincts, and the assumption of their work in him by ' reason.' A fruitless discussion might be waged on this point by two theorizers who were careful not to define their terms. ' Reason ' might be used, as it often has been, since Kant, not as the mere power of ' inferring,' but also as a name for the tendency to obey impulses of a certain lofty sort, such as duty, or universal ends. And ' instinct ' might have its sig nificance so broadened as to cover all impulses whatever, even the impulse to act from the idea of a distant fact, as well as the impulse to act from a present sensation. "Were the word instinct used in this broad way, it would of course be impossible to restrict it, as we began by doing, to actions done with no prevision of an end. We must of course avoid a quarrel about words, and the facts of the case are * Der Thierische Wille, pp. 282-3. 390 PSYCHOLOGY. really tolerably plain. Man has a far greater variety of impulses than any lower animal ; and any one of these im pulses, taken in itself, is as ' blind ' as the lowest instinct can be ; but, owing to man's memory, power of reflection, and power of inference, they come each one to be felt by him, after he has once yielded to them and experienced their results, in connection with a foresight of those results. In this condition an impulse acted out may be said to be acted out, in part at least, for the sake of its results. It is obvious that every instinctive act, in an animal tvith memory, must cease to be ' blind ' after being once repeated, and must be accompanied with foresight of its ' end ' just so far as that end may have fallen under the animal's cognizance. An insect that lays her eggs in a place where she never sees them hatched must always do so ' blindly ; ' but a hen who has already hatched a brood can hardly be assumed to sit with perfect ' blindness ' on her second nest. Some expectation of consequences must in every case like this be aroused ; and this expectation, according as it is that of something desired or of something disliked, must necessarily either re-enforce or inhibit the mere impulse. The hen's idea of the chickens would probably encourage her to sit ; a rat's memory, on the other hand, of a former escape from a trap would neutralize his impulse to take bait from anything that reminded him of that trap. If a boy sees a fat hop- ping-toad, he probably has incontinently an impulse (espe cially if with other boys) to smash the creature with a stone, which impulse we may suppose him blindly to obey. But something in the expression of the dying toad's clasped hands suggests the meanness of the act, or reminds him of sayings he has heard about the sufferings of animals being like his own ; so that, when next he is tempted by a toad, an idea arises which, far from spurring him again to the torment, prompts kindly actions, and may even make him the toad's champion against less reflecting boys. It is plain, then, that, no matter how well endowed, an animal may originally be in the way of instincts, his resultant actions ivill be much modified if the instincts combine with experience, if in addition to impulses he have memories, associations, inferences, and expectations, on any considerable scale. An INSTINCT. 391 object O, on which he has an instinctive impulse to react in the manner A, would directly provoke him to that reaction. But O has meantime become for him a sign of the nearness of P, on which he has an equally strong impulse to react in the manner B, quite unlike A. So that when he meets O the immediate impulse A and the remote impulse B strug gle in his breast for the mastery. The fatality and unifor mity said to be characteristic of instinctive actions will be so little manifest that one might be tempted to deny to him altogether the possession of any instinct about the object O. Yet how false this judgment would be ! The instinct about O is there ; only by the complication of the associa tive machinery it has come into conflict with another in stinct about P. Here we immediately reap the good fruits of our simple physiological conception of what an instinct is. If it be a mere excito-motor impulse, due to the pre-existence of a certain ' reflex arc ' in the nerve-centres of the creature, of course it must follow the law of all such reflex arcs. One liability of such arcs is to have their activity 'inhibited,' by other processes going on at the same time. It makes no difference whether the arc be organized at birth, or ripen spontaneously later, or be due to acquired habit, it must take its chances with all the other arcs, and sometimes succeed, and sometimes fail, in drafting off the currents through itself. The mystical view of an instinct would make it invariable. The physiological view would require it to show occasional irregularities in any animal in whom the number of separate instincts, and the possible entrance of the same stimulus into several of them, were great. And such irregularities are what every superior animal's in stincts do show in abundance.* * In the instincts of mammals, and even of lower creatures, the uniform ity and infallibility which, a generation ago, were considered as essential characters do not exist. The minuter study of recent years has found con tinuity, transition, variation, and mistake, wherever it has looked for them, and decided that what is called an instinct is usually only a tendency to act in a way of which the average is pretty constant, but which need not be mathematically 'true.' Cf. on this point Darwin's Origin of Species: Romanes's Mental Evol., chaps, xi to xvi incl., and Appendix; W. L. Lindsay's Mind in Lower Animals, vol. i. 133-141 ; n. chaps, v, xx ; 392 PSYCHOLOGY. Wherever the mind is elevated enough to discriminate ; wherever several distinct sensory elements must combine to discharge the reflex-arc ; wherever, instead of plumping into action instantly at the first rough intimation of what sort of a thing is there, the agent waits to see which one of its kind it is and what the circumstances are of its appearance; wherever different individuals and different circumstances can impel him in different ways ; wherever these are the conditions — we have a masking of the elementary constitu tion of the instinctive life. The whole story of our dealings with the lower wild animals is the history of our taking advantage of the way in which they judge of everything by its mere label, as it were, so as to ensnare or kill them. Nature, in them, has left matters in this rough way, and made them act always in the manner which would be oftenest right. There are more worms unattached to hooks than impaled upon them ; therefore, on the whole, says Nature to her fishy children, bite at every worm and take your chances. But as her children get higher, and their lives more precious, she reduces the risks. Since what seems to be the same object may be now a genuine food and now a bait ; since in gregarious species each individual may prove to be either the friend or the rival, according to the circumstances, of another ; since any entirely unknown object may be fraught with weal or woe, Nature implants contrary impulses to act on many classes of things, and leaves it to slight alterations in the conditions of the individual case to decide which impulse shall carry the day. Thus, greediness and suspicion, curiosity and timidity, coyness and desire, bashfulness and vanity, sociability and pug nacity, seem to shoot over into each other as quickly, and to remain in as unstable equilibrium, in the higher birds and mammals as in man. They are all impulses, congenital, blind at first, and productive of motor reactions of a rigor ously determinate sort. Each one of them, then, is an instinct, as instincts are commonly defined. But they con tradict each other — ' experience ' in each particular oppor- and K. Semper's Conditions of Existence in Animals, where a great many instances will be found. INSTINCT. 393 tunity of application usually deciding the issue. The animal that exhibits them loses the l instinctive ' demeanor and appears to lead a life of hesitation and choice, an intellectual life ; not, however, because he has no instincts — rather because he has so many that they block each other's path. Thus, then, without troubling ourselves about the words instinct and reason, we may confidently say that however uncertain man's reactions upon his environment may some times seem in comparison with those of lower creatures, the uncertainty is probably not due to their possession of any principles of action which he lacks. On the contrary, man possesses all the impulses that they have, and a great many more besides. In other words, there is no material antagonism between instinct and reason. Eeason, per se, can inhibit no impulses ; the only thing that can neutralize an impulse is an impulse the other way. Eeason may, however, make an inference ivhich ivill excite the imagination so as to set loose the impulse the other way ; and thus, though the animal richest in reason might be also the animal richest in in stinctive impulses too, he would never seem the fatal au tomaton which a merely instinctive animal would be. Let us now turn to human impulses with a little more detail. All we have ascertained so far is that impulses of an originally instinctive character may exist, and yet not betray themselves by automatic fatality of conduct. But in man what impulses do exist? In the light of what has been said, it is obvious that an existing impulse may not always be superficially apparent even when its object is there. And we shall see that some impulses may be masked by causes of which we have not yet spoken. TWO PRINCIPLES OF NON-UNIFORMITY IN INSTINCTS. Were one devising an abstract scheme, nothing would be easier than to discover from an animal's actions just how many instincts he possessed. He would react in one way only upon each class of objects with which his life had to deal ; he would react in identically the same way upon every specimen of a class ; and he would react invariably during his whole life. There would be no gaps among his 394 PSYCHOLOGY. instincts ; all would come to light without perversion or disguise. But there are no such abstract animals, and no where does the instinctive life display itself in such a way. Not only, as we have seen, may objects of the same class arouse reactions of opposite sorts in consequence of slight changes in the circumstances, in the individual object, or in the agent's inward condition ; but two other principles of which we have not yet spoken, may come into play and produce results so striking that observers as eminent as Messrs. D. A. Spalding and Komanes do not hesitate to call them ' derangements of the mental constitution,' and to conclude that the instinctive machinery has got out of gear. These principles are those 1. Of the inhibition of instincts by habits; and 2. Of the transitoriness of instincts. Taken in conjunction with the two former principles — that the same object may excite ambiguous impulses, or sug gest an impulse different from that which it excites, by sug gesting a remote object — they explain any amount of de parture from uniformity of conduct, without implying any getting out of gear of the elementary impulses from which the conduct flows. 1. The law of inhibition of instincts by habits is this : When objects of a certain class elicit from an animal a certain sort of reaction, it often happens that the animal becomes partial to the first specimen of the class on which it has reacted, and ivill not afterward react on any other specimen. The selection of a particular hole to live in, of a partic ular mate, of a particular feeding-ground, a particular variety of diet, a particular anything, in short, out of a possible multi tude, is a very wide-spread tendency among animals, even those low down in the scale. The limpet will return to the same sticking-place in its rock, and the lobster to its favorite nook on the sea-bottom. The rabbit will deposit its dung in the same corner ; the bird makes its nest on the same bough. But each of these preferences carries with it an insensibility to other opportunities and occasions — an insensibility which can only be described physiologically as an inhibition of INSTINCT. 395 new impulses by the habit of old ones already formed. The possession of homes and wives of our own makes us strangely insensible to the charms of those of other people. Few of us are adventurous in the matter of food ; in fact, most of us think there is something disgusting in a bill of fare to which we are unused. Strangers, we are apt to think, cannot be woith knowing, especially if they come from distant cities, etc. The original impulse which got us homes, wives, dietaries, and friends at all, seems to exhaust itself in its first achievements and to leave no surplus energy for reacting on new cases. And so it comes about that, witnessing this torpor, an observer of mankind might say that no instinctive propensity toward certain objects ex isted at all. It existed, but it existed miscellaneously, or as an instinct pure and simple, only before habit was formed. A habit, once grafted on an instinctive tendency, restricts the range of the tendency itself, and keeps us from reacting on any but the habitual object, although other objects might just as well have been chosen had they been the first- comers. Another sort of arrest of instinct by habit is where the same class of objects awakens contrary instinctive impulses. Here the impulse first followed toward a given individual of the class is apt to keep him from ever awakening the opposite impulse in us. In fact, the whole class may be protected by this individual specimen from the application to it of the other impulse. Animals, for example, awaken in a child the opposite impulses of fearing and fondling. But if a child, in his first attempts to pat a dog, gets snapped at or bitten, so that the impulse of fear is strongly aroused, it may be that for years to come no dog will excite in him the impulse to fondle again. On the other hand, the greatest natural enemies, if carefully introduced to each other when young and guided at the outset by superior authority, set tle down into those ' happy families ' of friends which we see in our menageries. Young animals, immediately after birth, have no instinct of fear, but show their dependence by allowing themselves to be freely handled. Later, how ever, they grow 'wild,' and, if left to themselves, will not let man approach them. I am told by farmers in the 396 PSYCHOLOGY. Adirondack wilderness that it is a very serious matter if a cow wanders off and calves in the woods and is not found for a week or more. The calf, by that time, is as wild and almost as fleet as a deer, and hard to capture without vio lence. But calves rarely show any particular wildness to the men who have been in contact with them during the first days of their life, when the instinct to attach them selves is uppermost, nor do they dread strangers as they would if brought up wild. Chickens give a curious illustration of the same law. Mr. Spalding's wonderful article on instinct shall supply us with the facts. These little creatures show opposite in stincts of attachment and fear, either of which may be aroused by the same object, man. If a chick is born in the absence of the hen, it lkwill follow any moving object. And, when guided by sight alone, they seem to have no more disposition to follow a hen than to follow a duck or a human being. Unreflecting lookers-on, when they saw chick ens a day old running after me," says Mr. Spalding, "and older ones following me for miles, and answering to my whistle, imagined that I must have some occult power over the creatures : whereas I had simply allowed them to follow me from the first. There is the instinct to follow; and the ear, prior to experience, attaches them to the right object." * But if a man presents himself for the first time when the instinct of fear is strong, the phenomena are altogether reversed. Mr. Spalding kept three chickens hooded until they were nearly four days old, and thus describes their behavior : tk Each of them, on being unhooded, evinced the greatest terror to me, dashing off in the opposite direction whenever I sought to approach it. The table on which they were unhooded stood before a window, and each in its turn beat against the window like a wild bird. One of them darted behind some books, andr squeezing itself into a corner, remained cowering for a length of time. We might guess at the meaning of this strange and exceptional wildness ; but the odd fact is enough for my present purpose. Whatever might have been the meaning of this marked change in their mental constitution — had they been unhooded on the previous day they would have run to me instead of from me — it could not have been the effect of experience ; it must have resulted wholly from changes in their own organizations." f * Spalding, Macmillan's Magazine, Feb. 1873, p. 287. f Ibid. p. 289. INSTINCT. 397 Their case was precisely analogous to that of the Adi rondack calves. The two opposite instincts relative to the same object ripen in succession. If the first one engenders a habit, that habit will inhibit the application of the second instinct to that object. All animals are tame during the earliest phase of their infancy. Habits formed then limit the effects of whatever instincts of wildness may later be evolved. Mr. Romanes gives some very curious examples of the way in which instinctive tendencies may be altered by the habits to which their first * objects ' have given rise. The cases are a little more complicated than those mentioned in the text, inasmuch as the object reacted on not only starts a habit which inhibits other kinds of impulse toward it (al though such other kinds might be natural), but even modi fies by its own peculiar conduct the constitution of the impulse which it actually awakens. Two of the instances in question are those of hens who hatched out broods of chicks after having (in three previ ous years) hatched ducks. They strove to coax or to com pel their new progeny to enter the water, and seemed much perplexed at their unwillingness. Another hen adopted a brood of young ferrets which, having lost their mother, were put under her. During all the time they were left with her she had to sit on the nest, for they could not wan der like young chicks. She obeyed their hoarse growling as she would have obeyed her chickens' peep. She combed out their hair with her bill, and " used frequently to stop and look with one eye at the wriggling nestful, with an in quiring gaze, expressive of astonishment." At other times she would fly up with a loud scream, doubtless because the orphans had nipped her in their search for teats. Finally, a Brahma hen nursed a young peacock during the enor mous period of eighteen months, and never laid any eggs during all this time. The abnormal degree of pride which she showed in her wonderful chicken is described by Dr. Romanes as ludicrous.* * For the cases in full see Mental Evolution in Animals, pp. 213-217. 398 PSYCHOLOGY. 2. Tliis leads us to the law of transit oriness, which is this : Many instincts ripen at a certain o,ge and then fade away. A consequence of this law is that if, during the time of such an instinct's vivacity, objects adequate to arouse it are met with, a habit of acting on them is formed, which re mains when the original instinct has passed away ; but that if no such objects are met with, then no habit will be formed; and, later on in life, when the animal meets the objects, he will altogether fail to react, as at the earlier epoch he would instinctively have done. No doubt such a law is restricted. Some instincts are far less transient than others — those connected with feed ing and ' self-preservation ' may hardly be transient at all, and some, after fading out for a time, recur as strong as ever, e.g., the instincts of pairing and rearing young. The law, however, though not absolute, is certainly very wide spread, and a few examples will illustrate just what it means. In the chickens and calves above mentioned, it is ob vious that the instinct to follow and become attached fades out after a few days, and that the instinct of flight then takes its place, the conduct of the creature toward man be ing decided by the formation or non-formation of a certain habit during those days. The transiency of the chicken's instinct to follow is also proved by its conduct toward the hen. Mr. Spalding kept some chickens shut up till they were comparatively old, and, speaking of these, he says : " A chicken that has not heard the call of the mother till until eight or ten days old then hears it as if it heard it not. I regret to find that on this point my notes are not so full as I could wish, or as they might have been. There is, however, an account of one chicken that could not be returned to the mother when ten days old. The hen followed it, and tried to entice it in every way ; still, it continually left her and ran to the house or to any person of whom it caught sight. This it per sisted in doing, though beaten back with a small branch dozens of times, and, indeed, cruelly maltreated. It was also placed under the mother at night, but it again left her in the morning." The instinct of sucking is ripe in all mammals at birth, and leads to that habit of taking the breast which, in the human infant, may be prolonged by daily exercise long be- INSTINCT. 399 yond its usual term of a year or a year and a half. But the instinct itself is transient, in the sense that if, for any rea son, the child be fed by spoon during the first few days of its life and not put to the breast, it may be no easy matter after that to make it suck at all. So of calves. If their mother die, or be dry, or refuse to let them suck for a day or two, so that they are fed by hand, it becomes hard to get them to suck at all when a new nurse is provided. The ease with which sucking creatures are weaned, by simply breaking the habit and giving them food in a new way, shows that the instinct, purely as such, must be entirely extinct. Assuredly the simple fact that instincts are transient, and that the effect of later ones may be altered by the habits which earlier ones have left behind, is a far more philosophical explanation than the notion of an instinctive constitution vaguely 'deranged' or 'thrown out of gear.' I have observed a Scotch terrier, born on the floor of a stable in December, and transferred six weeks later to a carpeted house, make, when he was less than four months old, a very elaborate pretence of burying things, such as gloves, etc., with which he had played till he was tired. He scratched the carpet with his forefeet, dropped the ob ject from his mouth upon the spot, and then scratched all about it (with both fore- and hind-feet, if I remember rightly), and finally went away and let it lie. Of course, the act was entirely useless. I saw him perform it at that age, some four or five times, and never again in his life. The conditions were not present to fix a habit which should last when the prompting instinct died away. But suppose meat instead of a glove, earth instead of a carpet, hunger- pangs instead of a fresh supper a few hours later, and it is easy to see how this dog might have got into a habit of burying superfluous food, which might have lasted all his life. Who can swear that the strictly instructive part of the food-burying propensity in the wild Canidce may not be as short-lived as it was in this terrier ? A similar instance is given by Dr. H. D. Schmidt * of New Orleans: * Transactions of American Neurological Association, vol. i. p. 129 (1875). 400 PSYCHOLOGY. " I may cite the example of a young squirrel which I had tamed, a number of years ago, when serving in the army, and when I had suffi cient leisure and opportunity to study the habits of animals. In the autumn, before the winter sets in, adult squirrels bury as many nuts, as they can collect, separately, in the ground. Holding the nut firmly between their teeth, they first scratch a hole in the grond, and, after pointing their ears in all directions to convince themselves that no enemy is near, they ram—the head, with the nut still between the front teeth, serving as a sledge-hammer— the nut into the ground, and then fill up the hole by means of their paws. The whole process is executed with great rapidity, and, as it appeared to me, always with exactly the same movements ; in fact, it is done so well that I could never discover the traces of the burial-ground. Now, as regards the young squirrel, which, of course, never had been present at the burial of a nut, I observed that, after having eaten a number of hickory-nuts to appease its appetite, it would take one between its teeth, then sit upright and listen in all directions. Finding all right, it would scratch upon the smooth blanket on which I was playing with it as if to make a hole, then hammer with the nut between its teeth upon the blanket, and finally perform all the motions required to fill up a hole— in the air; after which it would jump away, leaving the nut, of course, uncovered." The anecdote, of course, illustrates beautifully the close relation of instinct to reflex action— a particular perception calls forth particular movements, and that is all. Dr. Schmidt writes me that the squirrel in question soon passed away from his observation. It may fairly be presumed that, if he had been long retained prisoner in a cage, he would soon have forgotten his gesticulations over the hick ory-nuts. One might, indeed, go still further with safety, and ex pect that, if such a captive squirrel were then set free, he would never afterwards acquire this peculiar instinct of his tribe.* Leaving lower animals aside, and turning to human in stincts, we see the law of transiency corroborated on the * "Mr. Spalding," says Mr. Lewes (Problems of Life and Mind, prob. I. chap. n. § 22, note), "tells me of a friend of his who reared a gosling in the kitchen, away from all water ; when this bird was some months old, and was taken to a pond, it not only refused to go into the water, but when thrown in scrambled out again, as a hen would have done. Here was an instinct entirely suppressed." See a similar observation on duck lings in T.R. R. Stebbing : Essays on Darwinism (London, 1871), p. 73. INSTINCT. 401 widest scale by the alternation of different interests and passions as human life goes on. With the child, life is all play and fairy-tales and learning the external properties of ' things ;' with the youth, it is bodily exercises of a more systematic sort, novels of the real world, boon-fellowship and song, friendship and love, nature, travel and adven ture, science and philosophy ; with the man, ambition and policy, acquisitiveness, responsibility to others, and the selfish zest of the battle of life. If a boy grows up alone at the age of games and sports, and learns neither to play ball, nor row, nor sail, nor ride, nor skate, nor fish, nor shoot, probably he will be sedentary to the end of his days ; and, though the best of opportunities be afforded him for learning these things later, it is a hundred to one but he will pass them by and shrink back from the effort of taking those necessary first steps the prospect of which, at an earlier age, would have filled him with eager delight. The sexual passion expires after a protracted reign ; but it is well known that its peculiar manifestations in a given in dividual depend almost entirely on the habits he may form during the early period of its activity. Exposure to bad company then makes him a loose liver all his days; chastity kept at first makes the same easy later on. In all pedagogy the great thing is to strike the iron while hot, and to seize the wave of the pupil's interest in each succes sive subject before its ebb has come, so that knowledge may be got and a habit of skill acquired — a headway of in terest, in short, secured, on which afterward the individual may float. There is a happy moment for fixing skill in drawing, for making boys collectors in natural history, and presently dissectors and botanists ; then for initiating them into the harmonies of mechanics and the wonders of physi cal and chemical law. Later, introspective psychology and the metaphysical and religious mysteries take their turn ; and, last of all, the drama of human affairs and worldly wisdom in the widest sense of the term. In each of us a saturation-point is soon reached in all these things ; the impetus of our purely intellectual zeal expires, and un less the topic be one associated with some urgent personal need that keeps our wits constantly whetted about it, we 402 PSYCHOLOGY. settle into an equilibrium, and live on what we learned when our interest was fresh and instinctive, without adding to the store. Outside of their own business, the ideas gained by men before they are twenty-five are practically the only ideas they shall have in their lives. They cannot get anything new. Disinterested curiosity is past, the mental grooves and channels set, the power of assimilation gone. If by chance we ever do learn anything about some entirely new topic we are afflicted with a strange sense of insecurity, and we fear to advance a resolute opinion. But, with things learned in the plastic days of instinctive curi osity we never lose entirely our sense of being at home. There remains a kinship, a sentiment of intimate acquaint ance, which, even when we know we have failed to keep abreast of the subject, flatters us with a sense of power over it, and makes us feel not altogether out of the pale. Whatever individual exceptions might be cited to this are of the sort that 'prove the rule.' To detect the moment of the instinctive readiness for the subject is, then, the first duty of every educator. As for the pupils, it would probably lead to a more earnest temper on the part of college students if they had less be lief in their unlimited future intellectual potentialities, and could be brought to realize that whatever physics and polit ical economy and philosophy they are now acquiring are, for better or worse, the physics and political economy and philosophy that will have to serve them to the end. The natural conclusion to draw from this transiency of instincts is that most instincts are implanted for the sake of giving rise to habits, and that, this purpose once accomplished, the instincts themselves, as such, have no raison d'etre in the psychical economy, and consequently fade away. That occa sionally an instinct should fade before circumstances per mit of a habit being formed, or that, if the habit be formed, other factors than the pure instinct should modify its course, need not surprise us. Life is full of the imperfect adjustment to individual cases, of arrangements which, tak ing the species as a whole, are quite orderly and regular. Instinct cannot be expected to escape this general risk. INSTINCT. 403 SPECIAL HUMAN INSTINCTS. Let us now test our principles by turning to human instincts in more detail. We cannot pretend in these pages to be minute or exhaustive. But we can say enough to set all the above generalities in a more favorable light. But first, what kind of motor reactions upon objects shall we count as instincts? This, as aforesaid, is a somewhat arbitrary matter. Some of the actions aroused in us by objects go no further than our own bodies. Such is the bristling up of the attention when a novel object is per ceived, or the ' expression ' on the face or the breathing apparatus of an emotion it may excite. These movements merge into ordinary reflex actions like laughing when tickled, or making a wry face at a bad taste. Other actions take effect upon the outer world. Such are flight from a wild beast, imitation of what we see a comrade do, etc. On the whole it is best to be catholic, since it is very hard to draw an exact line ; and call both of these kinds of activity instinctive, so far as either may be naturally provoked by the presence of specific sorts of outward fact. Professor Preyer, in his careful little work, ' Die Seele des Kindes,' says " instinctive acts are in man few in number, and, apart from those connected with the sexual passion, difficult to recognize after early youth is past." And he adds, " so much the more attention should we pay to the instinctive movements of new-born babies, suck lings, and small children." That instinctive acts should be easiest recognized in childhood would be a very natural effect of our principles of transitoriness, and of the restric tive influence of habits once acquired ; but we shall see how far they are from being ' few in number ' in man. Professor Preyer divides the movements of infants into impulsive, reflex, and instinctive. By impulsive movements he means random movements of limbs, body, and voice, with no aim, and before perception is aroused. Among the first reflex movements are crying on contact with the air, sneezing, snuffling, snoring, coughing, sighing, sobbing, gagging, vomiting, hiccuping, starting, moving the limbs when tickled, touched, or Uoivn upon, etc., etc. 404 PSYCHOLOGY. Of the movements called by him instinctive in the child, Professor Preyer gives a full account. Herr Schneider does the same ; and as their descriptions agree with each other and with what other writers about infancy say, I will base my own very brief statement on theirs. Sucking : almost perfect at birth ; not coupled with any congenital tendency to seek the breast, this being a later acquisition. As we have seen, sucking is a transitory in stinct. Biting an object placed in the mouth, chewing and grind ing the teeth ; licking sugar ; making characteristic grimaces over bitter and sweet tastes ; spitting out. Clasping an object which touches the fingers or toes. Later, attempts to grasp at an object seen at a distance. Pointing at such objects, and making a peculiar sound ex pressive of desiret which, in my own three children, was the first manifestation of speech, occurring many weeks before other significant sounds. Carrying to the mouth of the object, when grasped. This instinct, guided and inhibited by the sense of taste, and combined with the instincts of biting, chewing, sucking, spitting-out, etc., and with the reflex act of swallowing, leads in the individual to a set of habits which constitute his function of alimentation, and which may or may not be gradually modified as life goes on. Crying at bodily discomfort, hunger, or pain, and at solitude. Smiling at being noticed, fondled, or smiled at by others. It seems very doubtful whether young infants have any instinctive fear of a terrible or scowling face. 1 have been unable to make my own children, under a year old, change their expression when I changed mine ; at most they manifested attention or curiosity. Preyer instances a protrusion of the lips, which, he says, may be so great as to remind one of that in the chimpanzee, as an instinctive expression of concentrated attention in the human infant. Turning the head aside as a gesture of rejection, a gesture usually accompanied with a frown and a bending back oi the body, and with holding the breath. Holding head erect. Sitting up. INSTINCT. 405 Standing. Locomotion. The early movements of children's limbs are more or less symmetrical. Later a baby will move his legs in alternation if suspended in the air. But until the impulse to walk awakens by the natural ripening of the nerve-centres, it seems to make no difference how often the child's feet may be placed in contact with the ground ; the legs remain limp, and do not respond to the sensation of contact in the soles by muscular contractions pressing down wards. No sooner, however, is the standing impulse born, than the child stiffens his legs and presses downward as soon as he feels the floor. In some babies this is the first locomotory reaction. In others it is preceded by the in stinct to creep, which arises, as I can testify, often in a very sudden way. Yesterday the baby sat quite contentedly wherever he was put ; to-day it has become impossible to keep him sitting at all, so irresistible is the impulse, aroused by the sight of the floor, to throw himself forward upon his hands. Usually the arms are too weak, and the ambitious little experimenter falls on his nose. But his perseverance is dauntless, and he ends in a few days by learning to travel rapidly around the room in the quadrupedal way. The position of the legs in ' creeping ' varies much from one -child to another. My own child, when creeping, was often observed to pick up objects from the floor with his mouth, a phenomenon which, as Dr. O. W. Holmes has remarked, like the early tendency to grasp with the toes, easily lends itself to interpretation as a reminiscence of prehuman an cestral habits. The walking instinct may awaken with no less sudden ness, and its entire education be completed within a week's compass, barring, of course, a little 'grogginess' in the gait. Individual infants vary enormously ; but on the whole it is safe to say that the mode of development of these locomotor instincts is inconsistent with the account given by the older English associationist school, of their being results of the individual's education, due altogether to the gradual association of certain perceptions with certain hap hazard movements and certain resultant pleasures. Mr- 406 PSYCHOLOGY. Bain has tried,* by describing the demeanor of new-born lambs, to show that locomotion is learned by a very rapid experience. But the observation recorded proves the faculty to be almost perfect from the first ; and all others who have observed new-born calves, lambs, and pigs agree that in these animals the powers of standing and walking, and of interpreting the topographical significance of sights and sounds, are all but fully developed at birth. Often in animals who seem to be ' learning ' to walk or fly the sem blance is illusive. The awkwardness shown is not due to the fact that ' experience ' has not yet been there to asso ciate the successful movements and exclude the failures, but to the fact that the animal is beginning his attempts before the co-ordinating centres have quite ripened for their work. Mr. Spalding's observations on this point are conclusive as to birds. " Birds," he says, " do not learn to fly. Two years ago I shut up five unfledged swallows in a small box, not much larger than the nest from which they were taken. The little box, which had a wire front, was hung on the wall near the nest, and the young swallows were fed by their parents through the wires. In this confinement, where they could not even extend their wings, they were kept until after they were fully fledged. ... On going to set the prisoners free, one was found dead. . . . The remaining four were allowed to escape one at a time. Two of these were perceptibly wavering and unsteady in their flight. One of them, after a flight of some ninety yards, disappeared among some trees." No. 3 and No. 4 "never flew against anything, nor was there, in their avoiding objects, any appreciable difference between them and the old birds. No. 3 swept round the Wellingtonia, and No. 4 rose over the hedge, just as we see the old swallows doing every hour of the day. I have this summer verified these observations. Of two swallows I had similarly confined, one, on being set free, flew a yard or two close to the ground, rose in the direction of a beech-tree, which it gracefully avoided ; it was seen for a considerable time sweeping round the beeches and performing magnificent evolutions in the air high above them. The other, which was observed to beat the air with its wings more than usual, was soon lost to sight behind some trees. Titmice, tomtite, and wrens I have made the subjects of similar observations, and with similar results." * In the light of this report, one may well be tempted to make a prediction about the human child, and say that if a * Senses and Intellect 3d ed. pp. 413-675. t Nature, xn. 507 (1875). INSTINCT. 407 baby were kept from getting on his feet for two or three weeks after the first impulse to walk had shown itself in him, — a small blister on each sole would do the business, — he might then be expected to walk about as well, through the mere ripening of his nerve-centres, as if the ordinary process of * learning ' had been allowed to occur during all the blistered time. It is to be hoped that some scientific widower, left alone with his offspring at the critical moment, may ere long test this suggestion on the living subject. Climbing on trees, fences, furniture, banisters, etc., is a well- marked instinctive propensity which ripens after the fourth year. Vocalization. This may be either musical or significant. Yery few weeks after birth the baby begins to express its spirits by emitting vowel sounds, as much during inspira tion as during expiration, and will lie on its back cooing and gurgling to itself for nearly an hour. But this singing has nothing to do with speech. Speech is sound significant. During the second year a certain number of significant sounds are gradually acquired ; but talking proper does not set in till the instinct to imitate sounds ripens in the nervous system; and this ripening seems in some children to be quite abrupt. Then speech grows rapidly in extent and perfection. The child imitates every word he hears uttered, and repeats it again and again with the most evident plea sure at his new power. At this time it is quite impossible to talk itiih him, for his condition is that of ' Echolalia,' — instead of answering the question, he simply reiterates it. The result is, however, that his vocabulary increases very fast ; and little by little, with teaching from above, the young prattler understands, puts words together to express his own wants and perceptions, and even makes intelligent replies. From a speechless, he has become a speaking, animal. The interesting point with regard to this instinct is the oftentimes very sudden birth of the impulse to imi tate sounds. Up to the date of its awakening the child may have been as devoid of it as a dog. Four days later his whole energy may be poured into this new channel. The habits of articulation formed during the plastic age of childhood are in most persons sufficient to inhibit the for- 408 PSYCHOLOGY. mation of new ones of a fundamentally different sort — wit ness the inevitable ' foreign accent ' which distinguishes the speech of those who learn a language after early youth. Imitation. The child's first words are in part vocables of his own invention, which his parents adopt, and whichv as far as they go, form a new human tongue upon the earth ; and in part they are his more or less successful imitations of words he hears the parents use. But the instinct of imitating gestures develops earlier than that of imitating sounds, — unless the sympathetic crying of a baby when it hears another cry may be reckoned as imitation of a sound. Professor Preyer speaks of his child imitating the protru sion of the father's lips in its fifteenth week. The various accomplishments of infancy, making ' pat-a-cake,' saying ' bye-bye,' * blowing out the candle,' etc., usually fall well inside the limits of the first year. Later come all the various imitative games in which childhood revels, playing ' horse,' ' soldiers,' etc., etc. And from this time onward man is essentially the imitative animal. His whole educability and in fact the whole history of civilization depend on this trait, which his strong tendencies to rivalry, jealousy, and acquisitiveness reinforce. ' Humani nihil a me alienwn puto,' is the motto of each individual of the species ; and makes him, whenever another individual shows a power or superiority of any kind, restless until he can exhibit it himself. But apart from this kind of imitation, of which the psychological roots are complex, there is the more direct propensity to speak and walk and behave like others, usually without any conscious intention of so doing. And there is the imitative tendency which shows itself in large masses of men, and produces panics, and orgies, and frenzies of violence, and which only the rarest individuals can actively withstand. This sort of imitativeness is possessed by man in common with other gregarious animals, and is an instinct in the fullest sense of the term, being a blind impulse to act as soon as a cer tain perception occurs. It is particularly hard not to imi tate gaping, laughing, or looking and running in a certain direction, if we see others doing so. Certain mesmerized subjects must automatically imitate whatever motion their INSTINCT. 409 operator makes before their eyes.* A successful piece of mimicry gives to both bystanders and mimic a peculiar kind of aesthetic pleasure. The dramatic impulse, the ten dency to pretend one is someone else, contains this pleasure of mimicry as one of its elements. Another element seems to be a peculiar sense of power in stretching one's own personality so as to include that of a strange person. In young children this instinct often knows no bounds. For a few months in one of my children's third year, he liter ally hardly ever appeared in his own person. It was always, " Play I am So-and-so, and you are So-and-so, and the chair is such a thing, and then we'll do this or that." If you called him by his name, H., you invariably got the reply, " I'm not H., I'm a hyena, or a horse-car," or what ever the feigned object might be. He outwore this impulse after a time ; but while it lasted, it had every appearance of being the automatic result of ideas, often suggested by perceptions, working out irresistible motor effects. Imita tion shades into Emulation or Rivalry, a very intense instinct, especially rife with young children, or at least especially undisguised. Everyone knows it. Nine-tenths of the work of the world is done by it. We know that if we do not do the task some one else will do it and get the credit, so we do it. It has very little connection with sympathy, but rather more with pugnacity, which we proceed in turn to consider. Pugnacity; anger; resentment. In many respects man is the most ruthlessly ferocious of beasts. As with all gregarious animals, ' two souls,' as Faust says, * dwell with in his breast,' the one of sociability and helpfulness, the other of jealousy and antagonism to his mates. Though in a general way he cannot live without them, yet, as regards certain individuals, it often falls out that he cannot live with them either. Constrained to be a member of a tribe, he still has a right to decide, as far as in him lies, of which other members the tribe shall consist. Killing off a few * See, for some excellent pedagogic remarks about doing yourself what you want to get your pupils to do, and not simply telling them to do it, Baumann, Haudbuch der Moral (1879), p. 32 ff. 410 PSYCHOLOGY. obnoxious ones may often better the chances of those that remain. And killing off a neighboring tribe from whom no good thing comes, but only competition, may materially better the lot of the whole tribe. Hence the gory cradle, the bellum omnium contra omnes, in which our race was reared ; hence the fickleness of human ties, the ease with which the foe of yesterday becomes the ally of to-day, the friend of to-day the enemy of to-morrow ; hence the fact that we, the lineal representatives of the successful enactors of one scene of slaughter after another, must, whatever more pacific virtues we may also possess, still carry about with us, ready at any moment to burst into flame, the smoulder ing and sinister traits of character by means of which they lived through so many massacres, harming others, but themselves unharmed. Sympathy is an emotion as to whose instinctiveness psy chologists have held hot debate, some of them contending that it is no primitive endowment, but, originally at least, the result of a rapid calculation of the good consequences to ourselves of the sympathetic act. Such a calculation, at first conscious, would grow more unconscious as it be came more habitual, and at last, tradition and association aiding, might prompt to actions which could not be distin guished from immediate impulses. It is hardly needful to argue against the falsity of this view. Some forms of sym pathy, that of mother with child, for example, are surely primitive, and not intelligent forecasts of board and lodg ing and other support to be reaped in old age. Danger to the child blindly and instantaneously stimulates the mother to actions of alarm or defence. Menace or harm to the adult beloved or friend excites us in a corresponding way, often against all the dictates of prudence. It is true that sympathy does not necessarily follow from the mere fact of gregariousness. Cattle do not help a wounded com rade ; on the contrary, they are more likely to dispatch him. But a dog will lick another sick dog, and even bring him food ; and the sympathy of monkeys is proved by many observations to be strong. In man, then, we may lay it down that the sight of suffering or danger to others is a direct exciter of interest, and an immediate stimulus, if INSTINCT. 411 no complication hinders, to acts of relief. There is noth ing unaccountable or pathological about this— nothing to justify Professor Bain's assimilation of it to the 'fixed ideas ' of insanity, as ' clashing with the regular outgoings of the will.' It may be as primitive as any other 'outgo ing,' and may be due to a random variation selected, quite as probably as gregariousness and maternal love are, even in Spencer's opinion, due to such variations. It is true that sympathy is peculiarly liable to inhibi tion from other instincts which its stimulus may call forth. The traveller whom the good Samaritan rescued may well have prompted such instinctive fear or disgust in the priest and Levite who passed him by, that their sympathy could not come to the front. Then, of course, habits, reasoned reflections, and calculations may either check or reinforce one's sympathy ; as may also the instincts of love or hate, if these exist, for the suffering individual. The hunting and pugnacious instincts, when aroused, also inhibit our sympathy absolutely. This accounts for the cruelty of collections of men hounding each other on to bait or tor ture a victim. The blood mounts to the eyes, and sympa thy's chance is gone.* The hunting instinct has an equally remote origin in the evolution of the race.f The hunting and the fighting in- * Sympathy has been enormously written about in books on Ethics. A very good recent chapter is that by Thos. Fowler: The Principles of Morals part n. chap. n. f " I must now refer to a very general passion which occurs in boys who are brought up naturally, especially in the country. Everyone knows what pleasure a boy takes in the sight of a butterfly, fish, crab or other animal, or of a bird's nest, and what a strong propensity he has for pulling apart, breaking, opening, and destroying all complex objects, how he de- ights in pulling out the wings and legs of flies, and tormenting one animal >r another, how greedy he is to steal secret dainties, with what irresistible strength the plundering of birds' nests attracts him without his havino- the least intention of eating the eggs or the young birds. This fact has long been familiar, and is daily remarked by teachers; but an explanation of these impulses which follow upon a mere perception of the objects, with- t in most cases any representation being aroused of a future pleasure to 3e gained, has as yet been given by no one, and yet the impulses are very easy to explain. In many cases it will be said that the boy pulls things apart from curiosity. Quite correct : but whence comes this curiosity, thia irresistible desire to open everything and see what is inside ? What makes 412 PSYCHOLOGY. stinct combine in many manifestations. They both snpport the emotion of anger ; they combine in the fascination which stories of atrocity have for most minds ; and the utterly blind excitement of giving the rein to our fury when our blood is up (an excitement whose intensity is greater than that of any other human passion save one) is only explicable as an impulse aboriginal in character, and having more to do with immediate and overwhelming tendencies to muscular dis charge than to any possible reminiscences of effects of ex perience, or association of ideas. I say this here, because the pleasure of disinterested cruelty has been thought a paradox, and writers have sought to show that it is no primitive attribute of our nature, but rather a resultant of the subtile combination of other less malignant ele ments of mind. This is a hopeless task. If evolution and the survival of the fittest be true at all, the destruction of prey and of human rivals must have been among the most important of man's primitive functions, the fighting and the chasing instincts must have become ingrained. Certain perceptions must immediately, and without the in tervention of inferences and ideas, have prompted emotions and motor discharges ; and both the latter must, from the nature of the case, have been very violent, and therefore, when unchecked, of an intensely pleasurable kind. It is just because human bloodthirstiness is such a primitive part of us that it is so hard to eradicate, especially where a fight or a hunt is promised as part of the fun.* the boy take the eggs from the nest and destroy them when he never thinks of eating them ? These are effects of an hereditary instinct, so strong that warnings and punishments are unable to counteract it " (Schneider: Der Menschliche Wille, p. 224. See also Der Thierische W'lle, pp. 180-2.) * It is not surprising, in view of the facts of animal bistory and evolu tion, that the very special object blood should have become the stimulus for a very special interest and excitement. That the sight of it should make people faint is strange. Less so that a child who sees his blood flow should forthwith become much more frightened than by the mere feeling of the cut. Horned cattle often, though not always, becoipe furiously excited at the smell of blood. In some abnormal human being.* the sight or thought of it exerts a baleful fascination. " B and his father v*ere at a neighbor's one evening, and, while paring apples, the old man accidentally cut his hand so severely as to cause the blood to flow profusely. B was observed to become restless, nervous, pale, and to have undergone a peculiar INSTINCT. 413 As Rochef oucauld says, there is something in the misfor tunes of our very friends that does not altogether displease us ; and an apostle of peace will feel a certain vicious thrill run through him, and enjoy a vicarious brutality, as he turns to the column in his newspaper at the top of which * Shock ing Atrocity ' stands printed in large capitals. See how the crowd flocks round a street-brawl ! Consider the enormous annual sale of revolvers to persons, not one in a thousand of whom has any serious intention of using them, but of whom each one has his carnivorous self-consciousness agreeably tickled by the notion, as he clutches the handle of his weapon, that he will be rather a dangerous customer to meet. See the ignoble crew that escorts every great pugilist — parasites who feel as if the glory of his brutality rubbed off upon them, and whose darling hope, from day to day, is to arrange some set-to of which they may share the rapture without enduring the pains ! The first blows at a prize-fight are apt to make a refined spectator sick ; but his blood is soon up in favor of one party, and it will then seem as if the other fellow could not be banged and pounded and mangled enough — the refined spectator would like to rein force the blows himself. Over the sinister orgies of blood of certain depraved and insane persons let a curtain be drawn, as well as over the ferocity with which otherwise fairly decent men may be animated, when (at the sacking of a town, for instance), the excitement of victory long de- change in demeanor. Taking advantage of the distraction produced by the accident, B escaped from the house and proceeded to a neighboring farm-yard, where he cut the throat of a horse, killing it." Dr. D. H. Tuke, commenting on this man's case (Journal of Mental Science, October, 1885), speaks of the influence of blood upon him — his whole life had been one chain of cowardly atrocities— and continues : " There can be no doubt that with some individuals it constitutes a fascination. . . . We might speak of a mania sanguinis. Dr. Savage admitted a man from France into Bethlehem Hospital some time ago, one of whose earliest symptoms of in sanity was the thirst for blood, which he endeavored to satisfy by going to an abattoir in Paris. The man whose case I have brought forward had the same passion for gloating over blood, but had no attack of acute mania. The sight of blood was distinctly a delight to him, and at any time blood aroused in him the worst elements of his nature. Instances will easily be recalled in which murderers, undoubtedly insane, have described the in tense pleasure they experienced in the warm blood of children." 414 PSYCHOLOGY. layed, the sudden freedom of rapine and of lust, the con tagion of a crowd, and the impulse to imitate and outdo, all combine to swell the blind drunkenness of the killing-in stinct, and carry it to its extreme. No ! those who try to account for this from above downwards, as if it resulted from the consequences of the victory being rapidly inferred, and from the agreeable sentiments associated with them in the imagination, have missed the root of the matter. Our fe rocity is blind, and can only be explained from beloiv. Could we trace it back through our line of descent, we should see it taking more and more the form of a fatal reflex response, and at the same time becoming more and more the pure and direct emotion that it is.* In childhood it takes this form. The boys who pull out grasshoppers' legs and butterflies' wings, and disem bowel every frog they catch, have no thought at all about the matter. The creatures tempt their hands to a fascinating occupation, to which they have to yield. It is with them as with the ' boy-fiend ' Jesse Pomeroy, who cut a little girl's throat, 'just to see how she'd act.' The normal pro vocatives of the impulse are all living beasts, great and small, toward which a contrary habit has not been formed —all human beings in whom we perceive a certain intent towards us, and a large number of human beings who offend us peremptorily, either by their look, or gait, or by some circumstance in their lives which we dislike. Inhibited by sympathy, and by reflection calling up impulses of an op posite kind, civilized men lose the habit of acting out their pugnacious instincts in a perfectly natural way, and a pass ing feeling of anger, with its comparatively faint bodily ex- " Bombonnel, having rolled with a panther to the border of a ravine, gets his head awaj' from the open mouth of the animal, and by a prodi gious effort rolls her into the abyss. He gets up, blinded, spitting a mass of blood, not knowing exactly what the situation is. He thinks only of one thing, that he shall probably die of his wounds, but that before dying he must take vengeance on the panther. « I didn't think of my pain,' he tells us. ' Possessed entirely by the fury with which I was transported, I drew my hunting-knife, and not understanding what had become of the beast, I sought for her on every side in order to continue the struggle. It was in this plight that the Arabs found me when they arrived.'" (Quoted by Guyan, La Morale sans Obligation, etc., p. 210.) INSTINCT. 415 pressions, may be the limit of their physical combativeness. Such a feeling as this may, however, be aroused by a wide range of objects. Inanimate things, combinations of color and sound, bad bills of fare, may in persons who combine fastidious taste with an irascible temperament produce real ebullitions of rage. Though the female sex is often said to have less pugnacity than the male, the difference seems connected more with the extent of the motor con sequences of the impulse than with its frequency. Women take offence and get angry, if anything, more easily than men, but their anger is inhibited by fear and other principles of their nature from expressing itself in blows. The hunting- instinct proper seems to be decidedly weaker in them than in men. The latter instinct is easily restricted by habit to certain objects, which become legitimate 'game,' while other things are spared. If the hunting-instinct be not ex ercised at all, it may even entirely die out, and a man may enjoy letting a wild creature live, even though he might easily kill it. Such a type is now becoming frequent ; but there is no doubt that in the eyes of a child of nature such a personage would seem a sort of moral monster. Fear is a reaction aroused by the same objects that arouse ferocity. The antagonism of the two is an interest ing study in instinctive dynamics. We both fear, and wish to kill, anything that may kill us ; and the question which of the two impulses we shall follow is usually decided by some one of those collateral circumstances of the particular case, to be moved by which is the mark of superior mental natures. Of course this introduces uncertainty into the reaction ; but it is an uncertainty found in the higher brutes as well as in men, and ought not to be taken as proof that we are less instinctive than they. Fear has bodily expressions of an extremely energetic kind, and stands, beside lust and anger, as one of the three most ex citing emotions of which our nature is susceptible. The progress from brute to man is characterized by nothing so much as by the decrease in frequency of proper occasions for fear. In civilized life, in particular, it has at last be come possible for large numbers of people to pass from the cradle to the grave without ever having had a pang of genu- 416 PSYCHOLOGY. ine fear. Many of us need an attack of mental disease to teach us the meaning of the word. Hence the possibility of so much blindly optimistic philosophy and religion. The atrocities of life become ' like a tale of little meaning though the words are strong ;' we doubt if anything like us ever really was within the tiger's jaws, and conclude that the horrors we hear of are but a sort of painted tapestry for the chambers in which we lie so comfortably at peace with ourselves and with the world. Be this as it may, fear is a genuine instinct, and one of the earliest shown by the human child. Noises seem es pecially to call it forth. Most noises from the outer world, to a child bred in the house, have no exact significance. They are simply startling. To quote a good observer, M. Perez : " Children between three and ten months are less often alarmed by visual than by auditory impressions. In cats, from the fifteenth day, the contrary is the case. A child, three and a half months old, in the midst of the turmoil of a conflagration, in presence of the devouring flames and ruined walls, showed neither astonishment nor fear, but smiled at the woman who was taking care of him, while his parents were busy. The noise, however, of the trumpet of the firemen, wrho were approaching, and that of the wheels of the engine, made him start and cry. At this age I have never yet seen an infant startled at a flash of lightning, even when intense; but I have seen many of them alarmed at the voice of the thunder. . . . Thus fear comes rather by the ears than by the eyes, to the child without experience. It is nat ural that this should be reversed,. or reduced, in animals organized to perceive danger afar. Accordingly, although I have never seen a child frightened at his first sight of fire, I have many a time seen young dogs, young cats, young chickens, and young birds frightened thereby. ... I picked up some years ago a lost cat about a year old. Some months afterward at the onset of cold weather I lit the fire in the grate of my study, which was her reception-room. She first looked at the flame in a very frightened way. I brought her near to it. She leaped away and ran to hide under the bed. Although the fire was lighted every day, it was not until the end of the winter that I could prevail upon her to stay upon a chair near it. The next winter, however, all apprehension had disappeared. . . . Let us, then, conclude that there are hereditary dispositions to fear, which are independent of experience, but which experiences may end by attenuating very considerably. In the human infant I believe them to be particularly connected with the ear.'1* * Psychologic de 1'Enfant, pp. 72-74. In an account of a young gorilla quoted from Falkenstein,by R. Hartmann (' Anthropoid Apes,' International INSTINCT. 417 The effect of noise in heightening any terror we may feel in adult years is very marked. The howling of the storm, whether on sea or land, is a principal cause of our anxiety when exposed to it. The writer has been interested in noticing in his own person, while lying in bed, and kept awake by the wind outside, how invariably each loud gust of it arrested momentarily his heart. A dog, attacking us, is much more dreadful by reason of the noises he makes. Strange men, and strange animals, either large or small, excite fear, but especially men or animals advancing toward us in a threatening way. This is entirely instinctive and antecedent to experience. Some children will cry with terror at their very first sight of a cat or dog, and it will often be impossible for weeks to make them touch it. Others will wish to fondle it almost immediately. Certain kinds of ' vermin,' especially spiders and snakes, seem to excite a fear unusually difficult to overcome. It is impos sible to say how much of this difference is instinctive and how much the result of stories heard about these creatures. That the fear of ' vermin ' ripens gradually, seemed to me to be proved in a child of my own to whom I gave a live frog once, at the age of six to eight months, and again when he was a year and a half old. The first time he seized it promptly, and holding it, in spite of its struggling, at last got its head into his mouth. He then let it crawl up his breast, and get upon his face, without showing alarm. But the second time, although he had seen no frog and heard no story about a frog between whiles, it was almost impos sible to induce him to touch it. Another child, a year old, eagerly took some very large spiders into his hand. At present he is afraid, but has been exposed meanwhile to the teachings of the nursery. One of my children from her birth upwards saw daily the pet pug-dog of the house, and never betrayed the slightest fear until she was (if I recol- 3cientific Series, vol. LII (New York, 1886), p. 265), it is said: "He very much disliked strange noises. Thunder, the rain falling on the skylight, and especially the long-drawn note of a pipe or trumpet, threw him into such agitation as to cause a sudden affection of the digestive organs, and it became expedient to keep him at a distance. When he was slightly in disposed, we made use of this kind of music with results as successful as if we had administered purgative medicine." 418 PSYCHOLOGY. lect rightly) about eight months old. Then the instinct suddenly seemed to develop, and with such intensity that familiarity had no mitigating effect. She screamed when ever the dog entered the room, and for many months re mained afraid to touch him. It is needless to say that no change in the pug's unfailingly friendly conduct had any thing to do with this change of feeling in the child. Preyer tells of a young child screaming with fear on being carried near to the sea. The great source of terror to infancy is solitude. The teleology of this is obvious, as is also that of the infant's expression of dismay — the never- failing cry — on waking up and finding himself alone. Black tilings, and especially dark places, holes, caverns, etc., arouse a peculiarly gruesome fear. This fear, as well as that of solitude, of being l lost,' are explained after a fashion by ancestral experience. Says Schneider : " It is a fact that men, especially in childhood, fear to go into a dark cavern or a gloomy wood. This feeling of fear arises, to be sure, partly from the fact that we easily suspect that dangerous beasts may lurk in these localities— a suspicion due to stories we have heard and read. But, on the other hand, it is quite sure that this fear at a certain perception is also directly inherited. Children who have been carefully guarded from all ghost-stories are nevertheless terrified and cry if led into a dark place, especially if sounds are made there. Even an adult can easily observe that an uncomfortable timidity steals over him in a lonely wood at night, although , he may have the fixed conviction that not the slightest danger is near. "This feeling of fear occurs in many men even in their own house after dark, although it is much stronger in a dark cavern or forest. The fact of such instinctive fear is easily explicable when we consider that our savage ancestors through innumerable generations were accustomed to meet with dangerous beasts in caverns, especially bears, and were for the most part attacked by such beasts during the night and in the woods, and that tnus an inseparable association between the perceptions of darkness of caverns and woods, and fear took place, and was inherited."* High places cause fear of a peculiarly sickening sort, though here, again, individuals differ enormously. The utterly blind instinctive character of the motor impulses here is shown by the fact that they are almost always * Der Menschliche Wille, p. 224. INSTINCT. 419 entirely unreasonable, but that reason is powerless to suppress them. That they are a mere incidental peculiarity of the nervous system, like liability to sea-sickness, or love of music, with no teleological significance, seems more than probable. The fear in question varies so much from one per son to another, and its detrimental effects are so much more obvious than its uses, that it is hard to see how it could be a selected instinct. Man is anatomically one of the best fitted of animals for climbing about high places. The best psychical complement to this equipment would seem to be a * level head ' when there, not a dread of going there at all. In fact, the teleology of fear, beyond a certain point, is very dubious. Professor Mosso, in his interesting monograph, * La Paura ' (which has been translated into French), concludes that many of its manifestations must be considered pathological rather than useful ; Bain, in several places, expresses the same opinion ; and this, I think, is surely the view which any observer without a priori preju dices must take. A certain amount of timidity obviously adapts us to the world we live in, but the fear-paroxysm is surely altogether harmful to him who is its prey. Fear of the supernatural is one variety of fear. It is difficult to assign any normal object for this fear, unless it •were a genuine ghost. But, in spite of psychical research- societies, science has not yet adopted ghosts ; so we can only say that certain ideas of supernatural agency, associated with real circumstances, produce a peculiar kind of horror. This horror is probably explicable as the result of a combi nation of simpler horrors. To bring the ghostly terror to its maximum, many usual elements of the dreadful must com bine, such as loneliness, darkness, inexplicable sounds, espe cially of a dismal character, moving figures half discerned (or,if discerned, of dreadful aspect), and a vertiginous baffling of the expectation. This last element, which is intellectual, is very important. It produces a strange emotional * curdle ' in our blood to see a process with which we are familiar deliberately taking an unwonted course. Any one's heart would stop beating if he perceived his chair sliding unassisted across the floor. The lower animals appear to be sensitive to the mysteriously exceptional as 420 PSYCHOLOGY. well as ourselves. My friend Professor W. K Brooks, of the Johns Hopkins University, told me of his large and noble dog being frightened into a sort of epileptic fit by a bone being drawn across the floor by a thread which the dog did not see. Darwin and Eomanes have given similar experiences.* The idea of the supernatural involves that the usual should be set at naught In the witch and hob goblin supernatural, other elements still of fear are brought in — caverns, slime and ooze, vermin, corpses, and the like.f A human corpse seems normally to produce an instinctive dread,which is no doubt somewhat due to its mysteriousness, and which familiarity rapidly dispels. But, in view of the fact that cadaveric, reptilian, and underground horrors play so specific and constant a part in many nightmares and forms of delirium, it seems not altogether unwise to ask whether these forms of dreadful circumstance may not at a former period have been more normal objects of the envi ronment than now. The ordinary cock-sure evolutionist ought to have no difficulty in explaining these terrors, and the scenery that provokes them, as relapses into the consciousness of the cave-men, a consciousness usually overlaid in us by experiences of more recent date. There are certain other pathological fears, and certain peculiarities in the expression of ordinary fear, which might receive an explanatory light from ancestral con ditions, even infra-human ones. In ordinary fear, one may * Cf. Romanes, Mental Evolution, etc., p. 156. f In the ' Overland Monthly ' for 1887, a most interesting article on Laura Bridgman's writings has been published by Mr. E. C. Sandford. Among other reminiscences of her early childhood, while she still knew nothing of the sign-language, the wonderful blind deaf-mute records the following item in her quaint language : "My father [he was a farmer and probably did his own butchering] used to enter his kitchen bringing some killed animals in and deposited them on one of sides of the room many times. As I perceived it it make me shudder with terror because I did not know what the matter was. I hated to approach the dead. One morning I went to take a short walk with my Mother. I went into a snug house for some time. They took me into a room where there was a coffin. I put my hand in the coffin & felt something so queer. It frightened me unpleasantly. I found something dead wrapped in a silk h'd'k'f so care fully. It must have been a body that had had vitality. ... I did not like to venture to examine the body for I was confounded." INSTINCT 421 either run, or remain semi-paralyzed. The latter condition reminds us of the so-called death-shamming instinct shown by many animals. Dr. Lindsay, in his work ' Mind in Animals,' says this must require great self-command in those that practise it. But it is really no feigning of death at all, and requires no self-command. It is simply a terror- paralysis which has been so useful as to become hereditary. The beast of prey does not think the motionless bird, insect, or crustacean dead. He simply fails to notice them at all ; because his senses, like ours, are much more strongly excited by a moving object than by a still one. It is the same instinct which leads a boy playing ' I spy ' to hold his very breath when the seeker is near, and which makes the beast of prey himself in many cases motionlessly lie in wait for his victim or silently ' stalk ' it, by rapid ap proaches alternated with periods of immobility. It is the opposite of the instinct which makes us jump up and down and move our arms when we wish to attract the notice of some one passing far away, and makes the shipwrecked sailor frantically wave a cloth upon the raft where he is floating when a distant sail appears. Now, may not the statue-like, crouching immobility of some melancholiacs, insane with general anxiety and fear of everything, be in some way connected with this old instinct ? They can give no reason for their fear to move ; but immobility makes them feel safer and more comfortable. Is not this the mental state of the * feigning ' animal ? Again, take the strange symptom which has been de scribed of late years by the rather absurd name of agora phobia. The patient is seized with palpitation and ter ror at the sight of any open place or broad street which he has to cross alone. He trembles, his knees bend, he may even faint at the idea. Where he has sufficient self- command he sometimes accomplishes the object by keep ing safe under the lee of a vehicle going across, or join ing himself to a knot of other people. But usually he slinks round the sides of the square, hugging the houses as closely as he can. This emotion has no utility in a civilized man, but when we notice the chronic agora phobia of our domestic cats, and see the tenacious way 422 PSYCHOLOGY. in which many wild animals, especially rodents, cling to cover, and only venture on a dash across the open as a desperate measure — even then making for every stone or bunch of weeds which may give a momentary shelter — when we see this we are strongly tempted to ask whether such an odd kind of fear in us be not due to the accidental resur rection, through disease, of a sort of instinct which may in some of our ancestors have had a permanent and on the whole a useful part to play ? Appropriation or Acquisitiveness. The beginnings of ac quisitiveness are seen in the impulse which very young children display, to snatch at, or beg for, any object which pleases their attention. Later, when they begin to speak, among the first words they emphasize are ' me ' and ' mine.' * Their earliest quarrels with each other are about questions of ownership ; and parents of twins soon learn that it con duces to a quiet house to buy all presents in impartial du plicate. Of the later evolution of the proprietary instinct I need not speak. Everyone knows how difficult a thing it is not to covet whatever pleasing thing we see, and how the sweetness of the thing often is as gall to us so long as it is another's. When another is in possession, the impulse to appropriate the thing often turns into the impulse to harm him — what is called envy, or jealousy, ensues. In civilized life the impulse to own is usually checked by a variety of considerations, and only passes over into action under cir cumstances legitimated by habit and common consent, an additional example of the way in which one instinctive ten dency may be inhibited by others. A variety of the propri etary instinct is the impulse to form collections of the same sort of thing. It differs much in individuals, and shows in a striking way how instinct and habit interact. For, al- * I lately saw a boy of five (who had been told the story of Hector and Achilles) teaching his younger brother, aged three, how to play Hector, wHle he himself should play Achilles, and chase him round the walls of Troy. Having armed themselves, Achilles advanced, shouting "Where's my Patroklos ? " Whereupon the would-be Hector piped up, quite distract ed from his role, ' ' Where's my Patroklos ? I want a Patroklos ! I want a Patroklos ! " — and broke up the game. Of what kind of a thing a Patroklos might be he had, of course, no notion— enough that his brother had one, for him to claim one too. INSTINCT. 423 though a collection of any given thing — like postage-stamps — need not be begun by any given person, yet the chances are that if accidentally it be begun by a person with the col lecting instinct, it will probably be continued. The chief interest of the objects, in the collector's eyes, is that they are a collection, and that they are his. Kivalry, to be sure, inflames this, as it does every other passion, yet the objects of a collector's mania need not be necessarily such as are generally in demand. Boys will collect anything that they see another boy collect, from pieces of chalk and peach-pits up to books and photographs. Out of a hundred students whom I questioned, only four or five had never collected anything.* The associationist psychology denies that there is any blind primitive instinct to appropriate, and would explain all acquisitiveness, in the first instance, as a desire to secure the ' pleasures ' which the objects possessed may yield ; and, sec ondly, as the association of the idea of pleasantness with the holding of the thing, even though the pleasure originally got by it was only gained through its expense or destruction. Thus the miser is shown to us as one who has transferred to the gold by which he may buy the goods of this life all the emotions which the goods themselves would yield ; and who thereafter loves the gold for its own sake, preferring the means of pleasure to the pleasure itself. There can be little doubt that much of this analysis a broader view of the facts would have dispelled. ' The miser ' is an abstrac tion. There are all kinds of misers. The common sort, the excessively niggardly man, simply exhibits the psycho logical law that the potential has often a far greater influ ence over our mind than the actual. A man will not marry now, because to do so puts an end to his indefinite potenti alities of choice of a partner. He prefers the latter. He will not use open fires or wear his good clothes, because the day may come when he will have to use the furnace or dress in a worn-out coat, ' and then where will he be ? ' * In • The Nation ' for September 3, 1886, President G. S. Hall has given some account of a statistical research on Boston school-boys, by Miss Wiltse, from which it appears that only nineteen out of two hundred and twenty-nine had made no collections. 424 PSYCHOLOGY. For him, better the actual evil than the fear of it ; and so it is with the common lot of misers. Better to live poor now, with the power of living rich, than to live rich at the risk of losing the power. These men value their gold, not for its own sake, but for its powers. Demonetize it, and see how quickly they will get rid of it ! The associationist the ory is, as regards them, entirely at fault : they care noth ing for the gold in se. With other misers there combines itself with this pref erence of the power over the act the far more instinctive element of the simple collecting propensity. Every one collects money, and when a man of petty ways is smitten with the collecting mania for this object he necessarily be comes a miser. Here again the associationist psychology is wholly at fault. The hoarding instinct prevails widely among animals as well as among men. Professor Silliman has thus described one of the hoards of the California wood-rat, made in an empty stove of an unoccupied house : " I found the outside to be composed entirely of spikes, all laid with symmetry, so as to present the points of the nails outward. In the centre of this mass was the nest, composed of finely-divided fibres of hemp-packing. Interlaced with the spikes were the following : about two dozen knives, forks, and spoons ; all the butcher's knives, three in number ; a large carving-knife, fork, and steel ; several large plugs of tobacco, ... an old purse containing some silver, matches, and tobacco ; nearly all the small tools from the tool-closets, with several large augers, ... all of which must have been transported some dis tance, as they were originally stored in different parts of the house. . . . The outside casing of a silver watch was disposed of -in one part of the pile, the glass of the same watch in another, and the works in still another."* In every lunatic asylum we find the collecting instinct developing itself in an equally absurd way. Certain pa tients will spend all their time picking pins from the floor and hoarding them. Others collect bits of thread, buttons, or rags, and prize them exceedingly. Now, 'the Miser ' par excellence of the popular imagination and of melodrama, the monster of squalor and misanthropy, is simply one of these mentally deranged persons. His in tellect may in many matters be clear, but his instincts, * Quoted in Lindsay, ' Mind in Lower Animals,' vol. n. p. 151. INSTINCT. 425 especially that of ownership, are insane, and their insanity has no more to do with the association of ideas than with the precession of the equinoxes. As a matter of fact his hoarding usually is directed to money ; but it also includes almost anything besides. Lately in a Massachusetts. town there died a miser who principally hoarded newspapers. These had ended by so filling all the rooms of his good- sized house from floor to ceiling that his living-space was restricted to a few narrow channels between them. Even as I write, the morning paper gives an account of the emptying of a miser's den in Boston by the City Board of Health. What the owner hoarded is thus described : u He gathered old newspapers, wrapping-paper, incapacitated um brellas, canes, pieces of common wire, cast-off clothing, empty barrels, pieces of iron, old bones, battered tin-ware, fractured pots, and bushels of such miscellany as is to be found only at the city 'dump.' The empty barrels were filled, shelves were filled, every hole and corner was filled, and in order to make more storage-room, ' the hermit ' covered his store-room with a network of ropes, and hung the ropes as full as they could hold of his curious collections. There was nothing one could think of that wasn't in that room. As a wood-sawyer, the old man had never thrown away a saw-blade or a wood-buck. The bucks were rheu matic and couldn't stand up, and the saw-blades were worn down to almost nothing in the middle. Some had been actually worn in two, but the ends were carefully saved and stored away. As a coal-heaver, the old man had never cast off a worn-out basket, and there were dozens of the remains of the old things, patched up with canvas and rope-yarns, in the store-room. There were at least two dozen old bats, fur, cloth, silk, and straw," etc. Of course there may be a great many * associations of ideas ' in the miser's mind about the things he hoards. He is a thinking being, and must associate things; but, without an entirely blind impulse in this direction behind all his ideas, such practical results could never be reached.* Kleptomania, as it is called, is an uncontrollable impulse to appropriate, occurring in persons whose ' associations of ideas' would naturally all be of a counteracting sort. * Cf . Flint, Mind, vol. i. pp. 330-333 ; Sully, iUd. p. 567. Most people probably have the impulse to keep bits of useless finery, old tools, pieces of once useful apparatus, etc. ; but it is normally either inhibited at the outset by reflection, or, if yielded to, the objects soon grow displeasing %nd are thrown away. 426 PSYCHOLOGY. Kleptomaniacs often promptly restore, or permit to be re stored, what they have taken ; so the impulse need not be to keep, but only to take. But elsewhere hoarding com plicates the result. A gentleman, with whose case I am acquainted, was discovered, after his death, to have a hoard in his barn of all sorts of articles, mainly of a trumpery sort, but including pieces of silver which he had stolen from his own dining-room, and utensils which he had stolen from his own kitchen, and for which he had afterward bought substitutes with his own money. Constructiveness is as genuine and irresistible an instinct in man as in the bee or the beaver. Whatever things are plastic to his hands, those things he must remodel into shapes of his own, and the result of the remodelling, how ever useless it may be, gives him more pleasure than the original thing. The mania of young children for breaking and pulling apart whatever is given them is more often the expression of a rudimentary constructive impulse than of a destructive one. ' Blocks ' are the playthings of which they are least apt to tire. Clothes, weapons, tools, habitations, and works of art are the result of the discoveries to which the plastic instinct leads, each individ ual starting where his forerunners left off, and tradition preserving all that once is gained. Clothing, where not necessitated by cold, is nothing but a sort of attempt to re model the human body itself — an attempt still better shown in the various tattooings, tooth-filings, scarrings, and other mutilations that are practised by savage tribes. As for habitation, there can be no doubt that the instinct to seek a sheltered nook, open only on one side, into which he may retire and be safe, is in man quite as specific as the in stinct of birds to build a nest. It is not necessarily in the shape of a shelter from wet and cold that the need comes before him, but lie feels less exposed and more at home when not altogether uninclosed than when lying all abroad. Of course the utilitarian origin of this instinct is obvious. But to stick to bare facts at present and not to trace origins, we must admit that this instinct now exists, and probabty always has existed, since man was man. Habits INSTINCT. 427 of the most complicated kind are reared upon it. But even in the midst of these habits we see the blind instinct cropping out ; as, for example, in the fact that we feign a shelter within a shelter, by backing up beds in rooms with their heads against the wall, and never lying in them the other way— just as dogs prefer to get under or upon some piece of furniture to sleep, instead of lying in the middle of the room. The first habitations were caves and leafy grottoes, bettered by the hands ; and we see children to day, when playing in wild places, take the greatest delight in discovering and appropriating such retreats and ' play ing house ' there. Play. The impulse to play in special ways is certainly instinctive. A boy can no more help running after another boy who runs provokingly near him, than a kitten can help running after a rolling ball. A child trying to get into its own hand some object which it sees another child pick up, and the latter trying to get away with the prize, are just as much slaves of an automatic prompting as are two chickens or fishes, of which one has taken a big morsel into its moutli and decamps with it, while the other darts after in pursuit. All simple active games are attempts to gain the excitement yielded by certain primitive instincts, through feigning that the occasions for their exercise are there. They involve imitation, hunting, fighting, rivalry, acquisitiveness, and construction, combined in various ways ; their special rules are habits, discovered by accident, selected by intelligence, and propagated by tradition ; but unless they were founded' in automatic impulses, games would lose most of their zest. The sexes differ somewhat in their play-impulses. As Schneider says : "The little boy imitates soldiers, models clay into an oven, builds houses, makes a wagon out of chairs, rides on horseback upon a stick, drives nails with the hammer, harnesses his brethren and comrades together and plays the stage-driver, or lets himself be captured as a wild horse by some one else. The girl, on the contrary, plays with her doll, washes and dresses it, strokes it, clasps and kisses it, puts it to bed and tucks it in, sings it a cradle-song, or speaks with it as if it • were a living being. . . . This fact that a sexual difference exists in the play-impulse, that a boy gets more pleasure from a horse and 428 PSYCHOLOGY. rider and a soldier than from a doll, while with the girl the opposite is the case, is proof that an hereditary connection exists between the perception of certain things (horse, doll, etc.), and the feeling of pleas ure, as well as between this latter and the impulse to play." * There is another sort of human play, into which higher aesthetic feelings enter. I refer to that love of festivities, ceremonies, ordeals, etc., which seems to be universal in our species. The lowest savages have their dances, more or less formally conducted. The various religions have their solemn rites and exercises, and civic and military power symbolize their grandeur by processions and celebrations of divers sorts. We have our operas and parties and mas querades. An element common to all these ceremonial games, as they may be called, is the excitement of con certed action as one of an organized crowd. The same acts, performed with a crowd, seem to mean vastly more than when performed alone. A walk with the people on a holiday afternoon, an excursion to drink beer or coffee at a popular * resort,' or an ordinary ball-room, are ex amples of this. Not only are we amused at seeing so many strangers, but there is a distinct stimulation at feeling our share in their collective life. The percep tion of them is the stimulus ; and our reaction upon it is our tendency to join them and do what they are doing, and our unwillingness to be the first to leave off and go home alone. This seems a primitive element in our nature, as it is difficult to trace any association of ideas that could lead up to it ; although, once granting it to exist, it is very easy to see what its uses to a tribe might be in facilitating prompt and vigorous collective action. The formation of armies and the undertaking of military expeditions would be among its fruits. In the ceremonial games it is but the impulsive starting-point. What particular things the crowd then shall do, depends for the most part on the initiative of individuals, fixed by imitation and habit, and continued by tradition. The co-operation of other aesthetic pleasures with games, ceremonial or other, has a great deal to do with the selection of such as shall become stereotyped and * Der Menschliclio Wille, p. 205. INSTINCT. 429 habitual. The peculiar form of excitement called by Pro fessor Bain the emotion of pursuit, the pleasure of a cres- cendc, is the soul of many common games. The immense extent of the play-activities in human life is too obvious to be more than mentioned.* Curiosity. Already pretty low down among vertebrates we find that any object may excite attention, provided it be only novel, and that attention may be followed by approach and exploration by nostril, lips, or touch. Curiosity and fear form a couple of antagonistic emotions liable to be awakened by the same outward thing, and manifestly both useful to their possessor. The spectacle of their alternation is often amusing enough, as in the timid approaches and scared wheelings which sheep or cattle will make in the presence of some new object they are investigating. I have seen alligators in the water act in precisely the same way towards a man seated on the beach in front of them — grad ually drawing near as long as he kept still, frantically careering back as soon as he made a movement. Inasmuch as new objects may always be advantageous, it is better that an animal should not absolutely fear them. But, inas much as they may also possibly be harmful, it is better that he should not be quite indifferent to them either, but on the whole remaining on the qui vive, ascertain as much about them, and what they may be likely to bring forth, a& he can, before settling down to rest in their presence. Some such susceptibility for being excited and irritated by the mere novelty, as such, of any movable feature of the environment must form the instinctive basis of all human curiosity; though, of course, the superstructure absorbs contributions from so many other factors of the emotional life that the original root may be hard to find. With what * Professor Lazarus (Die Reize des Spieles, Berlin, 1883, p. 44) denies that we have an instinct to play, and says the root of the matter is the aver sion to remain unoccupied, which substitutes a sham occupation when no real one is ready. No doubt this is true; but why the particular forms of sham occupation? The elements of all bodily games and of ceremonial games are given by direct excito-motor stimulations — just as when puppies chase one another and swallows have a parliament. 430 PSYCHOLOGY. is called scientific curiosity, and with metaphysical wonder, the practical instinctive root has probably nothing to do. The stimuli here are not objects, but ways of conceiving objects ; and the emotions and actions they give rise to are to be classed, with many other aesthetic manifestations, sen sitive and motor, as incidental features of our mental life, The philosophic brain responds to an inconsistency or a gap in its knowledge, just as the musical brain responds to a discord in what it hears. At certain ages the sensitiveness to particular gaps and the pleasure of resolving particular puzzles reach their maximum, and then it is that stores of scientific knowledge are easiest and most naturally laid in. But these effects may have had nothing to do with the uses for which the brain was originally given ; and it is probably only within a few centuries, since religious beliefs and economic applications of science have played a prominent part in the conflicts of one race with another, that they may have helped to 'select' for survival a particular type of brain. I shall have to consider this matter of incidental and supernumerary faculties in Chapter XXVIII. Sociability and Shyness. As a gregarious animal, man is excited both by the absence and by the presence of his kind. To be alone is one of the greatest of evils for him. Solitary confinement is by many regarded as a mode of torture too cruel and unnatural for civilized countries to adopt. To one long pent up on a desert island, the sight of a human footprint or a human form in the distance would be the most tumultuously exciting of experiences. In morbid states of mind, one of the commonest symptoms is the fear of being alone. This fear may be assuaged by the presence of a little child, or even of a baby. In a case of hydrophobia known to the writer, the patient insisted on keeping his room crowded with neighbors all the while, so intense was his fear of solitude. In a gregarious ani mal, the perception that he is alone excites him to vigorous activity. Mr. Galton thus describes the behavior of the South African cattle whom he had such good opportunities for observing : " Although the ox has little affection for, or interest in, his fellows, he cannot endure even a momentary separation from his herd. If he INSTINCT. 431 oe separated from it by stratagem or force, he exhibits every sign of mental agony; he strives with all his might to get back again, and when he succeeds he plunges into its middle to bathe his whole body with the comfort of closest companionship.1' * Man is also excited by the presence of his kind. The bizarre actions of dogs meeting strange dogs are not alto gether without a parallel in our own constitution. We f which we are devoid, and were all victims of what is now a pathological aberration limited to individuals. It is more probable that with them the instinct of physical aver- * To most of us it is even unpleasant to sit down in a chair still warm from occupancy by another person's body. To many, hand-shaking is disagreeable. INSTINCT. 439 sion toward a certain class of objects was inhibited early in life by habits, formed under the influence of example; and that then a kind of sexual appetite, of which very likely most men possess the germinal possibility, developed itself in an unrestricted way. That the development of it in an abnormal way may check its development in the normal way, seems to be a well- ascertained medical fact. And that the direc tion of the sexual instinct towards one individual tends to inhibit its application to other individuals, is a law, upon which, though it suffers many exceptions, the whole regime of monogamy is based. These details are a little unpleas ant to discuss, but they show so beautifully the correctness of the general principles in the light of which our review has been made, that it was impossible to pass them over unremarked. Jealousy is unquestionably instinctive. Parental Love is an instinct stronger in woman than in man, at least in the early childhood of its object. I need do little more than quote Schneider's lively description of it as it exists in her : " As soon as a wife becomes a mother her whole thought and feel ing, her whole being, is altered. Until then she had only thought of her own well-being, of the satisfaction of her vanity ; the whole world appeared made only for her ; everything that went on about her was only noticed so far as it had personal reference to herself ; she asked of every one that he should appear interested in her, pay her the requi site attention, and as far as possible fulfil her wishes. Now, how ever, the centre of the world is no longer herself, but her child. She does not think of her own hunger, she must first be sure that the child is fed. It is nothing to her that she herself is tired and needs rest, so long as she sees that the child's sleep is disturbed ; the moment it stirs she awakes, though far stronger noises fail to arouse her now. She, who formerly could not bear the slightest carelessness of dress, and touched everything with gloves, allows herself to be soiled by the in fant, and doea not shrink from seizing its clouts with her naked hands. Now, she has the greatest patience with the ugly, piping cry-baby (Schreihals), whereas until now every discordant sound, every slightly unpleasant noise, made her nervous. Every limb of the still hideous little being appears to her beautiful, every movement fills her with de light. She has, in one word, transferred her entire egoism to the child, and lives only in it. Thus, at least, it is in all unspoiled, naturally-bred 440 PSYCHOLOGY. mothers, who, alas ! seem to be growing rarer ; and thus it is with all . the higher animal-mothers. The maternal joys of a cat, for example, are not to be disguised. With an expression of infinite comfort she stretches out her fore-legs to offer her teats to her children, and moves her tail with delight when the little hungry mouths tug and suck. . . . But not only the contact, the bare look of the offspring affords end less delight, not only because the mother thinks that the child will some day grow great and handsome and bring her many joys, but because she has received from Nature an instinctive love for her children. She does not herself know why she is so happy, and why the look of the child and the care of it are so agreeable, any more than the young man can give an account of why he loves a maiden, and is so happy when she is near. Few mothers, in caring for their child, think of the proper purpose of maternal love for the preservation of the species. Such a thought may arise in the father's mind ; seldom in that of the mother. The latter feels only . . . that it is an everlasting delight to hold the being which she has brought forth protectingly in her arms, to dress it, to wash it, to rock it to sleep, or to still its hunger." So far the worthy Schneider, to whose words may be added this remark, that the passionate devotion of a mother —ill herself, perhaps— to a sick or dying child is perhaps the most simply beautiful moral spectacle that human life affords. Contemning every danger, triumphing over every difficulty, outlasting all fatigue, woman's love is here in vincibly superior to anything that man can show. These are the most prominent of the tendencies which are worthy of being called instinctive in the human species.* * Some will, of course, find the list too large, others too small. With the boundaries of instinct fading into reflex action below, and into ac quired habit or suggested activity above, it is likely that there will always be controversy about just what to include under the class-name. Shall we add the propensity to walk along a curbstone, or any other narrow path, to the list of instincts ? Shall we subtract secretiveness, as due to shyness or to fear? Who knows? Meanwhile our physiological method has this in estimable advantage, that such questions of limit have neither theoretical nor practical importance. The facts once noted, it matters little how they are named. Most authors give a shorter list than that in the text. The phrenologists add adhesiveness, inhabitiveness, love of approbation, etc., etc., to their list of ' sentiments,' which in the main agree with our list of instincts. Fortlage, in his System der Psychologie, classes among the Triebe all the vegetative physiological functions. Santlus (Zur Psychologie der Menschlichen Triebe, Leipsic, 1864) says there are at bottom but three instincts, that of 'Being,' that of 'Function,' and that ot 'Life,' The ' Instinct of Being ' he subdivides into animal, embracing the activities of INSTINCT. 441 It will be observed that no other mammal, not even tlw monkey, shows so large an array. In a perfectly-rounded development, every one of these instincts would start a habit toward certain objects and inhibit a habit toward cer tain others. Usually this is the case ; but, in the one sided development of civilized life, it happens that the timely age goes by in a sort of starvation of objects, and the individual then grows up with gaps in his psychic con stitution which future experiences can never fill. Compare the accomplished gentleman with the poor artisan or trades man of a city : during the adolescence of the former, objects appropriate to his growing interests, bodily and mental, were offered as fast as the interests awoke, and, as a consequence^ he is armed and equipped at every angle to meet the world. Sport came to the rescue and completed his education where real things were lacking. He has tasted of the essence of every side of human life, being sailor, hunter, athlete, scholar, fighter, talker, dandy, man of affairs, etc., all in one. Over the city poor boy's youth no such golden opportunities were hung, and in his man hood no desires for most of them exist. Fortunate it is for him if gaps are the only anomalies his instinctive life pre sents ; perversions are too often the fruit of his unnatural bringing up. all the senses ; and psychical, embracing the acts of the intellect and of the ' transempiric consciousness. ' The ' Instinct of Function ' he divides into sexual, inclinational (friendship, attachment, honor) ; and moral (re ligion, philanthropy, faith, truth, moral freedom, etc.). The 'Instinct of Life ' embraces conservation (nutrition, motion) ; sociability (imitation, juridical and ethical arrangements) ; and personal interest (love of inde pendence and freedom, acquisitiveness, self-defence). Such a muddled list as this shows how great are the &Ar- ^ages of the physiological analysis we have used. CHAPTEK XXV.* THE EMOTIONS. IN speaking of the instincts it has been impossible tc keep them separate from the emotional excitements which go with them. Objects of rage, love, fear, etc., not only prompt a man to outward deeds, but provoke characteristic alterations in his attitude and visage, and affect his breath ing, circulation, and other organic functions in specific ways. When the outward deeds are inhibited, these latter emotional expressions still remain, and we read the anger in the face, though the blow may not be struck, and the fear betrays itself in voice and color, though one may suppress all other sign. Instinctive reactions and emotional expressions thus shade imperceptibly into each other. Every object that excites an instinct excites an emotion as well. Emotions, however, fall short of instincts, in that the emotional reaction usually terminates in the subject's own body, whilst the instinctive reaction is apt to go farther and enter into practical rela tions with the exciting object. Emotional reactions are often excited by objects with which we have no practical dealings. A ludicrous object, for example, or a beautiful object are not necessarily ob jects to which we do anything ; we simply laugh, or stand in admiration, as the case may be. The class of emotional, is thus rather larger than that of instinctive, impulses, commonly so called. Its stimuli are more numerous, and its expressions are more internal and delicate, and often less practical. The physiological plan and essence of the two classes of impulse, however, is the same. As with instincts, so with emotions, the mere memory or imagination of the object may suffice to liberate the excite- * Parts of this chapter have already appeared in an article published in 1884 in Mind. 442 THE EMOTIONS. 443 ment. One may get angrier in thinking over one's insult than at the moment of receiving it ; and we melt jnore over a mother who is dead than we ever did when she was living. In the rest of the chapter I shall use the word object of emotion indifferently to mean one which is physically present or one which is merely thought of. It would be tedious to go through a complete list of the reactions which characterize the various emotions. For that the special treatises must be referred to. A few ex amples of their variety, however, ought to find a place here. Let me begin with the manifestations of Grief as a Danish physiologist, C. Lange, describes them : * " The chief feature in the physiognomy of grief is perhaps its para lyzing effect on the voluntary movements. This effect is by no means as extreme as that which fright produces, being seldom more than that degree of weakening which makes it cost an effort to perform actions usually done with ease. It is, in other words, a feeling of weariness ; and (as in all weariness) movements are made slowly, heavily, without strength, unwillingly, and with exertion, and are limited to the fewest possible. By this the grieving person gets his outward stamp : he walks slowly, unsteadily, dragging his feet and hanging his arms. His voice is weak and without resonance, in consequence of the feeble activity of the muscles of expiration and of the larynx. He prefers to sit still, sunk in himself and silent. The tonicity or ' latent innervation ' of the muscles is strikingly diminished. The neck is bent, the head hangs ('bowed down ' with grief), the relaxation of the cheek- and jaw-muscles makes the face look long and narrow, the jaw may even hang open. The eyes appear large, as is always the case where the orbicularis muscle is para lyzed, but they may often be partly covered by the upper lid which droops in consequence of the laming of its own levator. With this condition of weakness of the voluntary nerve- and muscle-apparatus of the whole body, there coexists, as aforesaid, just as in all states of similar motor weakness, a subjective feeling of weariness and heavi ness, of something which weighs upon one; one feels 'downcast,' ' oppressed,' % laden,' one speaks of his ' weight of sorrow,' one must ' bear up ' under it, just as one must ' keep down ' his anger. Many there are who ' succumb ' to sorrow to such a degree that they literally cannot stand upright, but sink or lean against surrounding objects, fall on their knees, or, like. Romeo in the monk's cell, throw themselves upon the earth in their despair. ' ' But this weakness of the entire voluntary motor apparatus (the so-called apparatus of ' animal ' life) is only one side of the physiology of grief. Another side, hardly less important, and in its consequences * Ueber Gemuthsbewegungen, uebersetzt von H. Kurella (Leipzig, 1887). 444 PSYCHOLOGY. perhaps even more so, belongs to another subdivision of the motor appa ratus, namely, the involuntary or ' organic ' muscles, especially those which are found in the walls of the blood-vessels, and the use of which is, by contracting, to diminish the latter's calibre. These muscles and their nerves, forming together the l vaso-motor apparatus,1 act in grief contrarily to the voluntary motor apparatus. Instead of being paralyzed, like the latter, the vascular muscles are more strongly contracted than usual, so that the tissues arid organs of the body become anaemic. The immediate consequence of this bloodlessness is pallor and shrunken- ness, and the pale color and collapsed features are the peculiarities which, in connection with the relaxation of the visage, give to the victim of grief his characteristic physiognomy, and often give an impression of emaciation which ensues too rapidly to be possibly due to real dis turbance of nutrition, or waste uncompensated by repair. Another regular consequence of the bloodlessness of the skin is a feeling of cold, and shivering. A constant symptom of grief is sensitiveness to cold, and difficulty in keeping warm. In grief, the inner organs are unques tionably anaemic as well as the skin. This is of course not obvious to the eye, but many phenomena prove it. Such is the diminution of the various secretions, at least of such as are accessible to observation. The mouth grows dry, the tongue sticky, and a bitter taste ensues which, it would appear, is only a consequence of the tongue's dryness. [The expression 'bitter sorrow' may possibly arise from this.] In nursing women the milk diminishes or altogether dries up. There is one of the most regular manifestations of grief, which apparently con tradicts these other physiological phenomena, and that is the weeping, with its profuse secretion of tears, its swollen reddened face, red eyes, and augmented secretion from the nasal mucous membrane." Lange goes on to suggest that this may be a reaction from a previously contracted vaso-motor state. The expla nation seems a forced one. The fact is that there are changeable expressions of grief. The weeping is as apt as not to be immediate, especially in women and children. Some men can never weep. The tearful and the dry phases alternate in all who can weep, sobbing storms being fol lowed by periods of calm ; and the shrunken, cold, and pale condition which Lange describes so well is more char acteristic of a severe settled sorrow than of an acute mental pain. Properly we have two distinct emotions here, both prompted by the same object, it is true, but affecting differ ent persons, or the same person at different times, and feeling quite differently whilst they last, as anyone's con sciousness will testify. There is an excitement during the crying fit which is not without a certain pungent pleasure THE EMOTIONS. 445 of its own ; but it would take a genius for felicity to dis cover any dash of redeeming quality in the feeling of dry and shrunken sorrow. — Our author continues : u If the smaller vessels of the lungs contract so that these organs become anemic, we have (as is usual under such conditions) the feeling of insufficient breath, and of oppression of the chest, and these tor menting sensations increase the sufferings of the griever, who seeks relief by long-drawn sighs, instinctively, like every one who lacks breath from whatever cause.* * The bronchial tubes may be contracted as well as the ramifications of the pulmonary artery. Professor J. Henle has, amongst his Anthropolo- gische Vortrage, an exquisite one on the ' Natural History of the Sigh,' in which he represents our inspirations as the result of a battle between the red muscles of our skeleton, ribs, and diaphragm, and the white ones of the lungs, which seek to narrow the calibre of the air-tubes. "In the normal state the former easily conquer, but under other conditions they either conquer with difficulty or are defeated. ... The contrasted emo tions express themselves in similarly contrasted wise, by spasm and paraly sis of the unstriped muscles, and for the most part alike in all the organs which are provided with them, as arteries, skin, and bronchial tubes. The contrast among the emotions is generally expressed by dividing them into exciting and depressing ones. It is a remarkable fact that the depressing emotions, like fear,, horror, disgust, increase the contraction of these smooth muscles, whilst the exciting emotions, like joy, anger, etc., make them relax. Contrasts of temperature act similarly, cold like the depressing, and warmth like the exciting, emotions. Cold produces pallor and goose- flesh, warmth smooths out the skin and widens the vessels. If one notices the uncomfortable mood brought about by strained expectation, anxiety before a public address, vexation at an unmerited affront, etc., one finds that the suffering part of it concentrates itself principally in the chest, and that it consists in a soreness, hardly to be called pain, felt in the middle of the breast and due to an unpleasant resistance which is offered to the move ments of inspiration, and sets a limit to their extent. The insufficiency of the diaphragm is obtruded upon consciousness, and we try by the aid of the external voluntary chest-muscles to draw a deeper breath. [This is the sigh. ] If we fail, the unpleasantness of the situation is increased, for then to our mental distress is added the corporeally repugnant feeling of lack of air, a slight degree of suffocation. If, on the contrary, the outer muscles over come the resistance of the inner ones, the oppressed breast is lightened. We think we speak symbolically when we speak of a stone weighing on our heart, or of a burden rolled from off our breast. But really we only express the exact fact, for we should have to raise the entire weight of the atmosphere (about 820 kilog.) at each inspiration, if the air did not balance it by streaming into our lungs." (P. 55.) It must not be forgotten that an inhibition of the inspiratory centre similar to that produced by exciting the superior laryngeal nerve may possibly play a part in these phenomena. For a very interesting discussion of the respiratory difficulty and its cornice- 446 PSYCHOLOGY " The anaemia of the brain in grief is shown by intellectual inertia, dullness, a feeling of mental weariness, effort, and indisposition to work, often by sleeplessness. Indeed it is the anaemia of the motor centres of the brain which lies at the bottom of all that weakening of the voluntary powers of motion which we described in the first instance." My impression is that Dr. Lange simplifies and univer salizes the phenomena a little too much in this description, and in particular that he very likely overdoes the anaemia- business. But such as it is, his account may stand as a favorable specimen of the sort of descriptive work to which the emotions have given rise. Take next another emotion, Fear, and read what Mr. Dar win says of its effects : " Fear is often preceded by astonishment, and is so far akin to it that both lead to the senses of sight and hearing being instantly aroused. In both cases the eyes and mouth are widely opened and the eyebrows raised. The frightened man at first stands like a statue, motionless and breathless, or crouches down as if instinctively to escape observation. The heart beats quickly and violently, so that it palpitates or knocks against the ribs ; but it is very doubtful if it then works more efficiently than usual, so as to send a greater supply of blood to all parts of the body ; for the skin instantly becomes pale as during incipient f aintness. This paleness of the surface, however, is probably in large part, or is ex clusively, due to the vaso-motor centre being affected in such a manner as to cause the contraction of the small arteries of the skin. That the skin is much affected under the sense of great fear, we see in the mar vellous manner in wThich perspiration immediately exudes from it. This exudation is all the more remarkable, as the surface is then cold, and hence the term, a cold sweat ; whereas the sudorific glands are properly excited into action when the surface is heated. The hairs also on the skin stand erect, and the superficial muscles shiver. In connection with the disturbed action of the heart the breathing is hurried. The salivary glands act imperfectly; the mouth becomes dry and is often opened and shut. I have also noticed that under slight fear there is strong tendency to yawn. One of the best marked symptoms is the trembling of all the mus cles of the body ; and this is often first seen in the lips. From this cause, and from the dryness of the mouth, the voice becomes husky or indis tinct or may altogether fail. k Obstupui steteruntque comae, et vox fau- cibus ha3sit.' . . . As fear increases into an agony of terror, we behold, as under all violent emotions, diversified results. The heart beats wild- tion with anxiety and fear, see ' A Case of Hydrophobia ' by the lamented Thos. B. Curtis in the Boston Med. and Surgr. Journal, Nov. 7 and 14, 1878, aud remarks thereou by James J. Putnam, ibid. Nov. 21. THE EMOTIONS. 447 Iv or must fail to act and faintness ensue ; there is a death-like pallor ; the breathing is labored ; the wings of the nostrils are widely dilated ; there is a gasping and convulsive motion of the lips, a tremor on the hollow cheek, a gulping and catching of the throat ; the uncovered and protruding eyeballs are fixed on the object of terror ; or they may roll restlessly from side to side, hue illuc volens oculos totumque pererrat. The pupils are said to be enormously dilated. All the muscles of the body may become rigid or may be thrown into convulsive movements. The hands are alternately clenched and opened, often with a twitching movement. The arms may be protruded as if to avert some dreadful danger, or may be thrown wildly over the head. The Rev. Mr. Hagen- auer has seen this latter action in a terrified Australian. In other cases there is a sudden and uncontrollable tendency to headlong flight ; and so strong is this that the boldest soldiers may be seized with a sudden panic.1'* Finally take Hatred, and read the synopsis of its possible effects as given by Sig. Mantegazza : t "Withdrawal of the head backwards, withdrawal of the trunk; projection forwards of the hands, as if to defend one's self against the hated object ; contraction or closure of the eyes ; elevation of the upper lip and closure of the nose,— these are all elementary movements of turn ing away. Next threatening movements, as : intense frowning ; eyes wide open ; display of teeth ; grinding teeth and contracting jaws ; opened mouth with tongue advanced ; clenched fists ; threatening action of arms ; stamping with the feet ; deep inspirations— panting ; growling and various cries ; automatic repetition of one word or syllable ; sud den weakness and trembling of voice ; spitting. Finally, various mis cellaneous reactions and vaso-motor symptoms: general trembling ; con vulsions of lips and facial muscles, of limbs and of trunk; acts of violence to one's self, as biting fist or nails ; sardonic laughter ; bright redness of face ; sudden pallor of face ; extreme dilatation of nostrils ; stand ing up of hair on head." Were we to go through the whole list of emotions which have been named by men, and study their organic mani festations, we should but ring the changes on the elements which these three typical cases involve. Rigidity of this muscle, relaxation of that, constriction of arteries here, dila tation there, breathing of this sort or that, pulse slowing or quickening, this gland secreting and that one dry, etc., etc. We should, moreover, find that our descriptions had no * Origin of the Emotions, Darwin, pp. 290-2. f La Physionomie et 1'Expression dea Sentiments (Paris, 1885), p. 140. 448 PSYCHOLOGY. absolute truth ; that they only applied to the average man ; that every one of us, almost, has some personal idiosyncrasy of expression, laughing or sobbing differently from his neighbor, or reddening or growing pale where others do not. We should find a like variation in the objects which excite emotion in different persons. Jokes at which one explodes with laughter nauseate another, and seem blas phemous to a third ; and occasions which overwhelm me with fear or bashfulness are just what give you the full sense of ease and power. The internal shadings of emotional feel ing, moreover, merge endlessly into each other. Language has discriminated some of them, as hatred, antipathy, ani mosity, dislike, aversion, malice, spite, vengefulness, ab horrence, etc., etc. ; but in the dictionaries of synonyms we find these feelings distinguished more by their severally appropriate objective stimuli than by their conscious or subjective tone. The result of all this flux is that the merely descriptive literature of the emotions is one of the most tedious parts of psychology. And not only is it tedious, but you feel that its subdivisions are to a great extent either fictitious or unimportant, and that its pretences to accuracy are a sham. But unfortunately there is little psychological writ ing about the emotions which is not merely descriptive. As emotions are described in novels, they interest us, for we are made to share them. We have grown acquainted with the concrete objects and emergencies which call them forth, and any knowing touch of introspection which may grace the page meets with a quick and feeling response. Confessedly literary works of aphoristic philos ophy also flash lights into our emotional life, and give us a fitful delight. But as far as " scientific psychology" of the emotions goes, I may have been surfeited by too much reading of classic works on the subject, but I should as lief read verbal descriptions of the shapes of the rocks on a New Hampshire farm as toil through them again. They give one nowhere a central point of view, or a deductive or generative principle. They distinguish and refine and specify in infinitum without ever getting on to another logi cal level. Whereas the beauty of all truly scientific work THE EMOTIONS. 449 is to get to ever deeper levels. Is there no way out from this level of individual description in the case of the emotions ? I believe there is a way out, but I fear that few will take it. The trouble with the emotions in psychology is that they are regarded too much as absolutely individual things. So long as they are set down as so many eternal and sacred psychic entities, like the old immutable species in natural history, so long all that can be done with them is reverently to catalogue their separate characters, points, and effects. But if we regard them as products of more general causes (as ' species ' are now regarded as products of heredity and variation), the mere distinguishing and cataloguing becomes of subsidiary importance. Having the goose which lays the golden eggs, the description of each egg already laid is a minor matter. Now the general causes of the emotions are indubitably physiological. Prof. C. Lange, of Copen hagen, in the pamphlet from which I have already quoted, published in 1885 a physiological theory of their constitu tion and conditioning, which I had already broached the previous year in an article in Mind. None of the criti cisms which I have heard of it have made me doubt its essential truth. I will therefore devote the next few pages to explaining what it is. I shall limit myself in the first instance to what may be called the coarser emotions, grief, fear, rage, love, in which every one recognizes a strong organic reverberation, and afterwards speak of the subtler emotions, or of those whose organic reverberation is less obvious and strong. EMOTION FOLLOWS UPON THE BODILY EXPRESSION IN THE COABSER EMOTIONS AT LEAST. Our natural way of thinking about these coarser emo tions is that the mental perception of some fact excites the mental affection called the emotion, and that this latter state of mind gives rise to the bodily expression. My theory, on the contrary, is that the bodily changes follow di rectly the perception of the exciting fact, and that our feeling of the same changes as they occur is the emotion. Common -sense says, we lose our fortune, are sorry and weep ; we meet a 450 PS YCHOLOG Y. bear, are frightened and run ; we are insulted by a rival, are angry and strike. The hypothesis here to be defended says that this order of sequence is incorrect, that the one mental state is not immediately induced by the other, that the bodily manifestations must first be interposed between, and that the more rational statement is that we feel sorry because we cry, angry because we strike, afraid because we tremble, and not that we cry, strike, or tremble, be cause we are sorry, angry, or fearful, as the case may be. Without the bodily states following on the perception, the latter would be purely cognitive in form, pale, colorless, destitute of emotional warmth. We might then see the bear, and judge it best to run, receive the insult and deem it right to strike, but we should not actually feel afraid or angry. Stated in this crude way, the hypothesis is pretty sure to meet with immediate disbelief. And yet neither many nor far-fetched considerations are required to mitigate its paradoxical character, and possibly to produce conviction of its truth. To begin with, no reader of the last two chapters will be inclined to doubt the fact that objects do excite bodily changes by a preorganized mechanism, or the farther fact that the changes are so indefinitely numerous and subtle that the entire organism may be called a sounding-board , which every change of consciousness, however slight, may make rever berate. The various permutations and combinations of which these organic activities are susceptible make it ab stractly possible that no shade of emotion, however slight, should be without a bodily reverberation as unique, when taken in its totality, as is the mental mood itself. The immense number of parts modified in each emotion is what makes it so difficult for us to reproduce in cold blood the total and integral expression of any one of them. We may catch the trick with the voluntary muscles, but fail with the skin, glands, heart, and other viscera. Just as an arti ficially imitated sneeze lacks something of the reality, so the attempt to imitate an emotion in the absence of its normal instigating cause is apt to be rather * hollow-' The next thing to be noticed is this, that every one of the THE EMOTIONS. 451 bodily changes, whatsoever it be, is FELT, acutely or obscurely, the moment it occurs. If the reader has never paid attention to this matter, he will be both interested and astonished to learn how many different local bodily feelings he can detect in himself as characteristic of his various emotional moods. It would be perhaps too much to expect him to arrest the tide of any strong gust of passion for the sake of any such curious analysis as this ; but he can observe more tranquil states, and that may be assumed here to be true of the greater which is shown to be true of the less. Our whole cubic capacity is sensibly alive ; and each morsel of it con tributes its pulsations of feeling, dim or sharp, pleasant, painful, or dubious, to that sense of personality that every one of us unfailingly carries with him. It is surprising what little items give accent to these complexes of sensibility. When worried by any slight trouble, one may find that the focus of one's bodily consciousness is the contraction, often quite inconsiderable, of the eyes and brows. When mo mentarily embarrassed, it is something in the pharynx that compels either a swallow, a clearing of the throat, or a slight cough ; and so on for as many more instances as might be named. Our concern here being with the general view rather than with the details, I will not linger to discuss these, but, assuming the point admitted that every change that occurs must be felt, I will pass on. I now proceed to urge the vital point of my whole theory, which is this : If we fancy some strong emotion, and then try to abstract from our consciousness of it all the feelings of its bodily symptoms, we find we have nothing left behind, no ' mind-stuff ' out of which the emotion can be constituted, and that a cold and neutral state of intellectual perception is all that remains. It is true that, although most people when asked say that their introspection verifies this state ment, some persist in saying theirs does not. Many cannot be made to understand the question. When you beg them to imagine away every feeling of laughter and of tendency to laugh from their consciousness of the ludicrousness of an object, and then to tell you what the feeling of its ludi crousness would be like, whether it be anything more than the perception that the object belongs to the class * funny,' 452 PSYCHOLOGY. they persist in replying that the thing proposed is a physical impossibility, and that they always must laugh if they see a funny object. Of course the task proposed is not the practical one of seeing a ludicrous object and anni hilating one's tendency to laugh. It is the purely specu lative one of subtracting certain elements of feeling from an emotional state supposed to exist in its fulness, and say ing what the residual elements are. I cannot help think ing that all who rightly apprehend this problem will agree with the proposition above laid down. What kind of an emotion of fear would be left if the feeling neither of quickened heart-beats nor of shallow breathing, neither of trembling lips nor of weakened limbs, neither of goose-flesh nor of visceral stirrings, were present, it is quite impossible for me to think. Can one fancy the state of rage and pic ture no ebullition in the chest, no flushing of the face, no dil atation of the nostrils, no clenching of the teeth, no impulse to vigorous action, but in their stead limp muscles, calm breathing, and a placid face ? The present writer, for one, certainly cannot. The rage is as completely evaporated as the sensation of its so-called manifestations, and the only thing that can possibly be supposed to take its place is some cold-blooded and dispassionate judicial sentence, confined entirely to the intellectual realm, to the effect that a certain person or persons merit chastisement for their sins. In like manner of grief : what would it be without its tears, its sobs, its suffocation of the heart, its pang in the breast bone ? A feelingless cognition that certain circumstances are deplorable, and nothing more. Every passion in turn tells the same story. A purely disembodied human emotion is a nonentity. I do not say that it is a contradiction in the nature of things, or that pure spirits are necessarily con demned to cold intellectual lives ; but I say that for us, emotion dissociated from all bodily feeling is inconceivable. The more closely I scrutinize my states, the more persuaded I become that whatever moods, affections, and passions I have are in very truth constituted by, and made up of, those bodily changes which we ordinarily call their expres sion or consequence ; and the more it seems to me that if I were to become corporeally anaesthetic, I should be ex- THE EMOTIONS. 453 eluded from the life of the affections, harsh and tender alike, and drag out an existence of merely cognitive or in tellectual form. Such an existence, although it seems to li^ve been the ideal of ancient sages, is too apathetic to be keenly sought after by those born pfter the revival of the worship of sensibility, a few generations ago. Let not this view be called materialistic. It is neither m ore nor less materialistic than any other view which says th,-at our emotions are conditioned by nervous processes. No \reader ot t^is book is likely to rebel against such a sayiirg so long a& it is expressed in general terms ; and if any^ one still finds materialism in the thesis now de fended/' that must be because of the special processes in voked, "jjrhey are %nsational processes, processes due to inward currents aret up by physical happenings. Sfrtfi processes ijave,it is true, always been regarded by the platonizers in psychology as having something peculiarly base about them. But our emotions must always be in wardly what they are, whatever be the physiological ground of their apparition. If they are deep, pure; worthy, spirit ual facts on any conceivable theory of their physiological source, they remain no less deep, pure, spiritual, and worthy of regard on this present sensational theory. They carry their own inner measure of worth with them ; and it is just as logical to use the present theory of the emotions for proving that sensational processes need not be vile and material, as to use their vileness and materiality as a proof that such a theory cannot be true. If such a theory is true, then each emotion is the result ant of a sum of elements, and each element is caused by a physiological process of a sort already well known, The elements are all organic changes, and each of them is the reflex effect of the exciting object. Definite questions now ' immediately arise — questions very different from those which were the only possible ones without this view. Those were questions of classification : " Which are the proper gen era of emotion, and which the species under each ?" or of description: "By what expression is each emotion char acterized?" The questions now are causal: Just what changes does this object and what changes does that object 454 PSYCHOLOGY. excite ?" and " How come they to excite these particular changes and not others ?" We step from a superficial to a deep order of inquiry. Classification and description are the lowest stage of science. They sink into the background the moment questions of genesis are formulated, and remain important only so far as they facilitate our answering these. Now the moment the genesis of an emotion is accounted f o r, as the arousal by an object of a lot of reflex acts which axe forthwith felt, we immediately see why there is KJ limit to the number of possible different emotions which w^y exist, and why the emotions of different individuals may '^'ry indefinitely., both as to their constitution and as to ^ojects which cal1! them forth. Fo:r there i& nothing sacranfntal or eternally fixed in reflex Action. Any sort of reflex effect is possible, and J.Qife,T.cjs actually vary indefinitely, as \£ know. ; 4 'We have all seen men dumb, instead of ftlkative. with joy; we have, seen fright drive the blood into the head of ^s vi ^ctim, instead of making him pale ; we have seen grief run restlessly about lamenting, instead of sitting bo wed down and mute ; etc., etc., and this naturally enough, for one and the same cause can work differently on different men's blood-vessels (since these do not always react alike), whilst more over the impulse on its way through the brain to the vaso-motor centre is differently influenced by different earlier impressions in the form of recollections or associations of ideas." * In short, any classification of the emotions is seen to be as true and as ' natural ' as any other , if it only serves some pur pose ; and such a question as " What is the * real ' or ' typical ' expression of anger, or fear ?" is seen to have no objective meaning at all. Instead of it we now have the question as to how any given ' expression ' of anger or fear may have come to exist ; and that is a real question of physiological mechanics on the one hand, and of history on the other,, which (like all real questions) is in essence answerable, although the answer may be hard to find. On a later page I shall mention the attempts to answer it which have been made. DIFFICULTY OF TESTING THE THEORY EXPERIMENTALLY. I have thus fairly propounded what seems to me the most fruitful way of conceiving of the emotions. It must * Lange, op. cit. p. 75. THE EMOTIONS. 455 be admitted that it is so far only a hypothesis, only pos sibly a true conception, and that much is lacking to its definite proof. The only way coercively to disprove it, however, would be to take some emotion, and then exhibit qualities of feeling in it which should be demonstrably ad ditional to all those which could possibly be derived from the organs affected at the time. But to detect with cer tainty such purely spiritual qualities of feeling would obviously be a task beyond human power. We have, as Professor Lange says, absolutely no immediate criterion by which to distinguish between spiritual and corporeal feel ings; and, I may add, the more we sharpen our introspection, the more localized all our qualities of feeling become (see above, Vol. I. p. 300) and the more difficult the discrimina tion consequently grows.* A positive proof of the theory would, on the • ther hand, be given if we could find a subject absolutely anaesthetic iuside and out, but not paralytic, so that emotion-inspiring objects might evoke the usual bodily expressions from him, but who, on being consulted, should say that no subjective emotional affection was felt. Such a man would be like one who, because he eats, appears to bystanders to be hungry, but who afterwards confesses that he had no appetite at all. Cases like this are extremely hard to find. Medical literature contains reports, so far as I know, of * ut three. In the famous one of Kemigius Leins no mention is made by the reporters of his emotional condition. In Dr. G. Winter's case f the patient is said to be inert and phleg matic, but no particular attention, as I learn from Dr. W., was paid to his psychic condition. In the extraordinary case reported by Professor Strumpell (to which I must refer later in another connection) J we read that the patient, a shoemaker's apprentice of fifteen, entirely anaesthetic, inside * Professor H5ffding, in his excellent treatise on Psychology, admits (p. 342) the mixture of bodily sensation with purely spiritual affection in the emotions. He does not, however, discuss the difficulties of discern ing the spiritual affection (nor even show that he has fairly considered them) in his contention that it exists. f Ein Fall von allgemeiner Anaesthesie (Heidelberg, 1882). j Ziemssen's Deutsches Archiv ftir klinische Medicin, xxn. 321 458 PSYCHOLOGY. , and out, with the exception of one eye and one ear, had 1 shown shame on the occasion of soiling his bed, and grief, when a formerly favorite dish was set before him, at the thought that he could no longer taste its flavor. Dr. Strum- pell is also kind enough to inform me that he manifested surprise, fear, and anger on certain occasions. In observ ing him, however, no such theory as the present one seems to have been thought of ; and it always remains possible that, just as he satisfied his natural appetites and neces sities in cold blood, with no inward feeling, so his emotional expressions may have been accompanied by a quite cold heart* Any new case which turns up of generalized anaes thesia ought to be carefully examined as to the inward emotional sensibility as distinct from the 'expressions ' of emotion which circumstances may bring forth. Objections Considered. Let me now notice a few objections. The replies will make the theory still more plausible. First Objection. There is no real evidence, it may be said, "^The not very uncommon cases of hysterical hemiansesthesia are not complete enough to be utilized in this inquiry. Moreover, the recent re searches, of which some account was given in Chapter IV, tend to show that hysterical anaesthesia is not a real absence of sensibility, but a ' disso ciation/ as M. Pierre Janet calls it, or splitting-off of certain sensations from the rest of the person's consciousness, this rest forming the self which remains connected with the ordinary organs of expression. The split-off consciousness forms a secondary self ; and M. Janet writes me that he sees no reason why sensations whose ' dissociation ' from the body of conscious ness makes the patient practically anaesthetic, might not, nevertheless, contribute to the emotional life of the patient. They do still contribute to the function of locomotion; for in his patient L. there was no ataxia in spite of the anaesthesia. M. Janet writes me, apropos of his anaesthetic patient L., that she seemed to ' suifer by hallucination.' " I have often pricked or bnrned her without warning, and when she did not see me. She never moved, and evidently perceived notlrng. But if afterwards in her move ments she caught sight of her wounded arm, and saw on her skin a little drop of blood resulting from a slight cut, she would begin to cry out and lament as if she suffered a great deal. ' My blood flows,' she said one day ; '1 must be suffering a great deal!' She suffered by hallucination, sort of suffering is very general in hysterics. It is enough for them to re ceive the slightest hint of a modification in their body, when their imagina tion fills up the rest and invents changes that were not felt.' See the remarks published at a later date in Janet's Automatisme Psychologique. pp. 214-15. THE EMOTIONS, 451 for the assumption that particular perceptions do produce wide-spread bodily effects by a sort of immediate physical influence, antecedent to the arousal of an emotion or emo tional idea ? Reply. There is most assuredly such evidence. In listening to poetry, drama, or heroic narrative we are often surprised at the cutaneous shiver which like a sudden wave flows over us, and at the heart-swelling and the lachrymal effusion that unexpectedly catch us at intervals. In listen ing to music the same is even more strikingly true. If we abruptly see a dark moving form in the woods, our heart stops beating, and we catch our breath instantly and before any articulate idea of danger can arise. If our friend goes near to the edge oi a precipice, we get the well-known feel ing of ' all-overishness.' and we shrink back, although we positively know him to be safe, and have no distinct imagi nation of his fall. The writer well remembers his aston ishment, when a boy of seven or eight, at fainting when he saw a horse bled. The blood was in a bucket, with a stick in it, and, if memory does not deceive him, he stirred it round and saw it drip from the stick with no feeling save that of childish curiosity. Suddenly the world grew black before his eyes, his ears began to buzz, and he knew no more. He had never heard of the sight of blood pro ducing faintness or sickness, and he had so little repugnance to it, and so little apprehension of any other sort of danger from it, that even at that tender age, as he well remembers, he could not help wondering how the mere physical pres ence of a pailful of crimson fluid could occasion in him such formidable bodily effects. Professor Lange writes : " No one has ever thought of separating the emotion produced by An unusually loud sound from the true inward affections. No one hesitates to call it a sort of fright, and it shows the ordinary signs of fright. And yet it is by no means combined with the idea of danger, or in any way occasioned by associations, memories, or other mental processes. The phenomena of fright follow the noise immediately with out a trace of * spiritual ' fear. Many men can never grow used to standing beside a cannon when it is fired off, although they perfectly know that there is danger neither for themselves nor for others — the bare sound is too much for them. " * * Ov. cit. p. 63. 458 PSYCHOLOGY. Imagine two steel knife-blades with their keen edges crossing each other at right angles, and moving to and fro. Our whole nervous organization is ' on-edge ' at the thought ; and yet what emotion can be there except the unpleasant nervous feeling itself, or the dread that more of it may come ? The entire fund and capital of the emotion here is the senseless bodily effect which the blades immediately arouse. This case is typical of a class : where an ideal emotion Beems to precede the bodily symptoms, it is often nothing but an anticipation of the symptoms themselves. One who has already fainted at the sight of blood may witness the preparations for a surgical operation with uncontrollable heart-sinking and anxiety. He anticipates certain feelings, and the anticipation precipitates their arrival. In cases of morbid terror the subjects often confess that what possesses them seems, more than anything, to be fear of the fear itself. In the various forms of what Professor Bain calls * tender emotion,' although the appropriate object must usually be directly contemplated before the emotion can be aroused, yet sometimes thinking of the symptoms of the emotion itself may have the same effect. In sentimental natures the thought of 'yearning' will produce real 'yearning/ And, not to speak of coarser examples, a mother's imagi nation of the caresses she bestows on her child may arouse a spasm of parental longing. In such cases as these we see plainly how the emotion both begins and ends with what we call its effects or mani festations. It has no mental status except as either the vivid feeling of the manifestations, or the idea of them ; and the latter thus constitute its entire material, and sum and substance. And these cases ought to make us see how in all cases the feeling of the manifestations may play a much deeper part in the constitution of the emotion than we are wont to suppose. The best proof that the immediate cause of emotion is a physical effect on the nerves is furnished by those patho logical coses in which the emotion is objectless. One of the chief merits, in fact, of the view which I propose seems to be that we can so easily formulate by its mean* Datho. THE EMOTIONS. 459 logical cases and normal cases under a common scheme. In every asylum we find examples of absolutely unmotived fear, anger, melancholy, or conceit ; and others of an equally unmotived apathy which persists in spite of the best of outward reasons why it should give way. In the former cases we must suppose the nervous machinery to be so ' labile ' in some one emotional direction that almost every stimulus (however inappropriate) causes it to upset in that way, and to engender the particular complex of feelings of which the psychic body of the emotion consists. Thus, to take one special instance, if inability to draw deep breath, fluttering of the heart, and that peculiar epigastric change felt as * precordial anxiety,' with an irresistible tendency to take a somewhat crouching attitude and to sit still, and with perhaps other visceral processes not now known, all spontaneously occur together in a certain person ; his feeling of their combination is the emotion of dread, and he is the victim of what is known as morbid fear. A friend who has had occasional attacks of this most distressing of all maladies tells me that in his case the whole drama seems to centre about the region of the heart and respiratory apparatus, that his main effort during the attacks is to get control of his inspirations and to slow his heart, and that the moment he attains to breath ing deeply and to holding himself erect, the dread, ipso facto, seems to depart* The emotion here is nothing but the feeling of a bodily state, and it has a purely bodily cause. It must be confessed that there are cases of morbid fear in which objectively the heart is not much perturbed. These, however, fail to prove anything against our theory, for it is of course possible that the cortical Centres normally percipient of dread as a complex of cardiac and other organic sensations due to real bodily change, should become primarily ex cited m brain-disease, and give rise to an hallucination of the changes being there,— an hallucination of dread, consequently, coexistent with a •omparatively calm pulse, etc. I say it is possible, for I am ignorant of observations which might test the fact. Trance, ecstasy, etc offer analo jrons examples,-not to speak of ordinary dreaming. Under all these con itions one may have the liveliest subjective feelings, either of eye or ear the more visceral and emotional sort, as a result of pure nerre-ceutral mvity, and yet, as I believe, with complete peripheral repose 460 PSYCHOLOGY. 1 ' All physicians who have been much engaged in general practice hare seen cases of dyspepsia in which constant low spirits and occa sional attacks of terror rendered the patient's condition pitiable in the extreme. I have observed these cases often, and have watched them closely, and I have never seen greater suffering of any kind than I have witnessed during these attacks. . . . Thus, a man is suffering from what we call nervous dyspepsia. Some day, we will suppose in the middle of the afternoon, without any warning or visible cause, one of these attacks of terror comes on. The first thing the man feels is great but vague discomfort. Then he notices that his heart is beating much too violently. At the same time shocks or flashes as of electrical dis charges, so violent as to be almost painful, pass one after another through his body and limbs. Then in a few minutes he falls into a condition of the most intense fear. He is not afraid of anything ; he is simply afraid. His mind is perfectly clear. He looks for a cause of his wretched condition, but sees none. Presently his terror is such that he trembles violently and utters low moans ; his body is damp with perspiration; his mouth is perfectly dry ; and at this stage there are no tears in his eyes, though his suffering is intense. When the climax of the attack is reached and passed, there is a copious flow of tears, or else a mental condition in which the person weeps upon the least provocation. At this stage a large quantity of pale urine is passed. Then the heart's action becomes again normal, and the attack passes off." * Again : " There are outbreaks of rage so groundless and unbridled that all must admit them to be expressions of disease. For the medical layman hardly anything can be more instructive than the observation of such a pathological attack of rage, especially when it presents itself pure and unmixed with other psychical disturbances. This happens in that rather rare disease named transitory mania. The patient predis posed to this — otherwise an entirely reasonable person — will be attacked suddenly without the slightest outward provocation, and thrown (to use the words of the latest writer on the subject, O. Schwartzer, Die transito- rische Tobsucht, Wien, 1880), * into a paroxysm of the wildest rage, with a feartul and blindly furious impulse to do violence and destroy.' He flies at those about him ; strikes, kicks, and throttles whomever he can catch ; dashes every object about which he can lay his hands on; breaks and crushes what is near him; tears his clothes; shouts, howls, and roars, with eyes that flash and roll, and shows meanwhile all those symptoms of vaso-motor congestion which we have learned to know as the concomitants of anger. His face is red, swollen, his cheeks hot, hia eyes protuberant and their whites bloodshot, the heart beats vie- *-R. M. Bucke: Man's Moral Nature (N. Y., 1879), p. 97. THE EMOTIONS 461 lently, the pulse marks 100-120 strokes a minutes. The arteries of the neck are full and pulsating, the veins are swollen, the saliva flows. The fit lasts only a few hours, and ends suddenly with a sleep of from 8 to 12 hours, on waking from which the patient has entirely forgotten what has happened." * In these (outwardly) causeless emotional conditions the particular paths which are explosive are discharged by any and every incoming sensation. Just as, when we are seasick, every smell, every taste, every sound, every sight, every movement, every sensible experience whatever, augments our nausea, so the morbid terror or anger is increased by each and every sensation which stirs up the nerve-centres. Absolute quiet is the only treatment for the time. It seems impossible not to admit that in all this the bodily condition takes the lead, and that the mental emotion fol lows. The intellect may, in fact, be so little affected as to play the cold-blooded spectator all the while, and note the absence of a real object for the emotion. f A few words from Henle may close my reply to this first objection : "Does it not seem as if the excitations Of the bodily nerves met the ideas half way, in order to raise the latter to the height of emotions ? [Note how justly this expresses our theory !] That they do so is proved by the cases in which particular nerves, when specially irritable, share in the emotion and determine its quality. When one is suffering from an open wound, any grievous or horrid spectacle will cause pain in the * Lange, op. cit. p. 61. f I am inclined to think that in some hysteriform conditions of grief, rage, etc., the visceral disturbances are less strong than those which go to outward expression. We have then a tremendous verbal display with a hollow inside. Whilst the bystanders are wrung with compassion, or pale with alarm, the subject all the while lets himself go, but feels his insin cerity, and wonders how long he can keep up the performance. The attacks are often surprisingly si ddeu in their onset. The treatment here is to in timidate the patient by a stronger will. Take out your temper, if he takes out his — "Nay, if thou'lt mouth, I'll rant as well as thou." These are the cases of apparently great bodily manifestation with comparatively little real subjective emotion, which may be used to throw discredit on the the ory advanced in the text. — It is probable that the visceral manifestations in these cases are quite disproportionately slight, compared with those of the vocal organs. The subject's state is somewhat similar to that of an actor who does not feel his part. 462 PSYCHOLOGY. wound. In sufferers from heart-disease there is developed a psychic excitability, which is often incomprehensible to the patients themselves, but which comes from the heart's liability to palpitate. I said that the very quality of the emotion is determined by the organs disposed to participate in it. Just as surely as a dark foreboding, rightly grounded on inference from the constellations, will be accompanied by a feeling of oppression in the chest, so surely will a similar feeling of oppression, when due to disease of the thoracic organs, be accompanied by ground' less forebodings. So small a thing as a bubble of air rising from the stomach through the oesophagus, and loitering on its way a few minutes and exerting pressure on the heart, is able during sleep to occasion a nightmare, and during waking to produce a vague anxiety. On the other hand, we see that joyous thoughts dilate our blood-vessels, and that a suitable quantity of wine, because it dilates the vessels, also dis poses us to joyous thoughts. If both the jest and the wine work to gether, they supplement each other in producing the emotional effect, and our demands on the jest are the more modest in proportion as the wine takes upon itself a larger part of the task. " * Second Objection. If our theory be true, a necessary corollary of it ought to be this : that any voluntary and cold-blooded arousal of the so-called manifestations of a special emotion ought to give us the emotion itself. Now this (the objection says) is not found to be the case. An actor can perfectly simulate an emotion and yet be inwardly cold ; and we can all pretend to cry and not feel grief ; and feign laughter without being amused. Reply. In the majority of emotions this test is inappli cable ; for many of the manifestations are in organs over which we have no voluntary control. Few people in pre tending to cry can shed real tears, for example. But, within the limits in which it can be verified, experience corroborates rather than disproves the corollary from our theory, upon which the present objection rests. Every one knows how panic is increased by flight, and how the giving way to the symptoms of grief or anger increases those passions themselves. Each fit of sobbing makes the sorrow more acute, and calls forth another fit stronger still, until at last repose only ensues with lassitude and with the * Op. cit. p. 72. — Lange lays great stress on the neurotic drugs, as parts of his proof that influences of a physical nature upon the body are the first thing in order in the production of emotions. THE EMOTIONS. 463 Apparent exhaustion of the machinery. In rage, it is no torious how we ' work ourselves up ' to a climax by re peated outbreaks of expression. Refuse to express a pas sion, and it dies. Count ten before venting your anger, and its occasion seems ridiculous. Whistling to keep up courage is no mere figure of speech. On the other hand, sit all day in a moping posture, sigh, and reply to every thing with a dismal voice, and your melancholy lingers. There is no more valuable precept in moral education than this, as all who have experience know : if we wish to con quer undesirable emotional tendencies in ourselves, we must assiduously, and in the first instance cold-bloodedly, go through the outward movements of those contrary dispo sitions which we prefer to cultivate. The reward of persis tency will infallibly come, in the fading out of the sullen- ness or depression, and the advent of real cheerfulness and kindliness in their stead. Smooth the brow, brighten the eye, contract the dorsal rather than the ventral aspect of the frame, and speak in a major key, pass the genial com pliment, and your heart must be frigid indeed if it do not gradually thaw ! This is recognized by all psychologists, only they fail to see its full import. Professor Bain writes, for example : " We find that a feeble [emotional] wave ... is suspended inwardly by being arrested outwardly ; the currents of the brain and the agita tion of the centres die away if the external vent is resisted at every point. It is by such restraint that we are in the habit of suppressing pity, anger, fear, pride — on many trifling occasions. If so, it is a fact that the suppression of the actual movements has a tendency to sup press the nervous currents that incite them, so that the external quies cence is followed by the internal. The effect would not happen in any case if there were not some dependence of the cerebral wave upon the free outward vent or manifestation. ... By the same interposition we may summon up a dormant feeling. By acting out the external manifestations, we gradually infect the nerves leading to them, and finally waken up the diffusive current by a sort of action ab extra. . . . Thus it is that we are sometimes able to assume a cheerful tone of mind by forcing a hilarious expression.* * Emotions and Will, pp. 361-8. 464 PSYCHOLOGY. We have a mass of other testimony of similar effect. Burke, in his treatise on the Sublime and Beautiful, writes as follows of the physiognomist Campanella : " This man, it seems, had not only made very accurate observations on human faces, but was very expert in mimicking such as were in any way remarkable. When he had a mind to penetrate into the inclinations of those he had to deal with, he composed his face, his gesture, and his whole body, as nearly as he could, into the exact similitude of the per son he intended to examine ; and then carefully observed what turn of mind he seemed to acquire by the change. So that, says my author, he was able to enter into the dispositions and thoughts of people as effec tually as if he had been changed into the very men. I have often ob served [Burke now goes on in his own person] that, on mimicking tha looks and gestures of angry, or placid, or frightened, or daring men, I have involuntarily found my mind turned to that passion whose appear ance I strove to imitate ; nay, I am convinced it is hard to avoid itr though one strove to separate the passion from its corresponding ges tures." * Against this it is to be said that many actors who per fectly mimic the outward appearances of emotion in face, gait, and voice declare that they feel no emotion at alL Others, however, according to Mr. Wm. Archer, who has made a very instructive statistical inquiry among them, say that the emotion of the part masters them whenever they play it well.f Thus : "'I often turn pale,' writes Miss Isabel Bateman, 'in scenes of terror or great excitement. I have been told this many times, and I can feel myself getting very cold and shivering and pale in thrilling situations.' 'When I am playing rage or terror,' writes Mr. Lionel Brough, ' I believe I do turn pale. My mouth gets dry, my tongue- cleaves to my palate. In Bob Acres, for instance (in the last act), I * Quoted by Dugald Stewart, Elements, etc. (Hamilton's ed.), in. 140, Fechner (Vorschule der Aesthetik, 156) says almost the same thing of him self : "One may find by one's own observation that the imitation of the bodily expression of a mental condition makes us understand it much better than the merely looking on. ... When I walk behind some one whom I do not know, and imitate as accurately as possible his gait and carriage, I get the most curious impression of feeling as the person himself must feel. To go tripping and mincing after the fashion of a young wo man puts one, so to speak, in a feminine mood of mind." f 'The Anatomy of Acting,' in Longman's Magazine, vol. xi. pp. 266, 375, 498 (1888), since repuT khed in book form. THE EMOTIONS. 465 have to continually moisten my mouth, or I shall become inarticulate. I have to u swallow the lump," as I call it.' All artists who have had much experience of emotional parts are absolutely unanimous. . . . ' Playing with the brain,' says Miss Alma Murray, ' is far less fatiguing than playing with the heart. An adventuress taxes the physique far less than a sympathetic heroine. Muscular exertion has comparatively little to do with it.' . . . 'Emotion while acting, 'writes Mr. Howe, 'will induce perspiration much more than physical exertion. I always per spired profusely while acting Joseph Surface, which requires little or no exertion.' . . . 4 1 suffer from fatigue,' writes Mr. Forbes Robertson, 4 in proportion to the amount of emotion I may have been called upon to go through, and not from physical exertion. ' . . . c Though I have played Othello,' writes Mr. Coleman, ' ever since I was seventeen (at nineteen I had the honor of acting the Moor to Macready's lago), hus band my resources as I may, this is the one part, the part of parts, which always leaves me physically prostrate. I have never been able to find a pigment that would stay on my face, though I have tried every preparation in existence. Even the titanic Edwin Forrest told me that he was always knocked over in Oftiello, and I have heard Charlea Kean, Phelps, Brooke, Dillion, say the same thing. On the other hand, I have frequently acted Richard III. without turning a hair.' " * The explanation for the discrepancy amongst actors is probably that which these quotations suggest. The vis- ceral and organic part of the expression can be suppressed in some men, but not in others, and on this it is probable that the chief part of the felt emotion depends. Coquelin and the other actors who are inwardly cold are probably able to affect the dissociation in a complete way. Prof. Sikorsky of Kieff has contributed an important article on the facial expression of the insane to the Neurologisches Centralblatt for 1887. Having practised facial mimicry himself a great deal, he says : ** When I contract my facial muscles in any mimetic combination, 1 feel no emotional excitement, so that the mimicry is in the fullest sense of the word artificial, although quite irreproachable from the expressive point of view.'1 f We find, however, from the context that Prof. S.'s prac tice before the mirror has developed in him such a virtu osity in the control of his facial muscles that he can entirely disregard their natural association and contract them in any order of grouping, on either side of the face isolatedly, * P. 394. f P. 496. 466 PSYCHOLOGY. and each one alone. Probably in liim the facial mimicry is an entirely restricted and localized thing, without sym pathetic changes of any sort elsewhere. Third Objection. Manifesting an emotion, so far from increasing it, makes it cease. Rage evaporates after a good outburst ; it is pent-up emotions that " work like madness in the brain." Eeply. The objection fails to discriminate between what is felt during and what is felt after the manifestation. During the manifestation the emotion is always felt. In the normal course of things this, being the natural channel of discharge, exhausts the nerve-centres, and emotional calm ensues. But if tears or anger are simply suppressed, whilst the object of grief or rage remains unchanged before the mind, the current which would have invaded the nor mal channels turns into others, for it must find some out let of escape. It may then work different and worse effects later on. Thus vengeful brooding may replace a burst of indignation ; a dry heat may consume the frame of one wrho fain would weep, or he may, as Dante says, turn to stone within ; and then tears or a storming fit may bring a grate ful relief. This is when the current is strong enough to strike into a pathological path when the normal one is dammed. When this is so, an immediate outpour may be best. But here, to quote Prof. Bain again : " There is nothing more implied than the fact that an emotion may be too strong to be resisted, and we only waste our strength in the endeavor. If we are really able to stem the torrent, there is no more reason for refraining from the attempt than in the case of weaker feelings. And undoubtedly the habitual control of the emotions is not to be attained without a systematic restraint, extended to weak and strong." When we teach children to repress their emotional talk and display, it is not that they may/eeZ more — quite the reverse. It is that they may think more ; for, to a certain extent, whatever currents are diverted from the regions below, must swell the activity of the thought-iracts of the brain. In apoplexies and other brain injuries we get the opposite condition — an obstruction, namely, to the passage THE EMOTIONS. 467 of currents among the thought-tracts, and with this an in creased tendency of objects to start downward currents into the organs of the body. The consequence is tears, laughter, and temper-fits, on the most insignificant provo cation, accompanying a proportional feebleness in logical thought and the power of volitional attention and decision, — just the sort of thing from which we try to wean our child. It is true that we say of certain persons that " they would feel more if they expressed less." And in another class of persons the explosive energy with which passion manifests itself on critical occasions seems correlated with the way in which they bottle it up during the intervals. But these are only eccentric types of character, and within each type the law of the last paragraph prevails. The sentimentalist is so constructed that ' gushing ' is his or her normal mode of expression. Putting a stopper on the 'gush ' will only to a limited extent cause more ' real ' activities to take its place ; in the main it will simply produce listlessness. On the other hand, the ponderous and bilious ' slumbering vol cano,' let him repress the expression of his passions as he will, will find them expire if they get no vent at all ; whilst if the rare occasions multiply which he deems worthy of their outbreak, he will find them grow in intensity as life proceeds. On the whole, I cannot see that this third ob jection carries any weight. If our hypothesis is true, it makes us realize more deeply than ever how much our mental life is knit up with our corporeal frame, in the strictest sense of the term. Rap ture, love, ambition, indignation, and pride, considered as feelings, are fruits of the same soil with the grossest bodily sensations of pleasure and of pain. But the reader will remember that we agreed at the outset to aifirm this cnly of what we then called the ' coarser ' emotions, and that those inward states of emotional sensibility which appeared devoid at first sight of bodily results should be left out of our account. We must now say a word or two about these latter feelings, the * subtler ' emotions, as we then agreed to call them. 468 PSYCHOLOGY. THE SUBTLER EMOTION'S. These are the moral, intellectual, and aesthetic feelings, Concords of sounds, of colors, of lines, logical consistencies, teleological fitnesses, affect us with a pleasure that seems ingrained in the very form of the representation itself, and to borrow nothing from any reverberation surging up from the parts below the brain. The Herbartian psychologists have distinguished feelings due to the form in which ideas may be arranged. A mathematical demonstration may be as 'pretty,' and an act of justice as ' neat,' as a drawing or a tune, although the prettiness and neatness seem to have nothing to do with sensation. We have, then, or some of us seem to have, genuinely cerebral forms of pleasure and displeasure, apparently not agreeing in their mode of pro duction with the ' coarser ' emotions we have been analyzing. And it is certain that readers whom our reasons have hitherto failed to convince will now start up at this admission, and consider that by it we give up our whole case. Since musi cal perceptions, since logical ideas, can immediately arouse a form of emotional feeling, they will say, is it not more natural to suppose that in the case of the so-called ' coarser * emotions, prompted by other kinds of objects, the emotional feeling is equally immediate, and the bodily expression something that comes later and is added on? In reply to this we must immediately insist that aesthetic emotion, pure and simple, the pleasure given us by certain lines and masses, and combinations of colors and sounds, is an absolutely sensational experience, an optical or auricular feeling that is primary, and not due to the repercussion backwards of other sensations elsewhere consecutively aroused. To this simple primary and immediate pleasure in certain pure sensations and harmonious combinations of them, there may, it is true, be added secondary pleas ures ; and in the practical enjoyment of works of art by the masses of mankind these secondary pleasures play a great part. The more classic one's taste is, however, the less relatively important are the secondary pleasures felt to be in comparison with those of the primary sensation as it THE EMOTIONS. 469 comes in.* Classicism and romanticism have their battles over this point. Complex suggestiveness, the awakening of * Even the feelings of the lower senses may have this secondary escort, due to the arousing of associational trains which reverberate. A flavor may f airly .shake us by the ghosts of ' banquet halls deserted, ' which it sud denly calls up; or a smell may make us feel almost sick with the waft it brings over our memory of ' gardens that are ruins, and pleasure-houses that are dust.' "In the Pyrenees, "says M. Guy au, " after a summer-day's tramp carried to the extreme of fatigue, I met a shepherd and asked him for some milk. He went to fetch from his hut, under which a brook ran, a jar of milk plunged in the water and kept at a coldness which was almost icy. In drinking this fresh milk into which all the mountain had put its perfume, and of which each savory swallow seemed to give new life, I certainly ex perienced a series of feelings which the word agreeable is insufficient to designate. It was like a pastoral symphony, apprehended by the taste in stead of by the ear" (quoted by F. Paulhan from ' Les Problemes de I'^Es- thetique Contemporaiue, p. 63). — Compare the dithyrambic about whiskey of Col. R. Ingersoll, to which the presidential campaign of 1888 gave such notoriety: " I send you some of the most wonderful whiskey that ever drove the skeleton from a feast or painted landscapes in the brain of man. It is the mingled souls of wheat and corn. In it you will find the sunshine and shadow that chase each other over the billowy fields, the breath of June, the carol of the lark, the dews of the night, the wealth of summer, and autumn's rich content — all golden with imprisoned light. Drink it, and you will hear the voice of men and maidens singing the ' Harvest Home/ mingled with the laughter of children. Drink it, and you will feel within your blood the star-lit dawns, the dreamy, tawny dusks of many perfect days. For forty years this liquid joy has been within the happy staves of oak, longing to touch the lips of man."— It is in this way that I should reply to Mr. Gurney's criticism on my theory. My "view," this writer says (Mind, ix. 425), " goes far to confound the two things which in my opinion it is the prime necessity of musical psychology to distinguish — the effect chiefly sensuous of mere streams or masses of finely colored sound, and the distinctive musical emotion to which the form of a sequence of sound, its melodic and harmonic individuality, even realized in complete silence, is the vital and essential object. It is with the former of these two very different things that the physical reactions, the stirring of the hair— the tingling and the shiver — are by far most markedly connected. ... If I may speak of myself, there is plenty of music from which I have received as much emotion in silent representation as when presented by the finest orchestra; but it is with the latter condition that I almost exclusively asso ciate the cutaneous tingling and hair-stirring. But to call rny enjoyment of the/0?*w, of the note-after-noteness of a melody a mere critical ' judgment of right ' [see below, p. 472] would really be to deny to me the power of expressing a fact of simple and intimate expression in English. It is quint- essentially emotion. . . . Now there are hundreds of other bits of music .... which I judge to be right without receiving an iota of the emotion. For purposes of emotion they are to me like geometrical demonstrations or 470 PSYCHOLOGY. vistas of memory and association, and the stirring of our flesh with picturesque mystery and gloom, make a work of art romantic. The classic taste brands these effects as coarse and tawdry, and prefers the naked beauty of the optical and auditory sensations, unadorned with frippery or foliage. To the romantic mind, on the contrary, the immediate beauty of these sensations seems dry and thin. I am of course not discussing which view is right, but only showing that the dis crimination between the primary feeling of beauty, as a pure incoming sensible quality, and the secondary emotions which are grafted thereupon, is one that must be made. These secondary emotions themselves are assuredly for the most part constituted of other incoming sensations aroused by the diffusive wave of reflex effects which the beautiful object sets up. A glow, a pang in the breast, a shudder, a fulness of the breathing, a flutter of the heart, a shiver down the back, a moistening of the eyes, a stirring in the hypogastrium, and a thousand unnamable symptoms besides, may be felt the moment the beauty excites us. And these symptoms also result when we are ex cited by moral perceptions, as of pathos, magnanimity, or courage. The voice breaks and the sob rises in the strug gling chest, or the nostril dilates and the fingers tighten, whilst the heart beats, etc., etc. As far as these ingredients of the subtler emotions go, then, the latter form no exception to our account, but rather an additional illustration thereof. In all cases of intellectual or moral rapture we find that, unless there be coupled a bodily reverberation of some kind with the mere like acts of integrity performed in Peru. " The Beethoven-rightness of which Gurney then goes on to speak, as something different from the Clementi- rightness (even when the respective pieces are only heard in idea), is prob ably a purely auditory-sensational thing. The Clernenti-rightness also ; only, for reasons impossible to assign, the Clementi form does not give the same sort of purely auditory satisfaction as the Beethoven form, and might better be described perhaps negatively as non-wrong, i.e., free from posi tively unpleasant acoustic quality. In organizations as musical as Mr. Gurney's, purely acoustic form gives so intense a degree of sensible pleas ure that the lower bodily reverberation is of no account. But I repeat that I see nothing in the facts which Mr. Gurney cites, to lead one to believe in an emotion divorced from sensational processes of any kind. THE EMOTIONS. 471 thought of the object and cognition of its quality ; unless we actually laugh at the neatness of the demonstration or witticism ; unless we thrill at the case of justice, or tingle at the act of magnanimity; our state of mind can hardly be called emotional at all. It is in fact a mere intellectual perception of how certain things are to be called — neat, right, witty, generous, and the like. Such a judicial state of mind as this is to be classed among awarenesses of truth; it is a cognitive act. As a matter of fact, however, the moral and intellectual cognitions hardly ever do exist thus unaccompanied. The bodily sounding-board is at work, as careful introspection will show, far more than we usually suppose. Still, where long familiarity with a certain class of effects, even aesthetic ones, has blunted mere emotional excitability as much as it has sharpened taste and judg ment, we do get the intellectual emotion, if such it can be called, pure and undefiled. And the dryness of it, the paleness, the absence of all glow, as it may exist in a thoroughly expert critic's mind, not only shows us what an altogether different thing it is from the ' coarser ' emo tions we considered first, but makes us suspect that almost the entire difference lies in the fact that the bodily sound ing-board, vibrating in the one case, is in the other mute. "Not so very bad" is, in a person of consummate taste, apt to be the highest limit of approving expression. " Rien ne me choque" is said to have been Chopin's superlative of praise of new music. A sentimental layman would feel, and ought to feel, horrified, on being admitted into such a critic's mind, to see how cold, how thin, how void of human significance, are the motives for favor or disfavor that there prevail. The capacity to make a nice spot on the wall will outweigh a picture's whole content ; a foolish trick of words will preserve a poem ; an utterly meaning less fitness of sequence in one musical composition set at naught any amount of * expressiveness ' in another. I remember seeing an English couple sit for more than an hour on a piercing February day in the Academy at Venice before the celebrated ' Assumption ' by Titian ; and when I, after being chased from room to room by the cold, concluded to get into the sunshine as fast as possible 472 PSYCHOLOGY. and let the pictures go, but before leaving drew reverently near to them to learn with what superior forms of suscepti bility they might be endowed, all I overheard was the woman's voice murmuring : " What a deprecatory expression her face wears ! What self-abnegaf ion ! How umvorthy she feels of the honor she is receiving!" Their honest hearts had been kept warm all the time by a glow of spuri ous sentiment that would have fairly made old Titian sick, Mr. Ruskin somewhere makes the (for him terrible) admis sion that religious people as a rule care little for pictures, and that when they do care for them they generally prefer the worst ones to the best. Yes ! in every art, in every science, there is the keen perception of certain relations being right or not, and there is the emotional flush and thrill consequent thereupon. And these are two things, not one. In the former of them it is that experts and masters are at home. The latter accompaniments are bodily commotions that they may hardly feel, but that may be experienced in their fulness by cretins and philistines in whom the critical judgment is at its lowest ebb. The ' marvels ' of Science, about which so much edifying popular literature is written, are apt to be ' caviare ' to the men in the laboratories. And even divine Philosophy itself, which common mortals con sider so * sublime ' an occupation, on account of the vast- ness of its data and outlook, is too apt to the practical philosopher himself to be but a sharpening and tightening business, a matter of ' points,' of screwing down things, of splitting hairs, and of the * intent ' rather than the ' extent ' of conceptions. Very little emotion here ! — except the effort of setting the attention fine, and the feeling of ease and relief (mainly in the breathing apparatus) when the inconsistencies are overcome and the thoughts run smoothly for a while. Emotion and cognition seem then parted even in this last retreat ; and cerebral processes are almost feel- ingless, so far as we can judge, until they summon help from parts below. NO SPECIAL BBAIN-CENTRES FOB EMOTION. If the neural process underlying emotional conscious ness be what I have now sought to prove it, the physi- THE EMOTIONS. 473 ology of the brain becomes a simpler matter than has been hitherto supposed. Sensational, associational, and motor elements are all that the organ need contain. The physi ologists who, during the past few years, have been so in dustriously exploring the brain's functions, have limited their explanations to its cognitive and volitional per formances. Dividing the brain into sensory and motor centres, they have found their division to be exactly paral leled by the analysis made by empirical psychology of the perceptive and volitional parts of the mind into their simplest elements. But the emotions have been so ignored in all these researches that one is tempted to suppose that if these investigators were asked for a theory of them in brain-terms, they would have to reply, either that they had as yet bestowed no thought upon the subject, or that they had found it so difficult to make distinct hypotheses that the matter lay among the problems of the future, only to be taken up after the simpler ones of the present should have been definitively solved. And yet it is even now certain that of two things con cerning the emotions, one must be true. Either separate and special centres, affected to them alone, are their brain- seat, or else they correspond to processes occurring in the motor and sensory centres already assigned, or in others like them, not yet known. If the former be the case, we must deny the view that is current, and hold the cortex to be something more than the surface of ' projection ' for every sensitive spot and every muscle in the body. If the latter be the case, we must ask whether the emotional process in the sensory or motor centre be an altogether peculiar one, or whether it resembles the ordinary perceptive pro cesses of which those centres are already recognized to be the seat. Now if the theory I have defended be true, the latter alternative is all that it demands. Supposing the cortex to contain parts, liable to be excited by changes in each special sense-organ, in each portion of the skin, in each muscle, each joint, and each viscus, and to contain absolutely nothing else, we still have a scheme capable of representing the process of the emotions. An object falls on a sense-organ, affects a cortical part, and is perceived ; 474 PSYCHOLOGY. or else the latter, excited inwardly, gives rise to an idea of the same object. Quick as a flash, the reflex currents pass down through their preordained channels, alter the con dition of muscle, skin, and viscus ; and these alterations, perceived, like the original object, in as many portions of the cortex, combine with it in consciousness and transform it from an object-simply-apprehended into an object- emotionally-felt. No new principles have to be invoked, nothing postulated beyond the ordinary reflex circuits, and the local centres admitted in one shape or another by all to exist. EMOTIONAL DIFFERENCES BETWEEN INDIVIDUALS. The revivability in memory of the emotions, like that of all the feelings of the lower senses, is very small. We can remember that we underwent grief or rapture, but not just how the grief or rapture felt. This difficult ideal reviva bility is, however, more than compensated in the case of the emotions by a very easy actual revivability. That is, we can produce, not remembrances of the old grief or rapture, but new griefs and raptures, by summoning up a lively thought of their exciting cause. The cause is now only an idea, but this idea produces the same organic irradiations, or almost the same, which were produced by its original, so that the emotion is again a reality. We have ' recaptured ' it. Shame, love, and anger are particu larly liable to be thus revived by ideas of their object. Professor Bain admits * that " in their strict character of emotion proper, they [the emotions] have the minimum of revivability ; but being always incorporated with the sensa tions of the higher senses, they share in the superior reviv ability of sights and sounds." But he fails to point out that the revived sights and sounds may be ideal without ceasing to be distinct ; whilst the emotion, to be distinct, must become real again. Prof. Bain seems to forget that an * ideal emotion ' and a real emotion prompted by an ideal object are two very different things. * In his chapter on ' Ideal Emotion, ' to which the reader is referred for farther details on this subject. THE EMOTIONS. 476 An emotional temperament on the one hand, and a lively imagination for objects and circumstances on the other, are thus the conditions, necessary and sufficient, for an abundant emotional life. No matter how emotional the temperament may be, if the imagination be poor, the oc casions for touching off the emotional trains will fail to be realized, and the life will be pro tanto cold and dry. This is perhaps a reason why it may be better that a man of thought should not have too strong a visualizing power. He is less likely to have his trains of meditation disturbed by emotional interruptions. It will be remembered that Mr. Galton found the members of the Royal Society and of the French Academy of Sciences to be below par in visual izing power. If I may speak of myself, I am far less able to visualize now, at the age of 46, than in my earlier years ; and I am strongly inclined to believe that the relative slug gishness of my emotional life at present is quite as much connected with this fact as it is with the invading torpor of hoary eld, or with the omnibus-horse routine of settled pro fessional and domestic life. I say this because I occasion ally have a flash of the old stronger visual imagery, and I notice that the emotional commentary, so to call it, is then liable to become much more acute than is its present wont. Charcot's patient, whose case is given above on p. 58 ff., complained of his incapacity for emotional feeling after his optical images - —re gone. His mother's death, which in former times would have wrung his heart, left him quite cold ; largely, as he himself suggests, because he could form no definite visual image of the event, and of the effect of the loss on the rest of the family at home. One final generality about the emotions remains to be noted : They blunt themselves by repetition more rapidly than any other sort of feeling. This is due not only to the gen eral law of ' accommodation ' to their stimulus which we saw to obtain of all feelings whatever, but to the peculiar fact that the « diffusive wave ' of reflex effects tends always to become more narrow. It seems as if it were essentially meant to be a provisional arrangement, on the basis of which precise and determinate reactions might arise. The more we exercise ourselves at anything, the fewer muscles 476 PSYCHOLOGY. we employ ; and just so, the oftener we meet an object, the more definitely we think and behave about it ; and the less is the organic perturbation to which it gives rise. The first time we saw it we could perhaps neither act nor think at all, and had no reaction but organic perturbation. The emotions of startled surprise, wonder, or curiosity were the result. Now we look on with absolutely no emotion.* This tendency to economy in the nerve-paths through which our sensations and ideas discharge, is the basis of all growth in efficiency, readiness, and skill. Where would the general, the surgeon, the presiding chairman, be, if their nerve-cur rents kept running down into their viscera, instead of keep ing up amid their convolutions ? But what they gain for prac tice by this law, they lose, it must be confessed, for feeling. For the world-worn and experienced man, the sense of pleasure which he gets from the free and powerful flow of thoughts, overcoming obstacles as they arise, is the only compensation for that freshness of the heart which he once enjoyed. This free and powerful flow means that brain- paths of association and memory have more and more organized themselves in him, and that through them the stimulus is drafted off into nerves which lead merely to the writing finger or the speaking tongue. t The trains of intel lectual association, the memories, the logical relations, may, * Those feelings which Prof. Bain calls ' emotions of relativity,' excite ment of novelty, wonder, rapture of freedom, sense of power, hardly survive any repetition of the experience. But as the text goes on to ex plain, and as Goethe as quoted by Prof. Hoffding says, this is because " the so*ul is inwardly grown larger without knowing it, and can no longer be filled by that first sensation. The man thinks that he has lost, but really he has gained. What he has lost in rapture, he has gained in inward growth." " It is," as Prof. Hoffding himself adds, in a beautiful figure of speech, " with our virgin feelings, as with the first breath drawn by the new-born child, in which the lung expands itself so that it can never be emptied to the same degree again. No later breath can feel just like that first one." On this whole subject of emotional blunting, compare Hoffding's Psychologic, vi. E., and Bain's Emotions and Will, chapter iv. of the first part. f M. Fr. Paulhan, in a little work full of accurate observations of de tail (Les Phenomeues Affectifs et les Lois de leur Apparition), seems to me rather to turn the truth upside down by his formula that emotions are due to an inhibition of impulsive tendencies. One kind of emotion, namely, uneasiness, annoyance, distress, does occur when any definite impulsive tendency is checked, and all of M. P.'s illustrations are drawn from this THE EMOTIONS. 477 however, be voluminous in the extreme. Past emotions may be among the things remembered. The more of all these trains an object can set going in us, the richer our cognitive intimacy with it is. This cerebral sense of rich ness seems itself to be a source of pleasure, possibly even apart from the euphoria which from time to time comes up from respiratory organs. If there be such a thing as a purely spiritual emotion, I should be inclined to restrict it to this cerebral sense of abundance and ease, this feeling, as Sir W. Hamilton would call it, of unimpeded and not overstrained activity of thought. Under ordinary conditions, it is a fine and serene but not an excited state of consciousness. In certain intoxications it becomes exciting, and it may be intensely exciting. I can hardly imagine a more frenzied excitement than that which goes with the consciousness of seeing absolute truth, which characterizes the coming to from nitrous-oxide drunken ness. Chloroform, ether, and alcohol all produce this deepening sense of insight into truth ; and with all of them it may be a ' strong ' emotion ; but then there also coine with it all sorts of • strange bodily feelings and changes in the incoming sensibilities. I cannot see my way to affirming that the emotion is independent of these. I will concede, however, that if its independence is anywhere to be main tained, these theoretic raptures seem the place at which to begin the defence. THE GENESIS OF THE VARIOUS EMOTIONS. On a former page (pp. 453-4) I said that two questions, and only two, are important, if we regard the emotions as constituted by feelings due to the diffusive wave. (1) What special diffusive effects do the various special ob jective and subjective experiences excite ? and (2) How come they to excite them ? The works on physiognomy and expression are all of them attempts to answer question 1. As is but natural, the sort. The other emotions are themselves primary impulsive tendencies, of a diffusive sort (involving, as M. P. rightly says, a multiplicite des phe- nomdnes); and just in proportion as more and more of these multiple ten dencies are checked, and replaced by some few narrow forms of discharge, does the original emotion tend to disappear. 478 PSYCHOLOGY. effects upon the face have received the most careful atten tion. The reader who wishes details additional to those given above on pp. 443-7 is referred to the works men tioned in the note below. * As regards question 2, some little progress has of recent years been made in answering it. Two things are certain : a. The facial muscles of expression are not given us simply for expression's sake ;f b. Each muscle is not affected to some one emotion ex clusively, as certain writers have thought. Some movements of expression can be accounted for as weakened repetitions of movements which formerly (when they were stronger) were of utility to the subject. Others are similarly weakened repetitions of movements which under other conditions were physiologically necessary effects. Of the latter reactions the respiratory disturbances in anger and fear might be taken as examples — organic reminiscences, as it were, reverberations in imagination of the blowings of the man making a series of combative efforts, of the pantings of one in precipitate flight. Such at least is a suggestion made by Mr. Spencer which has found approval. And he also was the first, so far as I know, to suggest that other movements in anger and fear could be explained by the nascent excitation of formerly useful acts. " To have in a slight degree," he says, " such psychical states as ac company the reception of wounds, and are experienced during flight, is to be in a state of what we call fear. And to have in a slight degree such psychical states as the processes of catching, killing, and eating imply, is to have the desires to catch, kill, and eat. That the pro pensities to the acts are nothing else than nascent excitations of the * A list of the older writings on the subject is given in Mantegazza's work, La Physionomie et PExpression, chap, i; others in Darwin's first chapter. Bell's Anatomy of Expression, Mosso's La Paura, Pidcrit's WissenschaftJiches System der Mimik und Physiognomik, Duchenne's Mecanisme de la Physionomie Humaine, are, besides Lange and Darwin, the most useful works with which I am acquainted. Compare also Sully: Sensation and Intuition, chap. n. f One must remember, however, that just in so far forth as sexual selection may have played a part in determining the human organism, selec tion of expressive faces must have increased the average mobility of the hmruin countenance. THE EMOTIONS. 479 psychic-ill state involved in the acts, is proved by the natural language of the propensities. Fear, when strong, expresses itself in cries, in efforts to escape, in palpitations, in tremblings ; and these are just the manifestations that go along with an actual suffering of the evil feared. The destructive passion is shown in a general tension of the muscular system, in gnashing of teeth and protrusion of the claws, in dilated eyes and nostrils, in growls ; and these are weaker forms of the actions that accompany the killing of prey. To such objective evidences every one can add subjective evidences. Every one can testify that the psychical state called fear consists of mental representations of certain painful results ; and that the one called anger consists of mental representa tions of the actions and impressions which would occur while inflicting some kind of pain." * About i'ear I shall have more to say presently. Mean while the principle of revival in weakened form of reactions meful in more violent dealings with the object inspiring the emotion, has found many applications. So slight a symptom as the snarl or sneer, the one-sided uncovering of the upper teeth, is accounted for by Darwin as a survival from the time when our ancestors had large canines, and unfleshed them (as dogs now do) for attack. Similarly the raising of the eyebrows in outward attention, the opening of the mouth in astonishment, come, according to the same author, from the utility of these movements in extreme cases. The raising of the eyebrows goes with the opening of the eye for better vision ; the opening of the mouth with the in tensest listening, and with the rapid catching of the breath which precedes muscular effort. The distention of the nostrils in anger is interpreted by Spencer as an echo of the way in which our ancestors had to breathe when, during combat, their " mouth was filled up by a part of an antagonist's body that had been seized (!)." The trembling of fear is supposed by Mantegazza to be for the sake of warming the blood(!). The reddening of the face and neck is called by Wundt a compensatory arrangement for relieving the brain of the blood-pressure which the simultaneous excitement of the heart brings with it. The effusion of tears is explained both by this author and by Darwin to be a blood-with drawing agency of a similar sort. The contraction of the muscles around the eyes, of which the primitive use is to *Psychol.,§213. 480 PSYCHOLOGY. protect those organs from being too much gorged with blood during the screaming fits of infancy, survives in adult life in the shape of the frown, which instantly comes over the brow when anything difficult or displeasing pre sents itself either to thought or action. ' ' As the habit of contracting the brows has been followed by infants during innumerable generations, at the commencement of every crying or screaming fit," says Darwin, " it has become firmly associated with the incipient sense of something distressing or disagreeable. ' Hence, under similar circumstances, it would be apt to be continued during maturity, although never then developed, into a crying fit. Screaming or weeping begins to be voluntarily restrained at an early period of life, whereas frowning is hardly ever restrained at any age."* The intermittent expirations which constitute laughter have, according to Dr. Hecker, the purpose of counteract ing the anaemia of the brain, which he supposes to be brought about by the action of the joyous or comic stimulus upon the vaso- motor nerves, t A smile is the weak vestige of a laugh. The tight closure of the mouth in all effort is useful for retaining the air in the lungs so as to fix the chest and give a firm basis of insertion for the muscles of the flanks. Accordingly, we see the lips compress themselves upon every slight occasion of resolve. The blood-pressure has to be high during the sexual embrace ; hence the palpi- * Weeping in childhood is almost as regular a symptom of anger as it is of grief, which would account (on Darwin's principles) for the frown of anger. Mr. Spencer has an account of the angry frown as having arisen through the survival of the fittest, by its utility in keeping the sun out of one's eyes when engaged in mortal combat (!). (Principles of Psychology, n. 546.) Professor Mosso objects to any explanation of the frown by its utility for vision, that it is coupled, during emotional excitement, with a dilatation of the pupil which is very unfavorable for distinct vision, and that this ought to have been weeded out by natural selection, if natural selection had the power to fix the frown (see La Paura, chap. ix. § vi). Unfortunately this very able author speaks as if all the emotions affected the pupil in the same way. Fear certainly does make it dilate. But Gratiolet is quoted by Darwin and others as saying that the pupils con tract in anger. I have made no observations of my own on the point, and Mosso 's earlier paper on the pupil (Turin, 1875) I have not seen. I must repeat, with Darwin, that we need more minute observations on this subject. •f Physiologic u. Psychologic des Lachens und des Komischen (Berlin, 1873), pp. 13-15. THE EMOTIONS. 481 tations, and hence also the tendency to caressing action, which accompanies tender emotion in its fainter forms. Other examples might be given ; but these are quite enough to show the scope of the principle of revival of useful action in weaker form. Another principle, to which Darwin perhaps hardly does sufficient justice, may be called the principle of reacting similarly to analogous-feeling stimuli. There is a whole vocabulary of descriptive adjectives common to im pressions belonging to different sensible spheres — experi ences of all classes are siceet, impressions of all classes rich or solid, sensations of all classes sharp. Wundt and Piderit accordingly explain many of our most expressive reactions upon moral causes as symbolic gustatory movements. As soon as any experience arises which has an affinity with the feeling of sweet, or bitter, or sour, the same movements are executed which would result from the taste in point.* " All the states of mind which language designates by the metaphors bitter, harsh, sweet, combine themselves, there fore, with the corresponding mimetic movements of the mouth." Certainly the emotions of disgust and satisfac tion do express themselves in this mimetic way. Disgust is an incipient regurgitation or retching, limiting its expres sion often to the grimace of the lips and nose ; satisfaction goes with a sucking smile, or tasting motion of the lips. In Mantegazza's loose if learned work, the attempt is made, much less successfully, to bring in the eye and ear as ad ditional sources of symbolically expressive reaction. The ordinary gesture of negation — among us, moving the head about its axis from side to side — is a reaction originally used by babies to keep disagreeables from getting into their mouth, and may be observed in perfection in any nursery. t * These movements are explained Ideologically, in the first instance, by the efforts which the tongue is forced to make to adapt itself to the better perception or avoidance of the sapid body. (Cf. Physiol. Psych., n. 423.) f Professor Henle derives the negative wag of the head from an incipi ent shudder, and remarks how fortunate is the abbreviation, as when a lady declines a partner in the ballroom. The clapping of the hands for ap plause he explains as a symbolic abridgment of an embrace. The pro- 482 PSYCHOLOGY. It is now evoked where the stimulus is only an unwelcome idea. Similarly the nod forward in affirmation is after the analogy of taking food into the mouth. The connection of the expression of moral or social disdain or dislike, es pecially in women, with movements having a perfectly defi nite original olfactory function, is too obvious for comment. Winking is the effect of any threatening surprise, not only of what puts the eyes in danger ; and a momentary aver sion of the eyes is very apt to be one's first symptom of re sponse to an unexpectedly unwelcome proposition. — These may suffice as examples of movements expressive from analogy. But if certain of our emotional reactions can be ex plained by the two principles invoked — and the reader will himself have felt how conjectural and fallible in some of the instances the explanation is — there remain many reac tions which cannot so be explained at all, and these we must write down for the present as purely idiopathic effects of the stimulus. Amongst them are the effects on the viscera and internal glands, the dryness of the mouth and diar rhoea and nausea of fear, the ]iver-disturbances which some times produce jaundice after excessive rage, the urinary secretion of sanguine excitement, and the bladder-contrac tion of apprehension, the gaping of expectancy, the * lump in the throat' of grief, the tickling there and the swallow ing of embarrassment, the * precordial ' anxiety ' of dread, the changes in the pupil, the various sweatings of the skin, cold or hot, local or general, and its flushings, together with other symptoms which probably exist but are too hidden to have been noticed or named. It seems as if even the changes of blood-pressure and heart-beat during emo tional excitement might, instead of being teleologically de termined, prove to be purely mechanical or physiological outpourings through the easiest drainage-channels — the pneumogastrics and sympathetic nerves happening under ordinary circumstances to be such channels. trusion of the lips (der prufetide Zug) which goes with all sorts of dubious and questioning states of mind is derived by Dr. Piderit from the tasting movement which we can see on any one's mouth when deciding whether a wine is good or not. THE EMOTIONS. 483 Mr. Spencer argues that the smallest muscles must be such channels ; and instances the tail in dogs, cats, and birds, the ears in horses, the crest in parrots, the face and fingers in man, as the first organs to be moved by emotional stimuli.* This principle (if it be one) would apply still more easily to the muscles of the smaller arteries (though not exactly to the heart) ; whilst the great variability of the circulatory symptoms would also suggest that they are de termined by causes into which utility does not enter. The quickening of the heart lends itself, it is true, rather easily to explanation by inherited habit, organic memory of more violent excitement ; and Darwin speaks in favor of this view (see his Expression, etc., pp. 74-5). But, on the other hand, we have so many cases of reaction which are indisputably pathological, as we may say, and which could never be serviceable or derived from what was serviceable, that I think we should be cautious about pushing our ex planations of the varied heart-beat too far in the teleological direction. Trembling, which is found in many excitements besides that of terror, is, pace Mr. Spencer and Sig. Mante- gazza, quite pathological. So are terror's other strong symptoms. Professor Mosso, as the total result of his study, writes as follows : " We have seen that the graver the peril becomes, the more do the reactions which are positively harmful to the animal prevail in number and in efficacy. We already saw that the trembling and the palsy make it incapable of flight or defence ; we have also convinced ourselves that in the most decisive moments of danger we are less able to see [or to think] than when we are tranquil. In face of such facts we must admit that the phenomena of fear cannot all be accounted for by ' selection.' Their extreme degrees are morbid phenomena which show an imperfec tion in the organism. We might almost say that Nature had not been * Loc. cit. % 497. Why a dog's face-muscles are not more mobile than they are Mr. Spencer fails to explain, as also why different stimuli should innervate these small muscles in such different ways, if easy drainage be the only principle involved. Charles Bell accounted for the special part played by the facial muscles in expression by their being accessory mi\scle» of respiration, governed by nerves whose origin is close to the respiratory centre in the medulla oblongata. They are an adjuvant of voice, and like it their function is communication. (See Bell's Anatomy of Expression, Appendix by Alexander Shaw.) 484 PSYCHOLOGY. able to frame a substance which should be excitable enough to com pose the brain and spinal marrow, and yet which should not be so ex cited by exceptional stimulation as to overstep in its reactions those physiological bounds which are useful to the conservation of the crea ture."* Professor Bain, if I mistake not, had long previously commented upon fear in a similar way. Mr. Darwin accounts for many emotional expressions by what he calls the principle of antithesis. In virtue of this principle, if a certain stimulus prompted a certain set of movements, then a contrary-feeling stimulus would prompt exactly the opposite movements, although these might otherwise have neither utility nor significance. It is in this wise that Darwin explains the expression of impo tence, raised eyebrows, and shrugged shoulders, dropped arms and open palms, as being the antithesis of the frown ing brow, the thrown-back shoulders, and clenched fists of rage, which is the emotion of power. No doubt a certain number of movements can be formulated under this law ; but whether it expresses a causal principle is more than doubtful. It has been by most critics considered the least successful of Darwin's speculations on this subject. To sum up, we see the reason for a few emotional re actions ; for others a possible species of reason may be guessed ; but others remain for which no plausible reason can even be conceived. These may be reactions which are purely mechanical results of the way in which our nervous centres are framed, reactions which, although permanent in us now, may be called accidental as far as their origin goes. In fact, in an organism as complex as the nervous system there must be many such reactions, incidental to others evolved for utility's sake, but Avhich would never themselves have been evolved independently, for any utility they might possess. Sea-sickness, the love of music, of the various intoxicants, nay, the entire aesthetic life of man, shall have to trace to this accidental origin, f It would be foolish to suppose that none of the reactions called emo tional could have arisen in this gwcm'-accidental way. * La Paura, Appendice, p. 295. f See below, p. 627. THE EMOTIONS. 485 This is all I have to say about the emotions. If one should seek to name each particular one of them of which the human heart is the seat, it is plain that the limit to their number would lie in the introspective vocabulary of the seeker, each race of men having found names for some shade of feeling which other races have left undiscrimi nated. If then we should seek to break the emotions, thus enumerated, into groups, according to their affinities, it is again plain that all sorts of groupings would be pos sible, according as we chose this character or that as a basis, and that all groupings would be equally real and true. The only question would be, does this grouping or that suit our purpose best? The reader may then class the emotions as he will, as sad or joyous, sthenic or asthenic, natural or acquired, inspired by animate or inani mate things, formal or material, sensuous or ideal, direct or reflective, egoistic or non-egoistic, retrospective, pros pective or immediate, organismally or environmentally initiated, or what more besides. All these are divisions which have been actually proposed. Each of them has its merits, and each one brings together some emotions which the others keep apart. For a fuller account, and for other classificatory schemes, I refer to the Appendix to Bain's Emotions and the Will, and to Mercier's, Stanley's, and Bead's articles on the Emotions, in Mind, vols. ix, x, and XL In vol. ix. p. 421 there is also an article by the lamented Edmund Gurney in criticism of the view which in this chapter I continue to defend. CHAPTEE XXVI.* WILL. DESIKE, wish, will, are states of mind which everyone knows, and which no definition can make plainer. We de sire to feel, to have, to do, all sorts of things which at the moment are not felt, had, or done. If with the desire there goes a sense that attainment is not possible, we simply wish ; but if we believe that the end is in our power, we will that the desired feeling, having, or doing shall be real ; and real it presently becomes, either immediately upon the willing or after certain preliminaries have been fulfilled. The only ends which follow immediately upon our will ing seem to be movements of our own bodies. Whatever feelings and havings we may will to get, come in as results of preliminary movements which we make for the purpose-^ This fact is too familiar to need illustration; so that we may start with the proposition that the only direct outward effects of our will are bodily movements. The mechanism of production of these voluntary movements is what befalls us to study now. The subject involves a good many sepa rate points which it is difficult to arrange in any continu ous logical order. I will treat of them successively in the mere order of convenience ; trusting that at the end the reader will gain a clear and connected view. The movements we have studied hitherto have been automatic and reflex, and (on the first occasion of their per formance, at any rate) unforeseen by the agent. The move-i ments to the study of which we now address ourselves,! being desired and intended beforehand, are of course donej * Parts of this chapter have appeared in an essay called " The Feeling of Effort," published in the Anniversary Memoirs of the Boston Society of Natural History, 1880 ; and parts in Scribner's Magazine for Feb. 1888. 486 WILL. 487 with full prevision of what they are to be. It follows from this that voluntary movements must be secondary, not primary functions of our organism. This is the first point to under stand in the psychology of Volition. Keflex, instinctive, and emotional movements are all primary performances. The nerve-centres are so organized that certain stimuli pull the trigger of certain explosive parts ; and a creature going through one of these explosions for the first time under goes an entirely novel experience. The other day I was standing at a railroad station with a little child, when an express-train went thundering by. The child, who was near the edge of the platform, started, winked, had his breathing convulsed, turned pale, burst out crying, and ran frantically towards me and hid his face. I have no doubt that this youngster was almost as much astonished by his own behavior as he was by the train, and more than I was, who stood by. Of course if such a reaction has many times occurred we learn what to expect of ourselves, and can then foresee our conduct, even though it remain as involuntary and uncontrollable as it was before. But if, in voluntary action properly so-called, the act must be foreseen, it fol-| lows that no creature not endowed with divinatory power! can perform an act voluntarily for the first time. Well, we are no more endowed with prophetic vision of what move ments lie in our power, than we are endowed with pro phetic vision of what sensations we are capable of receiving. As we must wait for the sensations to be given us, so we must wait for the movements to be performed involun tarily,* before we can frame ideas of what either of these things are. We learn all our possibilities by the way of experience. When a particular movement, having once occurred in a random, reflex, or involuntary way, has left an image of itself in the memory, then the movement can be desired again, proposed as an end, and deliberately willed. But it is impossible to see how it could be willed before. * I am abstracting at present for simplicity's sake, and so as to keep to the elements of the matter, from the learning of acts by seeing others do them. 488 PSYCHOLOGY. A supply of ideas of the various movements that are possible^ left in the memory by experiences of their involuntary perform-} ance is thus the first prerequisite of the voluntary life. Now the same movement involuntarily performed may leave many different kinds of ideas of itself in the memory. If performed by another person, we of course see it, or we feel it if the moving part strikes another part of our own body. Similarly we have an auditory image of its effects if it produces sounds, as for example when it is one of the movements made in vocalization, or in playing on a musical instrument. All these remote effects of the movement, as we may call them, are also produced by movements which we ourselves perform ; and they leave innumerable ideas in our mind by which we distinguish each movement from the rest. It looks distinct ; it feels distinct to some distant part of the body which it strikes ; or it sounds dis tinct. These remote effects would then, rigorously speak ing, suffice to furnish the mind with the supply of ideas required. But in addition to these impressions upon remote or gans of sense, we have, whenever we perform a movement ourselves, another set of impressions, those, namely, which come up from the parts that are actually moved. These kinwsthetic impressions, as Dr. Bastian has called them, are so many resident effects of the motion. Not only are our muscles supplied with afferent as well as with efferent nerves, but the tendons, the ligaments, the articular sur faces, and the skin about the joints are all sensitive, and, being stretched and squeezed in ways characteristic of each particular movement, give us as many distinctive feelings as there are mo^ ements possible to perform. It is by these resident impressions that we are made conscious of passive movements — movements communicated to our limbs by others. If you lie with closed eyes, and another person noiselessly places your arm or leg in any arbitrarily chosen attitude, you receive an accurate feeling of what attitude it is, and can immediately reproduce it yourself in the arm or leg of the opposite side. Similarly a man waked suddenly from sleep in the dark is aware of how he finds himself lying. At least this is what happens WILL. 489 the nervous apparatus is normal. But in cases of disease we sometimes find that the resident impressions do not normally excite the centres, and that then the sense of attitude is lost. It is only recently that pathologists have begun to study these anaesthesias with the delicacy which they require ; and we have doubtless yet a great deal to learn about them. The skin may be anaesthetic, and the muscles may not feel the cramp-like pain which is pro duced by faradic currents sent through them, and yet the sense of passive movement may be retained. It seems, in fact, to persist more obstinately than the other forms of sensibility, for cases are comparatively common in which all the other feelings in the limb but this one of attitude are lost. In Chapter XX I have tried to make it appear that the articular surfaces are probably the most important source of the resident kinaesthetic feelings. But the determination of their special organ is indifferent to our present quest. It is enough to know that the existence of these feelings cannot be denied. When the feelings of passive movement as well as all the other feelings of a limb are lost, we get such results as are given in the following account by Professor A. Strum- pell of his wonderful anaesthetic boy, whose only sources of feeling were the right eye and the left ear : * ' ' Passive movements could be imprinted on all the extremities to the greatest extent, without attracting the patient's notice. Only in violent forced hyperextension of the joints, especially of the knees, there arose a dull vague feeling of strain, but this was seldom precisely localized. We have often, after bandaging the eyes of the patient, carried him about the room, laid him on a table, given to his arms and legs the most fantastic and apparently the most inconvenient attitudes, without his having a suspicion of it. The expression of astonishment in his face, when all at once the removal of the handkerchief revealed his situation, is indescribable in words. Only when his head was made to hang away down he immediately spoke of dizziness, but could not assign its ground. Later he sometimes inferred from the sounds con nected with the manipulation that something special was being done with him .... He had no feelings of muscular fatigue. If, with his eyes shut, we told him to raise his arm and to keep it up, he did so without trouble. After one or two minutes, however, the arm began to *Deutsches Arcniv f. Klin. Medicin, xxn. 321. 490 PSYCHOLOGY. tremble and sink without his being aware of it. He asserted still his ability to keep it up. ... Passively holding still his fingers did not affect him. He thought constantly that he opened and shut his hand, whereas it was really fixed.'1 Or we read of cases like this : " Voluntary movements cannot be estimated the moment the patient ceases to take note of them by his eyes. Thus, after having made him close his eyes, if one asks him to move one of his limbs either wholly or in part, he does it but cannot tell whether the effected movement is '.large or small, strong or weak, or even if it has taken place at all. And when he opens his eyes after moving his leg from right to left, for example, he declares that he had a very inexact notion of the extent of the effected movement. ... If, having the intention of executing a certain movement, I prevent him, he does riot perceive it, and supposes the limb to have taken the position he intended to give it." * Or this : "The patient, when his eyes were closed in the middle of an unpractised movement, remained with the extremity in the position it had when the eyes closed and did not complete the movement properly. Then after some oscillations the limb gradually sank by reason of its weight (the sense of fatigue being absent). Of this the patient was not aware, and wondered, when he opened his eyes, at the altered position of his limb." f A similar condition can be readily reproduced experi mentally in many hypnotic subjects. All that is needed is to tell a suitably predisposed person during the hypnotic trance that he cannot feel his limb, and he will be quite unaware of the attitudes into which you may throw it.J All these cases, whether spontaneous or experimental, show the absolute need of guiding sensations of some kind for the successful carrying out of a concatenated series of movements. It is, in fact, easy to see that, just as where the chain of movements is automatic (see above, Vol. I. p. 116\ each later movement of the chain has to be discharged by the impression which the next earlier one makes in being * Landry : Memoire snr la Paralysie du Sens Musculaire, Gazette des Hdpitaux, 1855, p. 270. f Takacs : Ueber die Verspatung der Emptindungsleitung, Archiv fttr Psychiatrie, Bd. x. Heft 2, p. 533. Concerning all such cases see the re marks made above on pp. 205-6. t Proceedings of American Soc. for Psychical Research, p. 95. WILL. 491 executed, so also, where the chain is voluntary, we need to know at each movement just where we are in it, if we are to will intelligently what the next link shall be. A man with no feeling of his movements might lead off never so well, and yet be sure to get lost soon and go astray.* But patients like those described, who get no kinaesthetic impressions, can still be guided by the sense of sight Thus Striimpell says of his boy : ' ' One could always observe how his eye was directed first to the object held before him, then to his own arm; and how it never ceased * In reality the movement cannot even be started correctly in some cases without the kinaesthetic impression. Thus Dr. Striimpell relates how turning over the boy's hand made him bend the little finger instead of the forefinger, when his eye was closed. " Ordered to point, e.g., towards the left with his left arm, the arm was usually raised straight forward, and then wandered about in groping uncertainty, sometimes getting the right position and then leaving it again. Similarly with the lower limbs. If the patient, lying in bed, had, immediately after the tying of his eyes, to lay the left leg over the right, it often happened that he moved it farther over towards the left, and that it lay over the side of the bed in apparently the most intolerably-uncomfortable position. The turning of the head, too. from right to left, or towards certain objects known to the patient, only ensued correctly when the patient, immediately before his eye was bandaged, specially refreshed his perception as to what the required movement was to be." In another anaesthetic of Dr. Strumpell's (described in the same essay) the arm could not be moved at all unless the eyes were opened, however energetic the volition. The variations in these hysteric cases are great. Some patients cannot move the anaesthetic part at all when the eyes are closed. Others move it perfectly well, and can even write continuous sentences with the anaesthetic hand. The causes of such differences are as yet incompletely unexplored. M. Binet suggests (Revue Philosophique, xxv. 478) that in those who cannot move the hand at all the sensation of light is required as a 'dynamogenic ' agent (see above, p 377); and that in those who can move it skilfully the anaesthesia is only a pseudo-insensi bility and that the limb is in reality governed by a dissociated or secondary consciousness. This latter explanation is certainly correct. Professor G. E. Milller (Pfltiger's Archiv, XLV. 90) invokes the fact of individual differences of imagination to account for the cases who cannot write at all. Their kinaesthetic images properly so called may be weak, he says, and their optical images insufficiently powerful to supplement them without a ' rillip ' from sensation. Janet's observation that hysteric anaesthesias may carry amnesias with them would perfectly legitimate Muller's supposition. What we now want is a minute examination of the individual cases. Meanwhile Binet 's article above referred to, and Bastian's paper in Brain for April 1887, contain important discussions of the question. In a later note I shall return to the subject again (see p. 520). 492 PSYCHOLOGY. to follow the latter during its entire movement. All his voluntary movements took place under the unremitting lead of the eye, which as an indispensable guide, was never untrue to its functions." So in the Landry case : "With his eyes open, he easily opposes the thumb to each of the other fingers ; with his eyes closed, the movement oil opposition occurs, but the thumb only by chance meets the finger which it seeks. With his eyes open he is able, without hesitation, to bring his two hands together ; but when his eyes are closed his hands seek one another in space, and only meet by chance." In Charles Bell's well-known old case of anaesthesia the Tvoman could only hold her baby safely in her arms so long as she looked at it. I have myself reproduced a similar condition in two hypnotic subjects whose arm and hand were made anaesthetic without being paralyzed. They could write their names when looking, but not when their eyes were closed. The modern mode of teaching deaf mutes to articulate consists in making them attentive to certain laryngeal, labial, thoracic, and other sensations, the repro duction of which becomes a guide to their vocalization. Normally it is the remoter sensations which we receive by the ear which keep us from going astray in our speech. The phenomena of aphasia show this to be the usual case.* This is perhaps all that need be said about the existence of passive sensations of movement and their in dispensable - ness for our voluntary activity. We may consequently set it down as certain that, whether or no there be anything else in the mind at the moment when we consciously will a certain actt a mental conception made up of memory-images of these sensa tions, defining which special act it is, must be there. Now is there anything else in the mind when we wiU to do an act ? We must proceed in this chapter from the simpler to the more complicated cases. My first thesis accordingly is, that there need be nothing else, and that in perfectly simple vol- * Professor Beaunis found that the accuracy with which a certain tenor sang was not lost when his vocal cords were made anaesthetic by cocain. He concludes that the guiding sensations here are resident in the laryngeal muscles themselves. They are much more probably in the ear. (Beaunis, Les Sensations Internes (1889), p. 253). WILL. 493 untary acts there is nothing else, in the mind but the kincesthetic. idea, thus defined, of ivhat the act is to be. A powerful tradition in Psychology will have it that something additional to these images of passive sensation is essential to the mental determination of a voluntary act. There must, of course, be a special current of energy going out from the brain into the appropriate muscles during the act ; and this outgoing current (it is supposed) must have in each particular case a feeling sui generis attached to it, or else (it is said) the mind could never tell which particular current, the current to this muscle or the current to that one, was the right one to use. This feeling of the current of out going energy has received from Wundt the name of the feeling of inner vation. I disbelieve in its existence, and must proceed to criticise the notion of it, at what I fear may to some prove tedious length. At first sight there is something extremely plausible in the feeling of innervation. The passive feelings of move ment with which we have hitherto been dealing all come after the movement's performance. But wherever a move ment is difficult and precise, we become, as a matter of fact, acutely aware in advance of the amount and direction of energy which it is to involve. One has only to play ten pins or billiards, or throw a ball, to catch his will in the act, as it were, of balancing tentatively its possible efforts, and ideally rehearsing various muscular contractions nearly correct, until it gets just the right one before it, when it says ' Now go ! ' This premonitory weighing feels so much like a succession of tentative sallyings forth of power into the outer world, followed by correction just in time to avoid the irrevocable deed, that the notion that outgoing nerve- currents rather than mere vestiges of former passive sensi bility accompany it, is a most natural one to entertain. We find accordingly that most authors have taken the existence of feelings of innervation as a matter of course. Bain, Wundt, Helmholtz, and Mach defend them most explicitly. But in spite of the authority which such writers deservedly wield, I cannot help thinking that they are in this instance wrong,— that the discharge into the motor nerves is insentient, and that all our ideas of movement, in- 494 PSYCHOLOGY. eluding those of tlie effort wliicli it requires, as well as those of its direction, its extent, its strength, and its velocity, are images of peripheral sensations, either ' remote,' or resident in the moving parts, or in other parts which sympathetically act with them in consequenceof the ' diffusive wave.' A priori, as I shall show, there is no reason why there should be a consciousness of the motor discharge, and there is a reason why there should not be such a consciousness. The presumption is thus against the existence of the feeling of innervation ; and the burden of proving it falls upon those who believe in it. If the positive empirical evidence which they offer prove also insufficient, then their case falls to the ground, and the feeling in question must be ruled out of court. In the first place, then, let me show that the assumption of the feeling of innervation is unnecessary. I cannot help suspecting that the scholastic prejudice that ' the effect must be already in some way contained in the cause ' has had something to do with making psychologists so ready to admit the feeling of innervation. The outgoing current being the effect, what psychic antecedent could contain or prefigure it better than a feeling of it ? But if we take a wide view, and consider the psychic ante cedents of our activities at large, we see that the scholastic maxim breaks down everywhere, and that its verification in this instance would rather violate than illustrate the general rule. In the diffusive wave, in reflex action, and in emotional expression, the movements which are the effects are in no manner contained by anticipation in the stimuli which are their cause. The latter are subjective sensations or objective perceptions, which do not in the slightest degree resemble or prefigure the movements. But we get them, and, presto ! there the movements are ! They are knocked out of us, they surprise us. It is just cause for wonder, as our chapter on Instinct has shown us; that such bodily consequences should follow such men tal antecedents. We explain the mystery tant bien que mal by our evolutionary theories, saying that lucky varia tions and heredity have gradually brought it about that WILL. 495 this particular pair of terms should have grown into a uni form sequence. Meanwhile why any state of consciousness at all should precede a movement, we know not — the tw i things seem so essentially discontinuous. But if a state of consciousness there must be, why then it may, for aught we can see, as easily be one sort of a state as another. It is swallowing a camel and straining at a gnat for a man (all of whose muscles will on certain occasions contract at a sudden touch or sound) to suppose that on another occasion the idea of the feelings about to be produced by their con traction is an insufficient mental signal for the latter^ and to insist that an additional antecedent is needed in the shape of 'a feeling of the outgoing discharge.' No ! for aught we can see, and in the light of general analogy, the kinsesthetic ideas, as we have defined them, or images of incoming feelings of attitude and motion, are as likely as any feelings of innervation are, to be the last psychic antecedents and determiners of the various cur rents downwards into the muscles from the brain. The question " What are the antecedents and determinants ?" is a question of fact, to be decided by whatever empirical evi dence may be found.* * As the feeling of heat, for example, is the last psychic antecedent of sweating, as the feeling of bright light is that of the pupil's contraction, as the sight or smell of carrion is that of the movements of disgust, as the remembrance of a blunder may be that of a blush, so the idea of a move ment's sensible effects might be that of the movement itself. It is true that the idea of sweating will not commonly make us sweat, nor that of blushing make us blush. But in certain nauseated states the idea of vom iting will make us vomit; and a kind of sequence which is in this case realized only exceptionally might be the rule with the so-called voluntary muscles It all depends on the nervous connections between the centres of ideation and the discharging paths. These may differ from one sort of centre to another. They do differ somewhat from one individual to an other Many persons never blush at the idea of their blunders, but only when the actual blunder is committed; others blush at the idea; and some do uot blush at all. According to Lotze, with some persons " It is possible to weep at will by trying to recall that peculiar feeling in the trigeminal nerve which habitually precedes tears. Some can even succeed in sweating voluntarily, by the lively recollection of the characteristic skin -sensations, and the voluntary reproduction of an indescribable sort of feeling of relax ation, which ordinarily precedes the flow of perspiration." (Med. Psych., p. 303.) The commoner type of exceptional case is that in which the idea of the stimulus, not that of the effects, provokes the effects. Thus wo 496 PSYCHOLOGY. But before considering the empirical evidence, let me go on to show that there is a certain a priori reason why the kin&sthetic images OUGHT to be the last psychic antecedents of the outgoing currents, and why we should expect these currents to be insentient; tvhy, in shorty the soi-disant feelings of inner- vation should NOT exist. It is a general principle in Psychology that conscious ness deserts all processes where it can no longer be of use. The tendency of consciousness to a minimum of complica tion is in fact a dominating law. The law of parsimony in logic is only its best known case. We grow unconscious of every feeling which is useless as a sign to lead us to our ends, and where one sign will suffice others drop out, and that one remains, to work alone. We observe this in the whole history of sense-perception, and in the acquisition of every art. We ignore which eye we see with, because a fixed mechanical association has been formed between our motions and each retinal image. Our motions are the ends of our seeing, our retinal images the signals to these ends. If each retinal image, whichever it be, can suggest automatically a motion in the right direction, what need for us to know whether it be in the right eye or the left ? read of persons who contract their pupils at will by strongly imagining a brilliant light. A gentleman once informed me (strangely enough I can not recall who he was, but I have an impression of his being a medical man) that he could sweat at will by imagining himself on the brink of a precipice. The sweating palms of fear are sometimes producible by imagining a ter rible object (cf. Manouvrier in Rev. Phil., xxn. 203). One of my students, whose eyes were made to water by sitting in the dentist's chair before a bright window, can now shed tears by imagining that situation again. One might doubtless collect a large number of idiosyncratic cases of this sort. They teach us how greatly the centres vary in their power to dis charge through certain channels. All that we need, now, to account for the differences observed between the psychic antecedents of the volun tary and involuntary movements is that centres producing ideas of the movement's sensible effects should be able to instigate the former, but be out of gear with the latter, unless in exceptional individuals. The famous case of Col. Townsend, who could stop his heart at will, is well known. See, on this whole matter, D. H. Tuke: Illustrations of the Influence of the Mind on the Body, chap. xiv. § 3; also J. Braid: Observations on Trance or Human Hybernation (1850). The latest reported case of volun tary control of the heart is by Dr. S. A. Pease, in Boston Medical and Sur gical Journal, May 30, 1889. WILL. 497 That knowledge would be superfluous complication. So in acquiring any art or voluntary function. The marksman ends by thinking only of the exact position of the goal, the singer only of the perfect sound, the balancer only of the point of the pole whose oscillations he must counteract. The associated mechanism has become so perfect in all these persons that each variation in the thought of the end is functionally correlated with the one movement fitted to bring the latter about. Whilst they were tyros, they thought of their means as well as their end : the marksman of the position of his gun or bow, or the weight of his stone ; the pianist of the visible position of the note on the keyboard ; the singer of his throat or breathing ; the balancer of his feet on the rope, or his hand or chin under the pole. But little by little they succeeded in dropping all this supernumerary consciousness, and they became secure in their movements exactly in proportion as they did so. Now if we analyze the nervous mechanism of voluntary action, we shall see that by virtue of this principle of par simony in consciousness the motor discharge ought to be devoid of sentience. If we call the immediate psychic an tecedent of a movement the latter's mental cite, all that is needed for invariability of sequence on the movement's part is a, fixed connection between each several mental cue, and one particular movement. For a movement to be pro duced with perfect precision, it suffices that it obey in stantly its own mental cue and nothing else, and that this mental cue be incapable of awakening any other movement. Now the simplest possible arrangement for producing vol untary movements would be that the memory-images of the movement's distinctive peripheral effects, whether resi dent or remote,* themselves should severally constitute the mental cues, and that no other psychic facts should inter vene or be mixed up with them. For a million different voluntary movements, we should then need a million dis- * Prof. Harless, in an article which in many respects forestalls what I have to say (Der Apparat des Willens, in Fichte's Zeitschrift f. Philos., Bd. 88, 1861), uses the convenient word Effectsbild to designate these images. 498 PSYCHOLOGY. tinct processes in the brain-cortex (each corresponding to the idea cr memory-image of one movement), and a million distinct paths of discharge. Everything would then be unambiguously determined, and if the idea were right, the movement would be right too. Everything after the idea might then be quite insentient, and the motor discharge itself could be unconsciously performed. The partisans of the feeling of innervation, however, say that the motor discharge itself must be felt, and that it, and not the idea of the movement's distinctive effects, must be the proper mental cue. Thus the principle of parsimony is sacrificed, and all economy and simplicity are lost. For what can be gained by the interposition of this relay of feeling between the idea of the movement and the movement? Nothing on the score of economy of nerve- tracts ; for it takes just as many of them to associate a million ideas of movement with a million motor centres, each with a specific feeling of innervation attached to its discharge, as to associate the same million ideas with a million insentient motor centres. And nothing on the score of precision ; for the -only conceivable way in which the feelings of innervation might further precision would be by giving to a mind whose idea of a movement was vague, a sort of halting stage with sharper imagery on which to collect its wits before uttering its fiat. But not only are the con scious discriminations between our kinsesthetic ideas much sharper than any one pretends the shades of difference be tween feelings of innervation to be, but even were this not the case, it is impossible to see how a mind with its idea vaguely conceived could tell out of a lot of Innervations- gefuMe, were they never so sharply differentiated, which one fitted that idea exactly, and which did not. A sharply con ceived idea will, on the other hand, directly awaken a dis tinct movement as easily as it will awaken a distinct feeling of innervation. If feelings can go astray through vague ness, surely the fewer steps of feeling there are interposed the more securely we shall act. We ought then, on a priori grounds alone, to regard the Innervationsgefuhl as a pure encumbrance, and to presume that the peripheral ideas of movement are sufficient mental cues. WILL. 499 The presumption being thus against the feelings of in- nervation, those who defend their existence are bound to prove it by positive evidence. The evidence might be di rect or indirect. If we could introspectively feel them as something plainly distinct from the peripheral feelings and ideas of movement which nobody denies to be there, that would be evidence both direct and conclusive. Unfor tunately it does not exist. There is no introspective evidence of the feeling of innerva- tion, Wherever we look for it and think we have grasped it, we find that we have really got a peripheral feeling or image instead — an image of the way in which we feel when the innervation is over, and the movement is in process of doing or is done. Our idea of raising our arm, for example, or of crooking our finger, is a sense, more or less vivid, of how the raised arm or the crooked finger feels. There is no other mental material out of which such an idea might be made. We cannot possibly have any idea of our ears' motion until our ears have moved ; and this is true of every other organ as well. Since the time of Hume it has been a commonplace in psychology that we are only conversant with the outward results of our volition, and not with the hidden inner machinery of nerves and muscles which are what it prima rily sets at work.* The believers in the feeling of inner vation readily admit this, but seem hardly alive to its con sequences. It seems to me that one immediate conse quence ought to be to make us doubt the existence of the feeling in dispute. Whoever says that in raising his arm he is ignorant of how many muscles he contracts, in what order of sequence, and in what degrees of intensity, ex pressively avows a colossal amount of unconsciousness of the processes of motor discharge. Each separate muscle at any rate cannot have its distinct feeling of innervation. Wundt,t who makes such enormous use of these hypo- * The best modern statement I know is by Jaccoud: Des Paraplegics et de 1'Ataxie du Mouvement (Paris, 1864), p. 591. f Leidesdorf u. Meynert's Vierteljsch. f . Psychiatric, Bd. i. Heft I. S. 36-7 (1867). Physiologische Psychologic, 1st ed. S. 316. 500 PSYCHOLOGY. thetical feelings in his psychologic construction of space, is himself led to admit that they have no differences of quality, but feel alike in all muscles, and vary only in their degrees of intensity. They are used by the mind as guides, not of ivhich movement, but of how strong a movement, it is making, or shall make. But does not this virtually sur render their existence altogether ? * For if anything be obvious to introspection it is that the degree of strength of our muscular contractions is com pletely revealed to us by afferent feelings coming from the muscles themselves and their insertions, from the vicinity of the joints, and from the general fixation of the larynx, chest, face, and body, in the phenomenon of effort, objec tively considered. When a certain degree of energy of con traction rather than another is thought of by us, this com plex aggregate of afferent feelings, forming the material of our thought, renders absolutely precise and distinctive our mental image of the exact strength of movement to be made, and the exact amount of resistance to be overcome. Let the reader try to direct his will towards a particu lar movement, and then notice what constituted the direc tion of the will. Was it anything over and above the no tion of the different feelings to which the movement when effected would give rise ? If we abstract from these feel ings, will any sign, principle, or means of orientation be left by which the will may innervate the right muscles with the right intensity, and not go astray into the wrong ones ? Strip off these images of result, and so far from leaving us with a complete assortment of directions into which our will may launch itself, you leave our conscious ness in an absolute and total vacuum. If I will to write "Peter" rather than "Paul," it is the thought of certain digital sensations, of certain alphabetic sounds, of certain appearances on the paper, and of no others, which im mediately precedes the motion of my pen. * Professor Fouillee, who defends them in the Revue Philosophique, xxvin, 561 ff.. also admits (p. 574) that they are the same whatever be th* movement, and that all our discrimination of which movement we are inner vating is afferent, consisting of sensations after, and of sensory images before, the act. WILL. 501 If I will to utter the word Paid rather than Peter, it ih the thought of my voice falling on my ear, and of certain muscular feelings in my tongue, lips, and larynx, which guide the utterance. All these are incoming feelings, and between the thought of them, by which the act is mentally specified with all possible completeness, and the act itself, there is no room for any third order of mental phenome non. There is indeed the fiat, the element of consent, or resolve that the act shall ensue. This, doubtless, to the reader's mind, as to my own, constitutes the essence of the voluntariness of the act. This fiat will be treated of in detail farther on. It may be entirely neglected here, for it is a constant coefficient, affecting all voluntary actions alike, and incapable of serving to distinguish them. No one will pretend that its quality varies according as the right arm, for example, or the left is used. An anticipatory image, then, of the sensorial consequences^ of a movement, plus (on certain occasions) the fiat that these) consequences shall become actual, is the only psychic state] ^vhich introspection lets us discern as the forerunner of our) voluntary acts. There is no introspective evidence what ever of any still later or concomitant feeling attached to the efferent discharge. The various degrees of difficulty with which the fiat is given form a complication of the utmost importance, to be discussed farther on. Now the reader may still shake his head and say : " But can you seriously mean that all the wonderfully exact adjustment of my action's strength to its ends is not a matter of outgoing innervation ? Here is a cannon-ball, and here a pasteboard box : instantly and accurately I lift each from the table, the ball not refusing to rise because my innervation was too weak, the box not flying abruptly into the air because it was too strong. Could representations of the movement's different sensory effects im the two cases be so delicately foreshadowed in the mind? or being there, is it credible that they should, all unaided, so delicately graduate the stimulation of the unconscious motor centres to their work?" Even so! I reply to both queries. We have a most extremely deli cate foreshadowing of the sensory effects. Why else the 502 PSYCHOLOGY. start of surprise that runs through us if some one has tilled the light-seeming box with sand before we try to lift it, or has substituted for the cannon-ball which we know a painted wooden imitation? Surprise can only come from getting a sensation which differs from the one we expect. But the truth is that when we know the objects well, the very slightest difference from the expected weight will surprise us, or at least attract our notice. With un known objects we begin by expecting the weight made probable by their appearance. The expectation of this sensation innervates our lift, and we ' set ' it rather small at first. An instant verifies whether it is too small. Our expectation rises, i.e., we think in a twinkling of a setting of the chest and teeth, a bracing of the back, and a more violent feeling in the arms. Quicker than thought we have them, and with them the burden ascends into the air.* Bernhardt f has shown in a rough experimental way that our estimation of the amount of a resistance is as delicately graduated when our wills are passive, and our limbs made to contract by direct local faradization, as when we our- * Of. Souriau in Rev. Philosophique, xxn. 454.— Professor G. E. Mtiller thus describes some of his experiments with weights : If, after lifting a weight of 3000 grams a number of times we suddenly get a weight of only 500 grams to lift, " this latter weight is then lifted with a velocity which strikes every onlooker, so that the receptacle for the weight with all its contents often flies high up as if it carried the arm along with it, and the energy with which it is raised is sometimes so entirely out of propor tion to the weight itself, that the contents of the receptacle are slung out upon the table in spite of the mechanical obstacles which such a result has to overcome. A more palpable proof that the trouble here is a wrong adap- tation of the motor impulse could not be given." Pfltiger's Archiv, XLV. 47. Compare also p. 57, and the quotation from Bering on the same page. t Archiv fur Psychiatric, m. 618-635. Bernhardt strangely enough iieems to think that what his experiments disprove is the existence of affer ent muse liar feelings, not those of efferent innervation— apparently because he deems that the peculiar thrill of the electricity ought to overpower all other afferent feelings from the part But it is far more natural to inter pret his results the other way, even aside from the certainty yielded by other evidence that passive muscular feelings exist. This other evidence, after being compendiously summed up by Sachs in Reichert und Du Bois' Archiv (1874), pp. 174-188, is, as far as the anatomical and physio logical grounds go, again thrown into doubt by Mays, Zeitschrift f. Bin- logie, Bd. xx. WILL. 503 selves innervate them. Ferrier * has repeated and verified the observations. They admit of no great precision, and too much stress should not be laid upon them either way ; but at the very least they tend to show that no added deli cacy would accrue to our perception from the consciousness of the efferent process, even if it existed. Since there is no direct introspective evidence for the feelings of innervation, is there any indirect or circumstan tial evidence ? Much is offered ; but on critical examina tion it breaks down. Let us see what it is. Wundt says that were our motor feelings of an afferent nature, ' ' it ought to be expected that they would increase and diminish with the amount of outer or inner work actually effected in contraction. This, however, is not the case, but the strength of the motor sensation is purely proportional to the strength of the impulse to movement, which starts from the central organ innervating the motor nerves. This may be proved by observations made by physicians in cases of morbid alteration in the muscular effect. A patient whose arm or leg is half paralyzed, so that he can only move the limb with great effort, has a distinct feeling of this effort : the limb seems to him heavier than before, appearing as if weighted with lead ; he has, therefore, a sense of more work effected than formerly, and yet the effected work is either the same or even less. Only he must, to get even this effect, exert a stronger innervation, a stronger motor impulse, than formerly." f In complete paralysis, also, patients will be conscious of putting forth the greatest exertion to move a limb which remains absolutely still upon the bed, and from which of course no afferent muscular or other feelings can come.;): But Dr. Terrier in his Functions of the Brain (Am. Ed. * Functions of the Brain, p. 228. \ Vorlesungen iiber Menschen und Thierseele, i. 222. J In some instances we get an opposite result. Dr. H. Charlton Bastian (British Medical Journal (1869), p. 461, note), says : " Ask a man whose lower extremities are completely paralyzed, whether, when he ineffectually wills to move either of these limbs, he is conscious of an expenditure of energy in any degree proportionate to that which he would have experienced if his muscles had naturally responded to his voli tion. He will tell us rather that he has a sense only of his utter power- lessness, and that his volition is a mere mental act, carrying with it no feel ings of expended energy such as he is accustomed to experience when his muscles are in powerful action, and from which action and its consequences alone, as I think, he can derive any adequate notion of resistance." 504 PSYCHOLOGY pp. 222-4) disposes very easily of this line of argument He says : " It is necessary, however, to exclude movements altogether before such an explanation [as Wundt's] can be adopted. Now, though the hemiplegic patient cannot move his paralyzed limb, though he is con scious of trying hard, yet he will be found to be making powerful mus cular exertion of some kind. Vulpian has called attention to the fact, and I have repeatedly verified it, that when a hemiplegic patient is desired to close his paralyzed fist, in his endeavors to do so he uncon sciously performs this action with the sound one. It is, in fact, almost impossible to exclude such a source of complication, and unless this is taken into account very erroneous conclusions as to the cause of the sense of effort may be drawn. In the fact of muscular contraction and the concomitant centripetal impressions, even though the action is not euch as is desired, the conditions of the consciousness of effort exist without our being obliged to regard it as depending on central innerva- tion or outgoing currents. ' ' It is, however, easy to make an experiment of a simple nature which will satisfactorily account for the sense of effort, even when these unconscious contractions of the other side, such as hemiplegics make, are entirely excluded. ' l If the reader will extend his right arm and hold his forefinger in the position required for pulling the trigger of a pistol, he may without actually moving his finger, but by simply making believe, experience a consciousness of energy put forth. Here, then, is a clear case of con sciousness of energy without actual contraction of the muscles either of the one hand or the other, and without any perceptible bodily strain. If the reader will again perform the experiment, and pay careful atten tion to the condition of his respiration, he will observe that his con sciousness of effort coincides with a fixation of the muscles of his chest, and that in proportion to the amount of energy he feels he is putting forth, he is keeping his glottis closed and actively contracting his res piratory muscles. Let him place his finger as before, and continue breathing all the time, and he will find that however much he may direct his attention to his finger, he will experience not the slightest trace of consciousness of effort until he has actually moved the finger itself, and then it is referred locally to the muscles in action. It is only when this essential and ever-present respiratory factor is, as it has been, overlooked, that the consciousness of effort can with any degree of plausibility be ascribed to the outgoing current. In the contraction of the respiratory muscles there are the necessary conditions of centripetal impressions, and these are capable of originating the general sense of effort. When these active efforts are withheld, no consciousness of effort ever arises, except in so far as it is conditioned by the local con traction of the group of muscles towards which the attention ig directed, WILL. 505 or by other muscular contractions called unconsciously into play in the attempt. 1 ' I am unable to find a single case of consciousness of effort which is not explicable in one or other of the ways specified. In all instances the consciousness of effort is conditioned by the actual fact of muscular contraction. That it is dependent on centripetal impressions generated by the act of contraction, I have already endeavored to show. When the paths of the centripetal impressions or the cerebral centres of the same are destroyed, there is no vestige of a muscular sense. That the central organs for the apprehension of the impressions originating from muscular contraction are different from those which send out the motor impulse, has already been established. But when Wundt argues that this cannot be so, because then the sensation would always keep pace with the energy of muscular contraction, he overlooks the important factor of the fixation of the respiratory muscles, which is the basis of the general sense of effort in all its varying degrees." To these remarks of Ferrier's I have nothing to add.* Any one may verify them, and they prove conclusively that the consciousness of muscular exertion, being impossible without movement effected somewhere, must be an afferent and not an efferent sensation ; a consequence, and not an antecedent, of the movement itself. An idea of the amount of muscular exertion requisite to perform a certain move ment can consequently be nothing other than an anticipa tory image of the movement's sensible effects. * Miinstei berg's words may be added : "In lifting an object in the band I can discover no sensation of volitional energy 1 perceive in the drst place a slight tension about the head, but that this results from a con traction in the head muscles, and not from a feeling of the brain-discharge, is shown by the simple fact that I get the tension on the right side of the uead when I move the right arm, whereas the motor discharge takes place in the opposite side of the brain. ... In maximal contractions ofbody- tind limb-muscles there occur, as if it were to reinforce them, those special contractions of the muscles of the face [especially frowning and clinching teeth] and those tensions of the skin of the head. These sympathetic movements, felt particularly on the side which makes the effort, are perhaps the immediate ground why we ascribe our awareness of maximal contrac tion to the region of the head, and call it u consciousness of force, instead of a peripheral sensation." (Die Willenshandlung (1888), pp.73, 82.) Herr Milnsterberg's work is a little masterpiece, which appeared after my text was written, I shall have repeatedly to refer to it again, and cordially recommend to the reader its most thorough refutation of the Innervations- geftlhl-theory. 606 PSYCHOLOGY. Driven thus from the body at large, where next shall the circumstantial evidence for the feeling of innervation lodge itself? Where but in the muscles of the eye, from which small retreat it judges itself inexpugnable. Nevertheless, that fastness too must fall, and by the lightest of bom bardments. But, before trying the bombardment, let us recall our general principles about optical vertigo, or illu sory appearance of movement in objects. We judge that an object moves under two distinct sets of circumstances : 1. When its image moves on the retina, and we know that the eye is still. 2. When its image is stationary on the retina, and we know that the eye is moving. In this case we feel that we follow the object. In either of these cases a mistaken judgment about the state of the eye will produce optical vertigo. If in case 1 we think our eye is still when it is really moving, we get a movement of the retinal image which we judge to be due to a real outward motion of the object. This is what happens after looking at rushing water, or through the windows of a moving railroad car, or after turning on one's heel to giddiness. The eyes, without our intending to move them, go through a series of invol untary rotations, continuing those they were previously obliged to make to keep objects in view. If the objects had been whirling by to our right, our eyes when turned to stationary objects will still move slowly towards the right. The retinal image upon them will then move like that of an object passing to the left. We then try to catch it by vol untarily and rapidly rotating the eyes to the left, when the involuntary impulse again rotates the eyes to the right, con tinuing the apparent motion ; and so the game goes on. (See above, pp. 89-91.) If in case 2 we think our eyes moving when they are in reality still, we shall judge that we are following a moving object when we are but fixating a steadfast one. Illusions of this kind occur after sudden and complete paralysis of special eye muscles, and the partisans of feelings of efferent WILL. 507 innervation regard them as experimenta crucis. Helmholtz writes : * " When the external rectus muscle of the right eye, or its nerve, is 'paralyzed, the eye can no longer be rotated to the right side. So long as the patient turns it only to the nasal side it makes regular move ments, and he perceives correctly the position of objects in the visual field. So soon, however, as he tries to rotate it outwardly, i.e., towards the right, it ceases to obey his will, stands motionless in the middle of its course, and the objects appear flying to the right, although position of eye and retinal image are unaltered, t " In such a case the exertion of the will is followed neither by actual movement of the eye, nor by contraction of the muscle in question, nor even by increased tension in it. The act of will prodttced absolutely no effect beyond the nervous system, and yet we judge of the direction of the line of vision as if the will had exercised its normal effects. We believe it to have moved to the right, and since the retinal image is- unchanged, we attribute to the object the same movement we have er roneously ascribed to the eye. . . . These phenomena leave no room for doubt that we only judge the direction of the line of sight by the effort of will with which we strive to change the position of our eyes. There are also certain weak feelings in our eyelids, . . . and further more in excessive lateral rotations we feel a fatiguing strain in the muscles. But all these feelings are too faint and vague to be of use in the perception of direction. We feel then what impulse of the will, and how strong a one, we apply to turn our eye into a given position." Partial paralysis of the same muscle, paresis, as it has been called, seems to point even more conclusively to the same inference, that the will to innervate is felt independ ently of all its afferent results. I will quote the account given by a recent authority, $ of the effects of this accident : " When the nerve going to an eye muscle, e.g., the external rectus of one side, falls into a state of paresis, the first result is that the same volitional stimulus, which under normal circumstances would have per haps rotated the eye to its extreme position outwards, now is competent to effect only a moderate outward rotation, say of 20°. If now, shutting: the sound eye, the patient looks at an object situated just so far out- * Physiologische Optik, p. 600. f [The left and sound eye is here supposed covered. If both eyes look at the same field there are double images which still more perplex the judg ment. The patient, however, learns to see correctly before many days or weeks are over. — W. J.J t Alfred Graefe, in Handbuch der gesammten Augenheilkunde, Bd. vi. pp. 18-21. 508 PSYCHOLOGY. wards from the paretic eye that this latter must turn 20° in order to see it distinctly, the patient will feel as if he had moved it not only 20° towards the side, but into its extreme lateral position, for the impulse of innervation requisite for bringing it into view is a perfectly conscious act, whilst the diminished state of contraction of the paretic muscle lies for the present out of the ken of consciousness. The test proposed by von Graefe, of localization by the sense of touch, serves to render evi dent the error which the patient now makes. If we direct him to touch rapidly the object looked at, with the fore-finger of the hand of the same side, the line through which the finger moves will not be the line of sight directed 20° outward, but will approach more nearly to the ex treme possible outward line of vision. " A stone-cutter with the external rectus of the left eye paralyzed, will strike his hand instead of his chisel with his hammer, until experience has taught him wisdom. It appears as if here the judgment of direction could only arise from the excessive innervation of the rectus when the object is looked at. All the afferent feelings must be iden tical with those experienced when the eye is sound and the judgment is correct. The eyeball is rotated just 20° in the one case as in the other, the image falls on the same part of the retina, the pressures on the eyeball and the tensions of the skin and conjunctiva are identical. There is only one feeling which can vary, and lead us to our mistake. That feeling must be the effort which the will makes, mod erate in the one case, excessive in the other, but in both -cases an efferent feeling, pure and simple. Beautiful and clear as this reasoning seems to be, it is based on am incomplete inventory of the afferent data. The writers have all omitted to consider what is going on in the other eye. This is kept covered during the experiments, to prevent double images, and other complications. But if its condition under these circumstances be examined, it will be found to present changes which must result in strong afferent feelings. And the taking account of these feelings demolishes in an instant all the conclusions which the au thors from whom I have quoted base upon their supposed absence. This I will now proceed to show.* * Professor G. E. Muller (Zur Grundlegung der Psychophysik (1878), p. 318, WHS the first to explain the phenomenon after the manner advocated WILL. 509 Take first the case of complete paralysis and assume the right eye affected. Suppose the patient desires to rotate his gaze to an object situated in the extreme right of the field of vision. As Hering has so beautifully shown, both eyes move by a common act of innervation, and in this instance both move towards the right. But the paralyzed right eye stops short in the middle of its course, the object still appearing far to the sight of its fixation point. The left sound eye, meanwhile, although covered, continues its rotation until the extreme rightward limit thereof has been reached. To an observer looking at both eyes the left will seem to squint. Of course this continued and extreme ro tation produces afferent feelings of rightward motion in the eyeball, which momentarily overpower the faint feelings of central position in the diseased and uncovered eye. The patient feels by his left eyeball as if he were following an object which by his right retina he perceives he does not overtake. All the conditions of optical vertigo are here present : the image stationary on the retina, and the erro neous conviction that the eyes are moving. The objection that a feeling in the left eyeball ought not to produce a conviction that the right eye moves, will be considered in a moment. Let us meanwhile turn to the in the text. Still unacquainted with his book, 1 published my own simi lar explanation two years later. "Professor Mach in his wonderfully original little work 'Beitrage zur Analyse der Einpfindungen,' p 57, describes an artificial way of getting translocation, and explains the effect likewise by the feeling of innervation. "Turn your eyes," he says, " as far as possible towards the left and press against the right sides of the orbits two large lumps of putty. If you then try to look as quickly as possible towards the right, this succeeds, on ac count of the incompletely spherical form of the eyes, only imperfectly, and the objects consequently appear translocated very considerably towards the right. The bare will to look rightwards gives to all images on the retina a greater rightwards value, to express it shortly. The experiment is at first surprising."— I regret to say that I cannot myself make it succeed— I know not for what reason But even where it does succeed it seems to me that the conditions are much too complicated for Professor Mach's theoretic con- elusions to be safely drawn. The putty squeezed into the orbit, and the pressure of the eyeball against it must give rise to peripheral sensations strong enough, at any rate (if only of the right kind), to justify any amount of false perception of our eyeball's position, quite apart from the iunerva- tion feelings which Professsor Mach supposes to coexist. 510 PSYCHOLOGY. ease of simple paresis with apparent translocation 01 the field. Here the right eye succeeds in fixating the object, but observation of the left eye will reveal to an observer the fact that it squints just as violently inwards as in the former case. The direction which the finger of the patient takes in pointing to the object, is the direction of this squinting and covered left eye. As Graefe says (although he fails to seize the true import of his own observation), " It appears to have been by no means sufficiently noticed how signifi cantly the direction of the line of sight of the secondarily deviating eye [i.e., of the left,] and the line of direction of the pointed finger agree." The translocation would, in a word, be perfectly ex plained could we suppose that the sensation of a certain degree of rotation in the left eyeball were able to suggest to the patient the positign of an object whose image falls on the right retina alone. * Can, then, a feeling in one eyo * An illusion in principle exactly analogous to that of the patient under discussion can be produced experimentally in anyone in a way which Hering has described in his Lehre von Binocularen Sehen, pp. 12-14. I wiU quote Helmhoitz's account of it, which is especially valuable as coming from a believer in the Innervationsgefuhl : "Let the two eyes first look parallel, then let the right eye be closed whilst the left still looks at the in finitely distant object a. The directions of both eyes will thus remain un altered, and a will be seen in its right place. Now accommodate the left eye for a point / [a needle in Hering's experiment] lying on the optical axis between it and a, only very near. The position of the left eye and its optical axis, as well as the place of the retinal image upon it ... are wholly unaltered by this movement, But the consequence is that an ap parent movement of the object occurs — a movement towards the left, As soon as we accommodate again for distance the object returns to its old place. Now what alters itself in this experiment is only the position of the closed right eye : its optical axis, when the effort is made to accommodate for the point/, also converges towards this point. . . . Conversely it is possible for me to make my optical axes diverge, even with closed eyes, go that in the above experiment the right eye should turn far to the right of «. This divergence is but slowly reached, and gives me therefore no illusory movement. But when I suddenly relax my effort to make it, and the right optical axis springs back to the parallel position, I immediately see the object which the left eye fixates shift its position towards the left. Thus not only the position of the seeing eye a, but also that of the closed eye b, influences our judgment of the direction in which the seen object WILL. 5ll be confounded with a feeling in the other? It most as suredly can, for not only Bonders and Adamiik, by their vivisections, butHering by his exquisite optical experiments, have proved that the apparatus of innervation for both eyes is single, and that they function as one organ — a double eye, according to Hering, or what Helmholtz calls a Cydopenauge. The retinal feelings of this double organ, singly innervated, are naturally undistinguished as respects our knowing whether they belong to the left retina or to the right. We use them only to tell us where their objects lie. It takes long practice directed specially ad hoc to teach us on which retina the sensations severally fall. Simi larly the different sensations which arise from the posi tions of the eyeballs are used exclusively as signs of the position of objects ; an object directly fixated being local ized habitually at the intersection of the two optical axes, but without any separate consciousness on our part that the position of one axis is different from another. All we are aware of is a consolidated feeling of a certain ' strain ' in the eyeballs, accompanied by the perception that just so far in front and so far to the right or to the left there is an object which we see. So that a * muscular ' process in one eye is as likely to combine with a retinal process in the other eye to effect a perceptive judgment, as two processes in one eye are likely so to combine. Another piece of circumstantial evidence for the feelings of innervation is that adduced by Professor Mach, as fol lows : " If we stand on a bridge, and look at the water flowing beneath, we usually feel ourselves at rest, whilst the water seems in motion. Prolonged looking at the water, however, commonly has for its result to make the bridge with the observer and surroundings suddenly seem to movo in the direction opposed to that of the water, whilst the water itself assumes the appearance of standing still. The relative motion of the objects is in both cases the same, and there must therefore be some lies. The open eye remaining fixed, and the closed eye moving towards the right or left, the object seen by the open eye appears also to move to wards the right or left. " (Physiol. Optik, pp. 607-8.) 512 PSYCHOLOGY. adequate physiological ground why sometimes one, sometimes the other part of them is felt to move. In order to investigate the matter con- / veniently, I had the simple apparatus constructed which is represented in Fig. 86. An oil-cloth with a simple pattern is horizontally stretched over two cylinders (each 2 metres long and 3 feet apart) and kept in uniform motion by the help of a crank. Across the cloth, FlG- 86 and some 30 cm. above it, is stretched a string, with a knot #, which serves as a fixation-point for the eye of the observer. If the observer follow with his eyes the pattern of the cloth as it moves, he sees it in movement, himself and the surroundings at rest. But if he looks at the knot, he soon feels as if the entire room were moving contrary to the direction of the cloth, whilst the latter seems to stand still. This change in the mode of looking comes about in more or less time according to one's momentary disposition, but usually it takes but a few seconds. If one once under stands the point, one can make the two appearances alternate at will. Every following of the oil-cloth makes the observer stationary ; every fixation of the knot or inattention to the oil-cloth, so that its pattern becomes blurred, sets him in apparent motion." * Professor Mach proceeds to explain the phenomenon as follows: " Moving objects exert, as is well known, a peculiar motor stimulation upon the eye, they draw our attention and our look after them. If the look really follows them ... we assume that they move. But if the eye, instead of following the moving objects, remains steadfastly at rest, it must be that the constant stimulus to motion which it receives is neutralized by an equally constant current of innervation flowing into its motor apparatus. But this is just what would happen if the steadfastly fixated point were itself moving uniformly in the other di rection, and we were following it with our eyes. When this comes about, whatever motionless things are looked at must appear in mo tion.''! The knot a?, the string, we ourselves, and all our sta- * Beitrage zur Analyse der Empfindungen, p. 65. P. 68. WILL. 613 tionary surroundings thus appear in movement, according to Mach, because we are constantly innervating our eye balls to resist the drag exerted upon them by the pattern or the flowing waves. I have myself repeated the observa tion many times above flowing streams, but have never suc ceeded in getting the full illusion as described by Mach. I gain a sense of the movement of the bridge and of my own body, but the river never seems absolutely to stop : it still moves in one direction, whilst I float away in the other. But, be the illusion partial or complete, a different ex planation of it from Professor Mach's seems to me the more natural one to adopt. The illusion is said to cease when, our attention being fully fixed on the moving oil-cloth, we perceive the latter for what it is; and to recommence, on the contrary, when we perceive the oil-cloth as a vaguely moving background behind an object which we directly fixate and whose position with regard to our own body is unchanged. This, however, is the sort of consciousness which we have whenever we are ourselves borne in a vehicle, on horseback, or in a boat. As we and our belongings go one way, the whole background goes the other. I should rather, therefore, explain Professor Mach's illusion as similar to the illusion at railroad-stations described above on page 90. The other train moves, but it makes ours seem to move, because, filling the window as it does, it stands for the time being as the total background. So here, the water or oil-cloth stands for us as background iiberhaupt whenever we seem to ourselves to be moving over it. The relative motion felt by the retina is assigned to that one of its components which we look at more in itself and less as a mere repoussoir. This may be the knot above the oil cloth or the bridge beneath our feet, or it may be, on the other hand, the oil-cloth's pattern or the surface of the swirling stream. Similar changes may be produced in the apparent motion of the moon and the clouds through which it shines, by similarly altering the attention. Such altera tions, however, in our conception of which part of the vis ual field is substantive object and which part background, seem to have no connection with feelings of innervation. I 514 PS TCHOLOG T. cannot, therefore, regard the observation of Prof. Mach as any proof that the latter feelings exist.* The circumstantial evidence for the feeling of innervation thus seems to break down like the introspective evidence. But not only can we rebut experiments intended to prove it, we can also adduce experiments which disprove it. A person who moves a limb voluntarily must innervate it in any case, and if he feels the innervation he ought to be able to use the feeling to define what his limb is about, even though the limb itself were anaesthetic. If, however, the limb be totally anaesthetic, it turns out that he does not know at all how much work it performs in its contraction — in other words, he has no perception of the amount of inner vation which he exerts. A patient examined by Messrs. Gley and Marillier beautifully showed this. His entire arms, and his trunk down to the navel, were insensible both superficially and deeply, but his arms were not paralyzed : ' ' We take three stone bottles — two of them are empty and weigh each 250 grams; the third is full of mercury and weighs 1850 grams. We ask L ... to estimate their weight and tell us which is heaviest. He declares that he finds them all three alike. With many days of in terval we made two series of six experiments each. The result was always the same. The experiment, it need hardly be said, was arranged in * I owe the interpretation in the text to my friend and former student, Mr. E. S. Drown, whom I set to observe the phenomenon before I had observed it myself. Concerning the vacillations in our interpretation of relative motion over retina and skin, see above, p. 173. Herr Miinsterberg gives additional reasons against the feeling of in nervation, of which I will quote a couple. First, our ideas of movement are all faint ideas, resembling in this the copies of sensations in memory. Were they feelings of the outgoing discharge, they would be original states of consciousness, not copies ; and ought by analogy to be mmd like other original states. — Second, our unstriped muscles yield no feelings in con tracting, nor can they be contracted at will, differing thus in t wo peculiari ties from the voluntary muscles. What more natural than to suppose that the two peculiarities hang together, and that the reason why we cannot con tract our intestines, for example, at will, is, that we have no memory-images of how their contraction feels ? Were the supposed innervation-feeling al ways the 'mental cue,' one doesn't see why we might not have it even where, as here, the contractions themselves are unfelt, and why it might not bring the contractions about. (Die Willenshandlung, pp. 87-8.) WILL. 515 such wise that he could be informed neither by sight nor by hearing. He even declared, holding in his hand the bottleful of mercury, that he found it to have no weight. ... We place successively in his hand (his eyes being still bandaged) a piece of modelling wax, a stick of hard wood, a thick India-rubber tube, a newspaper folded up lengthwise and rumpled, and we make him squeeze these several objects. He feels no difference of resistance and does not even perceive that anything is in his hand."* M. Gley in another place t quotes experiments by Dr. Bloch which prove that the sense which we have of our limbs' position owes absolutely nothing to the feeling of in- nervation put forth. Dr. Bloch stood opposite the angle of a screen whose sides made an angle of about 90°, and tried to place his hands symmetrically, or so that both should fall on corresponding spots of the two screen-sides, which were marked with squares for the purpose. The average error being noted, one hand was then passively carried by an assistant to a spot on its screen-side, and the other actively sought the corresponding spot on the opposite side. The accuracy of the correspondence proved to be as great as when both arms were innervated voluntarily, showing that the consciousness of innervation in the first of the two experiments added nothing to the sense of the limbs' position. Dr. Bloch then tried, pressing a certain number of pages of a book between the thumb and fore finger of one hand, to press an equal number between the same fingers of the other hand. He did this just as well when the fingers in question were drawn apart by India- rubber bands as when they were uninterfered with, showing that the physiologically much greater innervation-current required in the former case had no effect upon the conscious ness of the movement made, so far as its spatial character at any rate was concerned.^ * Revue Philosophique. xxin. 442. f Ibid. xx. 604. \ Herr Stern berg (Pflilger's Archiv, xxxvn. p. 1) thinks that he proves the feeling of innervation by the fact that when we have willed to make a movement we generally think that it is made. We have already seen some of the facts on pp. 105-6, above. 8. cites from Exner the fact that if we put a piece of hard rubber between our back teeth and bite, our front teeth seem actually to approach each other, although it is physically impossible 516 PSYCHOLOGY. On the whole, then, it seems as probable as anything can well be, that these feelings of in nervation do not exist. for them to do so. He proposes the following experiment : Lay the palm of the hand on a table with the forefinger overlapping its edge and flexed back as far as possible, whilst the table keeps the other fingers extended ; then try to flex the terminal joint of the forefinger without looking. You do not do it, and yet you think that you do. Here again the innervation,, according to the author, is felt as an executed movement. It seems to me, as I said in the previous place, that the illusion is in all these cases due to the inveterate association of ideas. Normally our will to move has always, been followed by the sensation that we time moved, except when the simultaneous sensation of an external resistance was there. The result is. that where we feel no external resistance, and the muscles and tendons tighten, the invariably associated idea is intense enough to be hallucinatory. In the experiment with the teeth, the resistance customarily met with when our masseters contract is a soft one. We do not close our teeth on a thing like hard rubber once in a million times ; so when we do so, we imagine the habitual result.— Persons with amputated limbs more often than not continue to feel them as if they were still there, and can, moreover, give themselves the feeling of moving them at will. The life-long seusorial associate of the idea of 'working one's toes,' e.g. (uncorrected by any opposite sensation, since no real sensation of non-movement can come from non-existing toes), follows the idea and swallows it up. The man thinks that his toes are 'working' (cf. Proceedings of American Soc. for Psych. Research, p. 249). Herr Loeb also comes to the rescue of the feeling of innervation with observations of his own made after my text was written, but they convince me no more than the arguments of others. Loeb's facts are these (Pfliiger's Archiv, XLIV. p. 1): If we stand before a vertical surface., and if. with our hands at different heights, we simultaneously make with them what seem to us equally extensive movements, that movement always turns out really shorter which is made with the arm whose muscles (in virtue of the arm's position) are already the more contracted. The same result ensues when the arms are laterally un symmetrical. Loeb assumes that both arms contract by virtue of a common innervation, but that although this innervation is relatively less effective upon the more contracted arm, our feeling of its equal strength overpowers the disparity of the incoming sensations of movement which the two limbs send back, and makes us think that the spaces they traverse are the same. " The sensation of the extent and direction of our voluntary movements depends accordingly upon the impulse of our will to move, and not upon the feelings set up by the motion in the active organ ." Now if this is the elementary law which Loeb calls it, why does it only manifest its effect when both hands are moving simultaneously? Why not when the same hand makes successive movements ? and especially why not when both hands move symmetrically or at the same level, but one ^ of them is weighted? A weighted hand surely requires a stronger innervation than an unweighted one to move an equal distance upwards ; and yet, as Loeb confesses, we do not tend to overestimate the path which it trav erses under these circumstances. The fact is that the illusion which Loeb WILL. 517 If the motor cells are distinct structures, they are as insen tient as the motor nerve-trunks are after the posterior roots are cut. If they are not distinct structures, but are only the last sensory cells, those at the ' mouth of the funnel,' * then their consciousness is that of kinsesthetic ideas and sensations merely, and this consciousness accompanies the rise of activity in them rather than its discharge. The en tire content and material of our consciousness — conscious ness of movement, as of all things else — is thus of periph eral origin, and came to us in the first instance through the peripheral nerves. If it be asked what we gain by this sensationalistic conclusion, I reply that we gain at any rate simplicity and uniformity. In the chapters on Space, on Belief, on the Emotions, we found sensation to be a much richer thing than is commonly supposed ; and this chapter seems at this point to fall into line with those. Then, as for sensationalism being a degrading belief, which abol ishes all inward originality and spontaneity, there is this has studied is a complex resultant of many factors. One of them, it seems to me, is an instinctive tendency to revert to the type of the bilateral movements of childhood. In adult life we move our arms for the most part in alternation ; but in infancy the free movements of the arms are almost always similar on both sides, symmetrical when ihe direction of motion is horizontal, and with the hands on the same level when it is ver tical. The most natural innervation, when the movements are rapidly per formed, is one which takes the movement back to this form. Our estima tion meanwhile of the lengths severally traversed by the two hands is mainly based, as such estimations with closed eyes usually are (see Loeb's •own earlier paper, Untersuchungen uber den FiMraum der Hand, in Pfltiger's Archiv, XLI. 107), upon the apparent velocity and duration of the movement. The duration is the same for both hands, since the move ments begin and end simultaneously. The velocities of the two hands are under the experimental conditions almost impossible of comparison. It is well known how imperfect a discrimination of weights we have when we ' heft' them siuultaneously, one in either hand; and G. E. Muller has well shown (Prtiiger's Archiv, XLV. 57) that the velocity of the lift is the main factor in determining our judgment of weight. It is hardly possible to conceive of more unfavorable conditions for making an accurate compari son of the length of two movements than those which govern the experi ments which are under discussion. The only prominent sign is the dura tion, which would lead us to infer the equality of the two movements. We consequently deem them equal, though a native tendency in our motor centres keeps them from being so. * This is by no means an unplausible opinion. See Vol I. p. 65. 518 PSYCHOLOGY. to be said, that the advocates of inward spontaneity may be turning their backs on its real citadel, when they make a fight, on its behalf, for the consciousness of energy put forth in the outgoing discharge. Let there be no such con sciousness ; let all our thoughts of movements be of sen sational constitution ; still in the emphasizing, choosing, and espousing of one of them rather than another, in the saying to it, 'be thou the reality for me,' there is ample scope for our inward initiative to be shown. Here, it seems to me, the true line between the passive materials and the activity of the spirit should be drawn. It is certainly false strategy to draw it between such ideas as are con nected with the outgoing and such as are connected with the incoming neural wave.* If the ideas by which we discriminate between one movement and another, at the instant of deciding in our mind which one we shall perform, are always of sensorial origin, then the question arises, " Of which sensorial order need they be ? " It will be remembered that we distin guished two orders of kinaesthetic impression, the remote ones, made by the movement on the eye or ear or distant skin, etc., and the resident ones, made on the moving parts, themselves, muscles, joints, etc. Now do resident images, exclusively, form what I have called the mental cue, or will remote ones equally suffice ? There can be no doubt whatever that the mental cue may be either an image of the resident or of the remote kind. Although, at the outset of our learning a movement, it would seem that the resident feelings must come strongly before con sciousness (cf. p. 487), later this need not be the case. The rule, in fact, would seem to be that they tend to lapse * Maine de Biran, Royer Collard, Sir John Herschel, Dr. Carpenter, Dr. Martineau, all seem to posit a force-sense by which, in becoming aware of an outer resistance to our will, we are taught the existence of an outer world. I hold that every peripheral sensation gives us an outer world. An insect crawling on our skin gives us as ' outward ' an impres sion as a hundred pounds weighing on our back.— I have read M. A. Ber- trand's criticism of my views (La Psychologic de 1'Effort, 1889); but as he seems to think that I deny the feeling of effort altogether, I can get no profit from it, despite his charming way of saying things. WILL. 519 more and more from consciousness, and that the more practised we become in a movement, the more ' remote ' do the ideas become which form its mental cue. What we are interested in is what sticks in our consciousness : everything else we get rid of as quickly as we can. Our resident feel ings of movement have no substantive interest for us at all, as a rule. What interest us are the ends which the move ment is to attain. Such an end is generally an outer im pression on the eye or ear, or sometimes on the skin, nose, or palate. Now let the idea of the end associate itself definitely with the right motor innervation, and the thought of the innervation's resident effects will become as great an encumbrance as we formerly concluded that the feeling of the innervation itself would be. The mind does not need it ; the end alone is enough. The idea of the end, then, tends more and more to make itself all-sufficient. Or, at any rate, if the kinsesthetic ideas are called up at all, they are so swamped in the vivid kinsesthetic feelings by which they are immediately over taken that we have no time to be aware of their separate existence. As I write, I have no anticipation, as a thing distinct from my sensation, of either the look or the digital feel of the letters which flow from my pen. The words chime on my mental ear, as it were, before I write them, but not on my mental eye or hand. This comes from the rapidity with which often-repeated movements follow on their mental cue. An end consented to as soon as conceived innervates directly the centre of the first movement of the chain which leads to its accomplishment, and then the whole chain rattles off gw * though the heavens fall.' This reckless and exultant es- WILL. 533 pousal of an energy so little premeditated by us that we feel rather like passive spectators cheering on the display of some extraneous force than like voluntary agents, is a type of decision too abrupt and tumultuous to occur often in humdrum and cool-blooded natures. But it is prob ably frequent in persons of strong emotional endowment and unstable or vacillating character. And in men of the world-shaking type, the Napoleons, Luthers, etc., in whom tenacious passion combines with ebullient activity, when by any chance the passion's outlet has been dammed by scru ples or apprehensions, the resolution is probably often of this catastrophic kind. The flood breaks quite unexpectedly through the dam. That it should so often do so is quite sufficient to account for the tendency of these characters to a fatalistic mood of mind. And the fatalistic mood itself is sure to reinforce the strength of the energy just started on its exciting path of discharge. There is a fourth form of decision, which often ends deliberation as suddenly as the third form does. It comes when, in consequence of some outer experience or some inexplicable inward charge, we suddenly pass from the easy and careless to the sober and strenuous mood, or possibly the other way. The whole scale of values of our motives and impulses then undergoes a change like that which a change of the observer's level produces on a view. The most sobering possible agents are objects of grief and fear. When one of these affects us, all * light fantastic ' notions lose their motive power, all solemn ones find theirs multi plied many-fold. The consequence is an instant abandon ment of the more trivial projects with which we had been dallying, and an instant practical acceptance of the more grim and earnest alternative which till then could not extort our mind's consent. All those 'changes of heart,1 * awakenings of conscience,' etc., which make new men of so many of us, may be classed under this head. The char acter abruptly rises to another 'level,' and deliberation comes to an immediate end.* * My attention was first emphatically called to this class of decisions by my colleague, Professor C. C. Everett. 534 PSYCHOLOGY. In the fifth and final type of decision, the feeling that the evidence is all in, and that reason has balanced the books, may be either present or absent. But in either case we feel, in deciding, as if we ourselves by our own wilful act inclined the beam ; in the former case by adding our living effort to the weight of the logical reason which, taken alone, seems powerless to make the act discharge ; in the ]atter by a kind of creative contribution of something instead of a reason which does a reason's work. The slow dead heave of the will that is felt in these instances makes of them a class altogether different subjectively from all the three preceding classes. What the heave of the will betokens metaphysically, what the effort might lead us to infer about a will-power distinct from motives, are not matters that concern us yet. Subjectively and phenome nally, the feeling of effort, absent from the former decisions, accompanies these. Whether it be the dreary resignation for the sake of austere and naked duty of all sorts of rich mundane delights, or whether it be the heavy resolve that of two mutually exclusive trains of future fact, both sweet and good, and with no strictly objective or imperative principle of choice between them, one shall forevermore become impossible, while the other shall become reality, it is a desolate and acrid sort of act, an excursion into a lone some moral wilderness. If examined closely, its chief differ ence from the three former cases appears to be that in those eases the mind at the moment of deciding on the trium phant alternative dropped the other one wholly or nearly out of sight, whereas here both alternatives are steadily held in view, and in the very act of murdering the van quished possibility the chooser realizes how much in that instant he is making himself lose. It is deliberately driving a thorn into one's flesh ; and the sense of in ward effort with which the act is accompanied is an ele ment which sets the fourth type of decision in strong contrast with the previous three varieties, and makes of it an alto gether peculiar sort of mental phenomenon. The immense majority of human decisions are decisions without effort. In comparatively few of them, in most people, does effort accom pany the final act. We are, I think, misled into supposing that WILL. 535 effort is more frequent than it is, by the fact that during deliberation we so often have a feeling of how great an effort it would take to make a decision now. Later, after the de cision has made itself with ease, we recollect this and erroneously suppose the effort also to have been made then. The existence of the effort as a phenomenal fact in our consciousness cannot of course be doubted or denied. Its significance, on the other hand, is a matter about which the gravest difference of opinion prevails. Questions as mo mentous as that of the very existence of spiritual causality, as vast as that of universal predestination or free-will, de pend on its interpretation. It therefore becomes essential that we study with some care the conditions under which the feeling of volitional effort is found. THE FEELING OF EFFOBT. When, awhile back (p. 526), I said that consciousness (or the neural process which goes with it) is in its very nature impulsive, I added in a note the proviso that it must be sufficiently intense. Now there are remarkable differences in the power of different sorts of consciousness to excite movement. The intensity of some feelings is practically apt to be below the discharging point, whilst that of others is apt to be above it. By practically apt, I mean apt under ordinary circumstances. These circumstances may be habitual inhibitions, like that comfortable feeling of the dolcefar niente which gives to each and all of us a certain dose of laziness only to be overcome by the acuteness of the impulsive spur ; or they may consist in the native inertia, or internal resistance, of the motor centres them selves making explosion impossible until a certain inward tension has been reached and overpast. These conditions may vary from one person to another and in the same per son from time to time. The neural inertia may wax or wane, and the habitual inhibitions dwindle or augment. The in tensity of particular thought-processes and stimulations may also change independently, and particular paths of association grow more pervious or less so. There thus re sult great possibilities of alteration in the actual impul- PSYCHOLOGY. give efficacy of particular motives compared with others. It is where the normally less efficacious motive becomes more efficacious and the normally more efficacious one less so that actions ordinarily effortless, or abstinences ordi narily easy, either become impossible or are effected, if at all, by the expenditure of effort. A little more description will make it plainer what these cases are. There is a certain normal ratio in the impulsive power of different sorts of motive, which characterizes what may be called ordinary healthiness of will, and which is departed from only at exceptional times or by exceptional individuals. The states of mind which normally possess the most impul sive quality are either those which represent objects of passion, appetite, or emotion— objects of instinctive reac tion, in short ; or they are feelings or ideas of pleasure or of pain ; or ideas which for any reason we have grown accus tomed to obey so that the habit of reacting on them is in grained ; or finally, in comparison with ideas of remoter objects, they are ideas of objects present or near in space and time. Compared with these various objects, all far-off considerations, all highly abstract conceptions, unaccus tomed reasons, and motives foreign to the instinctive history of the race, have little or no impulsive power. They prevail, when they ever do prevail, with effort ; and the normal, as distinguished from the pathological, sphere of effort is thus found wherever non-instinctive motives to behavior are to rule the day. Healthiness of will moreover requires a certain amount of complication in the process which precedes the fiat or the act. Each stimulus or idea, at the same time that it wakens its own impulse, must arouse other ideas (associated and consequential) with their impulses, and action must follow, neither too slowly nor too rapidly, as the resultant of all the forces thus engaged. Even when the decision is very prompt, there is thus a sort of preliminary survey of the field and a vision of which course is best before the fiat comes. And where the will is healthy, the vision must be right (i.e., the motives must be on the whole in a normal WILL. 537 .ar not too unusual ratio to each other), and the action must obey the vision's lead. Unhealthiness of will may thus come about in many ways. The action may follow the stimulus or idea too rapidly, leaving no time for. the arousal of restraining associates — we then have a precipitate will Or, although the associates may come, the ratio which the impulsive and inhibitive forces normally bear to each other may be distorted, and we then have a will ivhich is perverse. The perversity, in turn, may be due to either of many causes — too much in tensity, or too little, here ; too much or too little inertia there ; or elsewhere too much or too little inhibitory power. If we compare the outward symptoms of perversity togetJier, they fall into two groups, in one of which normal actions are impossible, and in the other abnormal ones are irrepressi ble. Briefly, we may call them respectively the obstructed and the explosive will. It must be kept in mind, however, that since the result ant action is always due to the ratio between the obstructive and the explosive forces which are present, we never can tell by the mere outward symptoms to what elementary cause the perversion of a man's will may be due, whether to an increase of one component or a diminution of the other. One may grow explosive as readily by losing the usual brakes as by getting up more of the impulsive steam ; and one may find things impossible as well through the en- feeblement of the original desire as through the advent of new lions in the path. As Dr. Clouston says, " the driver may be so weak that he cannot control well-broken horses, or the horses may be so hard-mouthed that no driver can pull them up." In some concrete cases (whether of explo sive or of obstructed will) it is difficult to tell whether the trouble is due to inhibitory or to impulsive change. Gener ally, "however, we can make a plausible guess at the truth. ^ r THE EXPLOSIVE WILL. \ There is a normal type of character, for example, in which impulses seem to discharge so promptly into move ments that inhibitions get no time to arise. These are the 538 PSYCHOLOGY. ' dare-devil ' and ' mercurial ' temperaments, overflowing with animation, and fizzling with talk, which are so common in the Latin and Celtic races, and with which the cold-blooded and long-headed English character forms so marked a contrast. Monkeys these people seem to us, whilst we seem to them reptilian. It is quite impossible to judge, as between an ob structed and an explosive individual, which has the greatest sum of vital energy. An explosive Italian with good per ception and intellect will cut a figure as a perfectly tre mendous fellow, on an inward capital that could be tucked away inside of an obstructed Yankee and hardly let you know that it was there. He will be the king of his company, sing all the songs and make all the speeches, lead the parties, carry out the practical jokes, kiss all the girls, fight the men, and, if need be, lead the forlorn hopes and enterprises, so that an onlooker would think he has more life in his little finger than can exist in the whole body of a correct judicious fellow. But the judicious fellow all the while may have all these possibilities and more besides, ready to break out in the same or even a more violent way, if only the brakes were taken off. It is the absence of scruples, of conse- , quences, of considerations, the extraordinary simplification of each moment's mental outlook, that gives to the explosive individual such motor energy and ease ; it need not be the greater intensity of any of his passions, motives, or thoughts. As mental evolution goes on, the complexity of human con sciousness grows ever greater, and with it the multiplication of the inhibitions to which every impulse is exposed. But this predominance of inhibition has a bad as well as a good side ; and if a man's impulses are in the main orderly as well as prompt, if he has courage to accept their conse quences, and intellect to lead them to a successful end, he is all the better for his hair-trigger organization, and for not being ' sicklied o'er with the pale cast of thought/ Many of the most successful military and revolutionary"^ characters in history have belonged to this simple but quick witted impulsive type. Problems come much harder to reflective and inhibitive minds. They can, it is true, solve much vaster problems ; and they can avoid many a mis take to which the men of impulse are exposed. But when WILL. 539 the latter do not make mistakes, or when they are always able to retrieve them, theirs is one of the most engaging and indispensable of human types.* In infancy, and in certain conditions of exhaustion as well as in peculiar pathological states, the inhibitory power may fail to arrest the explosions of the impulsive discharge. We have then an explosive temperament temporarily real ized in an individual who at other times may be of a rela tively obstructed type. I cannot do better here than copy a few pages from Dr. Clouston's excellent work : f ** Take a child of six months, and there is absolutely no such brain power existent as mental inhibition ; no desire or tendency is stopped by a mental act. ... At a year old the rudiments of the great faculty of self-control are clearly apparent in most children. They will resist the desire to seize the gas-flame, they will not upset the milk- jug, they will obey orders to sit still when they want to run about, all through a higher mental inhibition. But the power of control is just as gradual a development as the motions of the hands. . . . Look at a more complicated act, that will be recognized by any competent physiologist to be automatic and beyond the control of any ordinary inhibitory power, e.g., irritate and tease a child of one or two years sufficiently, and it will suddenly strike out at you ; suddenly strike at a man, and he will either perform an act of defence or offence, or both, quite automatically, and without power of controlling himself. Place a bright tempting toy before a child of a year, and it will be in stantly appropriated. Place cold water before a man dying of thirst, and he will take and drink it without power of doing otherwise. Ex- *In an excellent article on The ' Mental Qualities of an Athlete ' in the Harvard Monthly, vol. vi. p. 43, Mr. A. T. Dudley assigns the first place to the rapidly impulsive temperament. " Ask him how, in some complex trick, he performed a certain act, why he pushed or pulled at a certaic in stant, and he will tell you he does not know , he did it by instinct ; or rather his nerves and muscles did it of themselves. . . . Here is the dis tinguishing feature of the good player .- the good player, confident in his training and his practice, in the critical game trusts entirely to his impulse, and does not think out every move. The poor player, unable to trust his impulsive actions, is compelled to think carefully all the time. He thus not only loses the opportunities through his slowness in comprehending the whole situation, but, being compelled to think rapidly all the time, at crit ical points becomes confused ; while the first rate player, not trying to reason, but acting as impulse directs, is continually distinguishing himself and plays the better under the greater pressure." fT. S. Clouston, Clinical Lectures on Mental Diseases (London 1883), pp. 310-318. 640 PSYCHOLOGY. haustion of nervous energy always lessens the inhibitory power. Who is not conscious of this ? ' Irritability ' is one manifestation of this. Many persons have so small a stock of reserve brain-power — that most valuable of all brain-qualities — that it is soon used up, and you see at once that they lose their power of self-control very soon. They are an gels or demons just as they are fresh or tired. That surplus store of energy or resistive force which provides, in persons normally constituted, that moderate excesses in all directions shall do no great harm so long as they are not too often repeated, not being present in these people, overwork, over-drinking, or small debauches leave them at the mercy of their morbid impulses without power of resistance. . . . Woe to the man who uses up his surplus stock of brain-inhibition too near the bitter end, or too often ! . . . The physiological word inhibition can be used synonymously with the psychological and ethical expression self-control, or with the will when exercised in certain directions. It is the charac teristic of most forms of mental disease for self-control to be lost, but this loss is usually part of a general mental affection with melancholic, maniacal, demented, or delusional symptoms as the chief manifestation of the disease. There are other cases, not so numerous, where the loss of the power of inhibition is the chief and by far the most marked symptom. ... I shall call this form 'Inhibitory Insanity.' Some of these cases have uncontrollable impulses to violence and destruction, others to homicide, others to suicide prompted by no depressed feel ings, others to acts of animal gratification (satyriasis, nympho- mania, erotomania, bestiality), others to drinking too much alcohol (dipsomania), others towards setting things on fire (pyromania), others to stealing (kleptomania), and others towards immoralities of all sorts. The impulsive tendencies and morbid desires are innumerable in kind. Many of these varieties of Insanity have been distinguished by distinct names. To dig up and eat dead bodies (necrophilism), to wander from home and throw off the restraints of society (planomania), to act like a wild beast (lycanthropia), etc. Action from impulse in all these direc tions may take place from a loss of controlling power in the higher re gions of the brain, or from an over-development of energy in certain portions of the brain, which the normal power of inhibition cannot control. The driver maybe so weak that he cannot control well-broken horses, or the horses may be so hard-mouthed that no driver can pull them up. Both conditions may arise from purely cerebral disorder .... or may be reflex. . . . The ego, the man, the will, may be non-existent for the time. The most perfect examples of this are murders done during somnambulism or epileptic unconsciousness, or acts done in the hypnotic state. There is no conscious desire to attain the object at all in such cases. In other cases there is consciousness and memory present, but no power of restraining action. The simplest example of this is where an imbecile or dement, seeing something glittering, appro priates it to himself, or when he commits indecent sexual acts. Through disease a previously sane and vigorous-minded person may get into the WILL. 541 same state. The motives that would lead other persons not to do such acts do not operate in such persons. I have known a man steal who said he had no intense longing for the article he appropriated at all, at least consciously, but his will was in abeyance, and he could not resist the ordinary desire of possession common to all human nature." It is not only those technically classed imbeciles and dements who exhibit this promptitude of impulse and tardi ness of inhibition. Ask half the common drunkards you know why it is that they fall so often a prey to temptation, and they will say that most of the time they cannot telL It is a sort of vertigo with them. Their nervous centres have become a sluice-way pathologically unlocked by every passing conception of a bottle and a glass. They do not thirst for the beverage ; the taste of it may even appear repug nant ; and they perfectly foresee the morrow's remorse. But when they think of the liquor or see it, they find them selves preparing to drink, and do not stop themselves : and more than this they cannot say. Similarly a man may lead a life of incessant love-making or sexual indulgence, though what spurs him thereto seems rather to be sug gestions and notions of possibility than any overweening strength in his affections or lusts. He may even be physi cally impotent all the while. The paths of natural (or it may be unnatural) impulse are so pervious in these charac ters that the slightest rise in the level of innervation pro duces an overflow. It is the condition recognized in pathol ogy as 'irritable weakness.' The phase known as nascency or latency is so short in the excitement of the neural tissues that there is no opportunity for strain or tension to accumu late within them; and the consequence is that with all the agitation and activity, the amount of real feeling engaged may be very small. The hysterical temperament is the play ground par excellence of this unstable equilibrium. One of these subjects will be filled with what seems the most genu ine and settled aversion to a certain line of conduct, and the very next instant follow the stirring of temptation and plunge in it up to the neck. Professor Eibot well gives the name of ' Le Kegne des Caprices ' to the chapter in which he describes the hysterical temperament in his interesting little monograph 'The Diseases of the Will.' 542 PSYCHOLOGY. Disorderly and impulsive conduct may, on the other hand, come about where the neural tissues preserve their proper inward tone, and where the inhibitory power is nor mal or even unusually great. In such cases the strength of the impulsive idea is preternaturally exalted, and what would be for most people the passing suggestion of a possibility becomes a gnawing, craving urgency to act. Works on in sanity are full of examples of these morbid insistent ideas, iu obstinately struggling against which the unfortunate victim's soul often sweats with agony, ere at last it gets swept away. One instance will stand for many ; M. Kibot quotes it from Calmeil : * " Glenadal, having lost his father in infancy, was brought up by his mother, whom he adored. At sixteen, his character, till then good iind docile, changed. He became gloomy and taciturn. Pressed with questions by his mother, he decided at last to make a confession. ' To you,' said he, ' I owe everything ; I love you with all my soul ; yet for some time past an incessant idea drives me to kill you. Prevent so terrible a misfortune from happening, in case some day the temptation should overpower me : allow me to enlist.' Notwithstanding pressing solicitations, he was firm in his resolve, went off, and was a good soldier. Still a secret impulse stimulated him without cessation to desert in order to come home and kill his mother. At the end of his term of service the idea was as strong as on the first day. He enlisted for another term. The murderous instinct persisted, but substituted another victim. He no longer thought of killing his mother — the hor rible impulse pointed day and night towards his sister-in-law. In order to resist the second impulse, he condemned himself to perpetual exile. At this time one of his old neighbors arrived in the regiment. Glena dal confesses all his trouble. ' Be at rest,' said the other. ' Your crime is impossible; your sister-in-law has just died.' At these words Glena dal rises like a delivered captive. Joy fills his heart. He travels to the home of his childhood, unvisited for so many years. But as he arrives he sees his sister-in-law living. He gives a cry, and the terrible impulse seizes him again as a prey. That very evening he makes his brother tie him fast. * Take a solid rope, bind me like a wolf in the barn, and go and tell Dr. Calmeil. . . . ' From him he got admission to an insane asylum. The evening before his entrance he wrote to the director of the establishment: 'Sir, I am to become an inmate of your house. I shall behave there as if 1 were in the regiment. You will think me cured. At moments perhaps I shall pretend to be so. Never believe me. Never let me out on any pretext. If I beg to be released, double * In his Maladies de la Volonte, p. 77. WILL. 543 your watchfulness ; the only use I shall make of my liberty will be to commit a crime which I abhor.' " The craving for drink in real dipsomaniacs, or for opium or chloral in those subjugated, is of a strength of which normal persons can form no conception. "Were a keg of rum in one corner of a room and were a cannon con stantly discharging balls between me and it, I could not refrain from passing before that cannon in order to get the rum;" "If a bottle of brandy stood at one hand and the pit of hell yawned at the other, and I were convinced that I should be pushed in as sure as I took one glass, I could not refrain :" such statements abound in dipsomaniacs' mouths. Dr. Mussey of Cincinnati relates this case : * ' A few years ago a tippler was put into an almshouse in this State. Within a few days he had devised various expedients to procure rum, but failed. At length, however, he hit upon one which was successful. He went into the wood-yard of the establishment, placed one hand upon the block, and with an axe in the other, struck it off at a single blow. With the stump raised and streaming he ran into the house and cried, 4 Get some rum ! get some rum! my hand is off! ' In the confusion and bustle of the occasion a bowl of rum was brought, into which he plunged the bleeding member of his body, then raising the bowl to his mouth, drank freely, and exultingly exclaimed, ' Now I am satisfied.' Dr. J. E. Turner tells of a man who, while under treatment for inebriety, during four weeks secretly drank the alcohol from six jars containing morbid specimens. On asking him why he had committed this loath some act, he replied: ' Sir, it is as impossible for me to control this dis eased appetite as it is for me to control the pulsations of my heart.' " f The passion of love may be called a monomania to which all of us are subject, however otherwise sane. It can coexist with contempt and even hatred for the ' object ' which inspires it, and whilst it lasts the whole life of the man is altered by its presence. Alfieri thus describes the struggles of his unusually powerful inhibitive power with his abnormally excited impulses toward a certain lady : "Contemptible in my own eyes, I fell into such a state of melan choly as would, if long continued, inevitably have led to insanity or * For other cases of ' impulsive insanity,' see H. Maudsley's Responsi bility in Mental Disease, pp. 133-170, and Forbes Winslow's Obscure Diseases of the Mind and Brain, chapters vr, vn, viii. f Quoted by G. Burr, in an article on the Insanity of Inebriety in the N. Y. Psychological and Medico-Legal Journal, Dec. 1874. 544 PSYCHOLOGY. death. I continued to wear my disgraceful fetters till towards the end of January, 1775, when my rage, which had hitherto so often been re strained within bounds, broke forth with the greatest violence. On returning one evening from the opera (the most insipid and tiresome amusement in Italy), where I had passed several hours in the box of the woman who was by turns the object of my antipathy and my love, I took the firm determination of emancipating myself forever from her yoke. Experience had taught me that flight, so far from enabling me to persevere in my resolutions, tended on the contrary to weaken and destroy them; I was inclined therefore to subject myself to a still more severe trial, imagining from the obstinacy and peculiarity of my char acter that I should succeed most certainly by the adoption of such measures as. would compel me to make the greatest efforts. I deter mined never to leave the house, which, as I have already said, was exactly opposite that of the lady; to gaze at her windows, to see her go in and out every day, to listen to the sound of her voice, though firmly resolved that no advances on her part, either direct or indirect, no tender remembrances, nor in short any other means which might be employed, should ever again tempt me to a revival of our friendship. I was determined to die or liberate myself from my disgraceful thraldom. In order to give stability to my purpose, and to render it impossible for me to waver without the imputation of dishonor, I communicated my determination to one of my friends, who was greatly attached to me, and whom I highly esteemed. He had lamented the state of mind into which I had fallen, but not wishing to give countenance to my conduct, and seeing the impossibility of inducing me to abandon it, he had for some time ceased to visit at my house. In the few lines which I ad dressed to him, I briefly stated the resolution I had adopted, and as a pledge of my constancy I sent him a long tress of my ugly red hair. I had purposely caused it to be cut off in order to prevent my going out, as no one but clowns and sailors then appeared in public with short hair. I concluded my billet by conjuring him to strengthen and aid my fortitude by his presence and example. Isolated in this manner in my own house, I prohibited all species of intercourse, and passed the first fifteen days in uttering the most frightful lamentations and groans. Some of my friends came to visit me, and appeared to commiserate my situation, perhaps because I did not myself complain; but my figure and whole appearance bespoke my sufferings. Wishing to read some thing I had recourse to the gazettes, whole pages of which I frequently ran over without understanding a single word. . . I passed more than two months till the end of March 1775, in a state bordering on frenzy; but about this time a new idea darted into my mind, which tended to assuage my melancholy." This was the idea of poetical composition, at which Alfieri describes his first attempts, made under these dis eased circumstances, and goes on : WILL. 645 " The only good that occurred to me from this whim was that of gradually detaching me from love, and of awakening my reason which had so long lain dormant. I no longer found it necessary to cause my self to be tied with cords to a chair, in order to prevent me from leaving my house and returning to that of my lady. This had been one of the expedients I devised to render myself wise by force. The cords were concealed under a large mantle in which I was enveloped, and only one hand remained at liberty. Of all those who came to see me, not one suspected I was bound down in this manner. I remained in this situa tion for whole hours; Elias, who was my jailer, was alone intrusted with the secret. He always liberated me, as he had been enjoined, whenever the paroxysms of my rage subsided. Of all the whimsical methods which I employed, however, the most curious was that of appearing in masquerade at the theatre towards the end of the carnival. Habited as Apollo, I ventured to present myself with a lyre, on which I played as well as I was able and sang some bad verses of my own composing. Such effrontery was diametrically opposite to my natural character. The only excuse I can offer for such scenes was my inability to resist an imperious passion. I felt that it was necessary to place an insuperable barrier between its object and me; and I saw that the strongest of all was the shame to which I should expose myself by renewing an attach ment which I had so publicly turned into ridicule." * Often the insistent idea is of a trivial sort, but it may wear the patient's life out. His hands feel dirty, they must be washed. He knows they are not dirty ; yet to get rid of the teasing idea he washes them. The idea, however, returns in a moment, and the unfortunate victim, who is not in the least deluded intellectually, will end by spending the whole day at the wash-stand. Or his clothes are not ' rightly ' put on ; and to banish the thought he takes them off and puts them on again, till his toilet consumes two or three hours of time. Most people have the potentiality of this disease. To few has it not happened to conceive, after get ting into bed, that they may have forgotten to lock the front door, or to turn out the entry gas. And few of us have not on some occasion got up to repeat the perform ance, less because they believed in the reality of its omis sion than because only so could they banish the worrying doubt and get to sleep, t * Autobiography, Howells' edition (1877), pp. 192-6. t See a paper on Insistent and Fixed Ideas by Dr. Cowles in American Journal of Psychology, i. 222 ; and another on the so-called Insanity of Doubt by Dr. Knapp, ibid. in. 1. The latter contains a partial bibliogiaphy of the subject. 646 PSYCHOLOGY. THE OBSTRUCTED WILL. In striking contrast with the cases in which inhibition is insufficient or impulsion in excess are those in which impulsion is insufficient or inhibition of in excess. We all know the condition described on p. 404 of Yol. I, in which the mind for a few moments seems to lose its focussing power and to be unable to rally its attention to any determinate thing. At such times we sit blankly staring and do nothing. The objects of consciousness fail to touch the quick or break the skin. They are there, but do not reach the level of effect iveness. This state of non-efficacious presence is the nor mal condition of some objects, in all of us. Great fatigue or exhaustion may make it the condition of almost all ob jects ; and an apathy resembling that then brought about is recognized in asylums under the name of abulia as a symptom of mental disease. The healthy state of the will requires, as aforesaid, both that vision should be right, and that action should obey its lead. But in the morbid con dition in question the vision may be wholly unaffected, and the intellect clear, and yet the act either fails to follow or follows in some other way. " Video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor " is the classic expression of the latter con dition of mind. The former it is to which the name abulia peculiarly applies. The patients, says Guislain, " are able to will inwardly, mentally, according to the dictates of reason. They experience the desire to act, but they are powerless to act as they should. . . . Their will cannot overpass certain limits : one would say that the force of action within them is blocked up :' the I will does not transform itself into impulsive volition, into active determination. Some of these patients wonder themselves at the impotence with which their will is smitten. If you abandon them to themselves, they pass whole days in their bed or on a chair. If one speaks to them or excites them, they express themselves properly though briefly ; and judge of things pretty well. " * In Chapter XXI, as will be remembered, it was said that the sentiment of reality with which an object ap pealed to the mind is proportionate (amongst other things) to its efficacy as a stimulus to the will. Here we get the * Quoted by Ribot, ov cit. p. 39. WILL. 547 obverse side of the truth. Those ideas, objects, con siderations, which (in these lethargic states) fail to get to the •will, fail to draw blood, seem, in so far forth, distant and un real. The connection of the reality of things with their effectiveness as motives is a tale that has never yet been fully told. The moral tragedy of human life comes almost wholly from the fact that the link is ruptured which nor mally should hold between vision of the truth and action, and that this pungent sense of effective reality will not at tach to certain ideas. Men do not differ so much in their mere feelings and conceptions. Their notions of possibility and their ideals are not as far apart as might be argued from their differing fates. No class of them have better sentiments or feel more constantly the difference between the higher and the lower path in life than the hopeless failures, the sentimentalists, the drunkards, the schemers, the * dead-beats,' whose life is one long contradiction between knowledge and action, and who, with full com mand of theory, never get to holding their limp characters erect. No one eats of the fruit of the tree of knowledge as they do ; as far as moral insight goes, in comparison with them, the orderly and prosperous philistines whom they scandalize are sucking babes. And yet their moral knowledge, always there grumbling and rumbling in the background, — discerning, commenting, protesting, longing, half resolving, — never wholly resolves, never gets its voice out of the minor into the major key, or its speech out of the subjunctive into the imperative mood, never breaks the spell, never takes the helm into its hands. In such characters as Eousseau and Kestif it would seem as if the lower motives had all the impulsive efficacy in their hands. Like trains with the right of way, they retain ex clusive possession of the track. The more ideal motives exist alongside of them in profusion, but they never get switched on, and the man's conduct is no more influenced by them than an express train is influenced by a wayfarer standing by the roadside and calling to be taken aboard. They are an inert accompaniment to the end of time ; and the consciousness of inward hollowness that accrues from habitually seeing the better only to do the worse, is one of 548 PSYCHOLOGY. the saddest feelings one can bear with him through this vale of tears. We now see at one view when it is that effort complicates volition. It does so whenever a rarer and more ideal im pulse is called upon to neutralize others of a more instinc tive and habitual kind ; it does so whenever strongly ex plosive tendencies are checked, or strongly obstructive conditions overcome. The dme bien nee, the child of the sunshine, at whose birth the fairies made their gifts, does not need much of it in his life. The hero and the neurotic subject, on the other hand, do. Now our spontaneous way of conceiving the effort, under all these circumstances, is as an active force adding its strength to that of the motives which ultimately prevail. When outer forces impinge upon a body, we say that the resultant motion is in the line of least resistance, or of greatest traction. But it is a curious fact that our spontaneous language never speaks of volition with effort in this way. Of course if we proceed a priori and define the line of least resistance as the line that is followed, the physical law must also hold good in the mental sphere. But we feel, in all hard cases of volition, as if the line taken, when the rarer and mere ideal motives prevail, were the line of greater resistance, and as if the line of coarser motivation were the more pervious and easy one, even at the very moment when we refuse to follow it. He who under the surgeon's knife represses cries of pain, or he who exposes himself to social obloquy for duty's sake, feels as if he were following the line of greatest temporary resistance. He speaks of conquering and overcoming his impulses and temptations. But the sluggard, the drunkard, the coward, never talk of their conduct in that way or say they resist their energy, overcome their sobriety, conquer their courage, and so forth. If in general we class all springs of action as pro- pensities on the one hand and ideals on the other, the sen sualist never says of his behavior that it results from a victory over his ideals, but the moralist always speaks of his as a victory over his propensities. The sensualist uses terms of inactivity, says he forgets his ideals, is deaf to WILL. 549 duty, and so forth ; which terms seem to imply that the ideal motives per se can be annulled without energy or •effort, and that the strongest mere traction lies in the line of the propensities. The ideal impulse appears, in compar ison with this, a still small voice which must be artificially reinforced to prevail. Effort is what reinforces it, making things seem as if, while the force of propensity were essen tially a fixed quantity, the ideal force might be of various amount. But what determines the amount of the effort when, by its aid, an ideal motive becomes victorious over a great sensual resistance ? The very greatness of the resist ance itself. If the sensual propensity is small, the effort is small. The latter is made great by the presence of a great antagonist to overcome. And if a brief definition of ideal or moral action were required, none could be given which would better fit the appearances than this : It is action in the line of the greatest resistance. The facts may be most briefly symbolized thus, P stand ing for the propensity, I for the ideal impulse, and E for the effort : I per se < P. I + E > P. In other words, if E adds itself to I, P immediately offers the least resistance, and motion occurs in spite of it. But the E does not seem to form an integral part of the I. It appears adventitious and indeterminate in advance. We can make more or less as we please, and if we make enough we can convert the greatest mental resistance into the least. Such, at least, is the impression which the facts spontaneously produce upon us. But we will not discuss the truth of this impression at present ; let us rather con tinue our descriptive detail. PLEASURE AND PAIN AS SPRINGS OP ACTION. Objects and thoughts of objects start our action, but the pleasures and pains which action brings modify its course and regulate it ; and later the thoughts of the pleas ures and the pains acquire themselves impulsive and in- 550 PSYCHOLOGY. hibitive power. Not that the thought of a pleasure need be itself a pleasure, usually it is the reverse — nessun mag- gior dolore — as Dante says — and not that the thought of pain meed be a pain, for, as Homer says, " griefs are often after wards an entertainment." But as present pleasures are tremendous reinforcers, and present pains tremendous in hibitors of whatever action leads to them, so the thoughts of pleasures and pains take rank amongst the thoughts which have most impulsive and inhibitive power. The precise relation which these thoughts hold to other thoughts is thus a matter demanding some attention. If a movement feels agreeable, we repeat and repeat it as long as the pleasure lasts. If it hurts us, our muscular contractions at the instant stop. So complete is the inhibi tion in this latter case that it is almost impossible for a man to cut or mutilate himself slowly and deliberately — his hand invincibly refusing to bring on the pain. And there are many pleasures which, when once we have begun to taste them, make it all but obligatory to keep up the activ ity to which they are due. So widespread and searching is this influence of pleasures and pains upon our movements that a premature philosophy has decided that these are our only spurs to action, and that wherever they seem to be absent, it is only because they are so far on among the * remoter ' images that prompt the action that they are over looked. This is a great mistake, however. Important as is the influence of pleasures and pains upon our movements, they are far from being our only stimuli. With the manifesta tions of instinct and emotional expression, for example, they have absolutely nothing to do. Who smiles for the pleasure of the smiling, or frowns for the pleasure of the frown ? Who blushes to escape the discomfort of not blushing ? Or who in anger, grief, or fear is actuated to the movements which he makes by the pleasures which they yield ? In all these cases the movements are discharged fatally by the vis a tergo which the stimulus exerts upon a nervous system framed to respond in just that way. The objects of our rage, love, or terror, the occasions of our tears and smiles, WILL. 551 whether they be present to our senses, or whether they be merely represented in idea, have this peculiar sort of im pulsive power. The impulsive quality of mental states is an attribute behind which we cannot go. Some states of mind have more of it than others, some have it in this direction, and some in that. Feelings of pleasure and pain have it, and perceptions and imaginations of fact have it, but neither have it exclusively or peculiarly. It is of the essence of all consciousness (or of the neural process which underlies it) to instigate movement of some sort. That with one creature and object it should be of one sort, with others of another sort, is a problem for evolutionary history to explain. However the actual impulsions may have arisen, they must now be described as they exist ; and those persons obey a curiously narrow teleological superstition who think them selves bound to interpret them in every instance as effects of the secret solicitancy of pleasure and repugnancy of pain.* * The silliness of the old-fashioned pleasure-philosophy saute aux yeux. Take, for example, Prof. Bain's explanation of sociability and parental love by the pleasures of touch: "Touch is the fundamental and generic sense. . . . Even after the remaining senses are differentiated, the primary sense continues to be a leading susceptibility of the miud. The soft warm touch, if not a first-class influence, is at least an approach to that. The combined power of soft contact and warmth amounts to a considerable pitch of massive pleasure ; while there may be subtle influences not redu cible to these two heads, such as we term, from not knowing anything about them, magnetic or electric. The sort of thrill from taking a baby in arms is something beyond mere warm touch ; and it may rise to the ecstatic height, in which case, however, there may be concurrent sensations and ideas. ... In mere tender emotion not sexual, there is nothing but the sense of touch to gratify, unless we assume the occult magnetic influences. . . . In a word, our love pleasures begin and end in sensual contact. Touch is both the alpha and omega of affection. As the terminal and satisfying sensation, the ne plus ultra, it must be a pleasure of the highest degree. . . . Why should a more lively feeling grow up towards a fellow-being than towards a perennial fountain ? [This ' should ' is simply delicious from the more modern evolutionary point of view.] It must be that there is a source of pleasure in the companionship of other sentient creatures, over and above the help afforded by them in obtaining the necessaries of life. To account for this, I can suggest nothing but the primary and independent pleasure of the animal embrace." [Mind, this is said not of the sexual interest, but of ' Sociability at Large.'] " For this pleasure every creature is disposed to pay something, even when it is only fraternal. A certain 552 PSYCHOLOGY. It might be that to reflection such a narrow teleology would justify itself, that pleasures and pains might seem the only comprehensible and reasonable motives for action, the only motives on which we ought to act. That is an ethical proposition, in favor of which a good deal may be said. But it is not a psychological proposition ; and nothing fol lows from it as to the motives upon which as a matter of fact we do act. These motives are supplied by innumerable objects, which innervate our voluntary muscles by a process c tibi erit janua leti" we feel. There is something so icy in this cold-water bath, something which seems so hostile to the movement of our life, so purely negative, in Eeason, when she lays her corpse-like finger on our heart and says, " Halt! give up ! leave off! go back ! sit down !" that it is no wonder that to most men the steadying influence seems, for the time being, a very minister of death. The strong-willed man, however, is the man who hears the still small voice unflinchingly, and who, when the death-bringing consideration comes, looks at its face, con sents to its presence, clings to it, affirms it, and holds it fast, in spite of the host of exciting mental images which 564 PSYCHOLOGY. rise in revolt against it and would expel it from the mind. Sustained in this way by a resolute effort of attention, the difficult object erelong begins to call up its own congeners and associates and ends by changing the disposition of the man's consciousness altogether. And with his conscious ness, his action changes, for the new object, once stably in possesion of the field of his thoughts, infallibly produces its own motor effects. The difficulty lies in the gaining possession of that field. Though the spontaneous drift of thought is all the other way, the attention must be kept strained on that one object until at last it grows, so as to maintain itself before the mind with ease. This strain of the attention is the fundamental act of will. And the will's work is in most cases practically ended when the bare pres ence to our thought of the naturally unwelcome object has been secured. For the mysterious tie between the^thought and the motor centres next comes into play, and, in a way which we cannot even guess at, the obedience of the bodily organs follows as a matter of course. In all this one sees how the immediate point of appli cation of the volitional effort lies exclusively in the mental world. The whole drama is a mental drama. The whole difficulty is a mental difficulty, a difficulty with an object of our thought. If I may use the word idea without suggest ing associationist or Herbartian fables, I will say that it is an idea to which our will applies itself, an idea which if wa let it go would slip away, but which we will not let go. Consent to the idea's undivided presence, this is effort's sole achievement. Its only function is to get this feeling of consent into the mind. And for this there is but one way. The idea to be consented to must be kept from flickering and going out. It must be held steadily before the mind until \ifiUs the mind. Such filling of the mind by an idea, with its congruous associates, is consent to the idea and to the fact which the idea represents. If the idea be that, or include that, of a bodily movement of our own, then we call the consent thus laboriously gained a motor volition. For Nature here ' backs ' us instantaneously and follows up our inward willingness by outward changes on her own part. She does this in no other instance. Pity she should not WILL. 565 have been more generous, nor made a world whose other parts were as immediately subject to our will ! On page 531, in describing the ' reasonable type ' of de cision, it was said that it usually came when the right con ception of the case was found. Where, however, the right conception is an anti-inpulsive one, the whole intellectual ingenuity of the man usually goes to work to crowd it out of sight, and to find names for the emergency, by the help of which the dispositions of the moment may sound sancti fied, and sloth or passion may reign unchecked. How many excuses does the drunkard find when each new temptation comes ! It is a new brand of liquor which the interests of intellectual culture in such matters oblige him to test ; moreover it is poured out and it is sin to waste it ; or others are drinking and it would be churlishness to refuse ; or it is but to enable him to sleep, or just to get through this job of work ; or it isn't drinking, it is because he feels so cold ; or it is Christmas-day ; or it is a means of stimulating him to make a more powerful resolution in favor of abstinence than any he has hitherto made ; or it is just this once, and once doesn't count, etc., etc., ad libitum — it is, in fact, any thing you like except being a drunkard. That is the concep tion that will not stay before the poor soul's attention. But if he once gets able to pick out that way of conceiving, from all the other possible ways of conceiving the various op portunities which occur, if through thick and thin he holds to it that this is being a drunkard and is nothing else, he is not likely to remain one long. The effort by which he succeeds in keeping the right name unwaveringly present to his mind proves to be his saving moral act* Everywhere then the function of the effort is the same: to keep affirming and adopting a thought which, if left to itself, would slip away. It may be cold and flat when the spontaneous mental drift is towards excitement, or great and arduous when the spontaneous drift is towards repose. In the one case the effort has to inhibit an explosive, in the * Of. Aristotle's Nichomachasan Ethics, vn. 3 ; also a discussion of the doctrine of ' The Practical Syllogism ' in Sir A. Grant's edition of thig work, 2d ed. vol. i. p. 212 ff. 666 PSYCHOLOGY. other to arouse an obstructed will. The exhausted sailor on a wreck has a will which is obstructed. One of his ideas is that of his sore hands, of the nameless exhaustion of his whole frame which the act of farther pumping in volves, and of the deliciousness of sinking into sleep. The other is that of the hungry sea ingulfing him. " Eathei the aching toil !" he says ; and it becomes reality then, in spite of the inhibiting influence of the relatively luxurious . sensations which he gets from lying still. But exactly similar in form would be his consent to lie and sleep. Often it is the thought of sleep and what leads to it which is the hard one to keep before the mind. If a patient afflicted with insomnia can only control the whirling chase of his thoughts so far as to think of nothing at all (which can be done), or so far as to imagine one letter after another of a verse of scripture or poetry spelt slowly and monotonously out, it is almost certain that here, too, specific bodily effects will follow, and that sleep will come. The trouble is to keep the mind upon a train of objects naturally so insipid. To sustain a representation, to think, is, in short, the only moral 0<3t, for the impulsive and the obstructed, for sane and lunatics alike. Most maniacs know their thoughts to be crazy, but find them too pressing to be withstood. Com pared with them the sane truths are so deadly sober, so cadaverous, that the lunatic cannot bear to look them in the face and say, "Let these alone be my reality !" But with sufficient effort, as Dr. Wigan says, " Such a man can for a time wind himself up, as it were, and deter mine that the notions of the disordered brain shall not be manifested. Many instances are on record similar to that told by Pinel, where an inmate of the Bicetre, having stood a long cross-examination, and given every mark of restored reason, signed his name to the paper authorizing his discharge • Jesus Christ, ' and then went off into all the vagaries connected with that delusion. In the phraseology of the gentleman whose case is related in an early part of this [Wigan's] work he had ' held himself tight ' during the examination in order to attain his object; this once accomplished he ' let himself down ' again, and, if even conscious of his delusion, could not control it. I have observed with such persons that it requires a considerable time to wind them selves up to the pitch of complete self-control, that the effort is a pain ful tension of the mind. . . . When thrown off their guard by any accidental remark or worn out by the length of the examination, thej WILL. 567 let themselves go, and cannot gather themselves up again without prep aration. Lord Erskine relates the story of a man who brought an action against Dr. Munro for confining him without cause. He under went the most rigid examination by the counsel for the defendant with out discovering any appearance of insanity, till a gentleman asked him about a princess with whom he corresponded in cherry-juice, and he became instantly insane."* To sum it all up in a word, the terminus of the psychologi cal process in volition, the point to which the will is directly ap plied, is alivays an idea. There are at all times some ideas *vom which we shy away like frightened horses the moment we get a glimpse of their forbidding profile upon the threshold of our thought. The only resistance which our tvill can possibly experience is the resistance which such an idea offers to being attended to at all. To attend to it is the voli tional act, and the only inward volitional act which we ever perform. I have put the thing in this ultra-simple way because I want more than anything else to emphasize the fact that volition is primarily a relation, not between our Self and * The Duality of the Mind, pp. 141-2. Another case from the same book (p 123): " A gentleman of respectable birth, excellent education, And ample fortune, engaged in one of the highest departments of trade, . . . and being induced to embark in one of the plausible speculations of the day . . . was utterly ruined. Like other men he could bear a sudden overwhelming reverse better than a long succession of petty misfortunes, and the way in which he conducted himself on the occasion met with un bounded admiration from his friends. He withdrew, however, into rigid seclusion, and being no longer able to exercise the generosity and indulge the benevolent feelings which had formed the happiness of his life, made himself a substitute for them by daydreams, gradually fell into a state of irritable despondency, from which he only gradually recovered with the loss of reason. He now fancied himself possessed of immense wealth, and gave without stint his imaginary riches. He has ever since been under gentle restraint, and leads a life not merely of happiness, but of bliss ; con verses rationally, reads the newspapers, where every tale of distress attracts his notice, and being furnished with an abundant supply of blank checks, he tills up one of them with a munificent sum, sends it off to the sufferer, and sits down to his dinner with a happy conviction that he has earned the right to a little indulgence in the pleasures of the table ; and yet, on a serious conversation with one of his old friends, he is quite conscious of his real position, but the conviction is so exquisitely painful th&theunU not let himself believe it." 568 PSYCHOLOGY. extra-mental matter (as many philosophers still maintain), but between our Self and our own states of mind. But when, a short while ago, I spoke of the filling of the mind with an idea as being equivalent to consent to the idea's object, I said something which the reader doubtless ques tioned at the time, and which certainly now demands some qualification ere we pass beyond. It is unqualifiedly true that if any thought do fill the mind exclusively, such filling is consent. The thought, for that time at any rate, carries the man and his will with it. But it is not true that the thought need fill the mind ex clusively for consent to be there ; for we often consent to things whilst thinking of other things, even of hostile things ; and we saw in fact that precisely what distinguishes our ' fifth type ' of decision from the other types (see p. 534) is just this coexistence with the triumphant thought of other thoughts which would inhibit it but for the effort which makes it prevail. The effort to attend is therefore only a part of what the word ' will ' covers ; it covers also the effort to consent to something to which our attention is not quite complete. Often, when an object has gained our attention exclusively, and its motor results are just on the point of setting in, it seems as if the sense of their immi nent irrevocability were enough of itself to start up the in hibitory ideas and to make us pause. Then we need a new stroke of effort to break down the sudden hesitation which seizes upon us, and to persevere. So that although atten tion is the first and fundamental thing in volition, express consent to the reality of what is attended to is often an ad ditional and quite distinct phenomenon involved. The reader's own consciousness tells him of course just what these words of mine denote. And I freely confess that I am impotent to carry the analysis of the matter any farther, or to explain in other terms of what this consent consists. It seems a subjective experience sui generis, which we can designate but not define. We stand here exactly where we did in the case of belief. When an idea stings us in a certain way, makes as it were a certain electric connec tion with our self, we believe that it is a reality. When it stings us in another way, makes another connection with WILL. 569 our Self, we say, let it be a reality. To the word 'is ' and to the words ' let it be ' there correspond peculiar attitudes of consciousness which it is vain to seek to explain. The indicative and the imperative moods are as much ultimate categories of thinking as they are of grammar. The ' qual ity of reality ' which these moods attach to things is not like other qualities. It is a relation to our life. It means our adoption of the things, our caring for them, our stand ing by them. This at least is what it practically means for us ; what it may mean beyond that we do not know. And the transition from merely considering an object as possible, to deciding or willing it to be real ; the change from the fluctuating to the stable personal attitude concern ing it ; from the ' don't care ' state of mind to that in which 4 we mean business,' is one of the most familiar things in life. We can partly enumerate its conditions ; and we can partly trace its consequences, especially the momentous one that when the mental object' is a movement of our own body, it realizes itself outwardly when the mental change in question has occurred. But the change itself as a sub jective phenomenon is something which we can translate into no simpler terms. THE QUESTION OF 'FREE-WILL.' Especially must we, when talking about it, rid our mind of the fabulous warfare of separate agents called ' ideas.' The brain-processes may be agents, and the thought as such may be an agent. But what the ordinary psychologies call ' ideas ' are nothing but parts of the total object of representation. All that is before the mind at once, no matter how complex a system of things and relations it may be, is one object for the thought. Thus, ' A-and-B-and-their- mutual - incompatibility - and - the - fact - that-only -one- can - be-true-or-can - become- real-notwithstanding -the-probabil- ity-or-desirability-of-both ' may be such a complex object ; and where the thought is deliberative its object has always some such form as this. When, now, we pass from delib eration to decision, that total object undergoes a change. We either dismiss A altogether and its relations to B, and think of B exclusively ; or after thinking of both as possi- 570 PSYCHOLOGY. bilities, we next think that A is impossible, and that B is or forthwith shall be real. In either case a new object is before our thought ; and where effort exists, it is where the change from the first object to the second one is hard. Our thought seems to turn in this case like a heavy door on rusty hinges ; only, so far as the effort feels spontaneous, it turns, not as if by some one helping, but as if by an inward activity, born for the occasion, of its own. The psychologists who discussed ' the muscular sense ' at the international congress at Paris in 1889 agreed at the end that they needed to come to a better understanding in regard to this appearance of internal activity at the moment when a decision is made. M. Fouillee, in an article which I find more interesting and suggestive than coherent or conclusive,* seems to resolve our sense of activity into that of our very existence as thinking entities. At least so I translate his words, t But we saw in Chapter X how hard it is to lay a verifying finger plainly upon the thinking process as such, and to distinguish it from certain objects of the stream. M. Fouillee admits this ; but I do not think he fully realizes how strong would be the position of a man who should suggest (see Yol. I. p. 301) that the feeling of moral activity itself which accompanies the advent of cer tain « objects ' before the mind is nothing but certain other objects, — constrictions, namely, in the brows, eyes, throat, and breathing apparatus, present then, but absent from other pulses of subjective change. Were this the truth, then a part, at any rate, of the activity of which we become aware in effort would seem merely to be that of our body ; and many thinkers would probably thereupon conclude that this ' settles the claims ' of inner activity, and dismisses the whole notion of such a thing as a superfluity in psy chological science. I cannot see my way to so extreme a view ; even al though I must repeat the confession made on pp. 296-7 of Yol. I, that I do not fully understand how we come to our unshakable belief that thinking exists as a special kind of * ' Le Sentiment de 1'Effort, et la Conscience de 1'Action,' in Revue Philosophique, xxvm. 561. t ?• 577 WILL. 571 immaterial process alongside of the material processes of the world. It is certain, however, that only by postulating such thinking do we make things currently intelligible ; and it is certain that no psychologist has as yet denied the fact of thinking, the utmost that has been denied being its dynamic power. But if we postulate the fact of the thinking at all, I believe that we must postulate its power as well ; nor do I see how we can rightly equalize its power with its mere existence, and say (as M. Fouillee seems to say) that for the thought-process to go on at all is an activity, and an activity everywhere the same ; for certain steps forward in this process seem prima facie to be passive, and other steps (as where an object comes with effort) seem prima facie to be active in a supreme degree. If we admit, therefore, that our thoughts exist, we ought to admit that they exist after the fashion in which they appear, as things, namely, that supervene upon each other, sometimes with effort and some times with ease ; the only questions being, is the effort where it exists a fixed function of the object, which the latter imposes on the thought? or is it such an independent 1 variable' that with a constant object more or less of it may be made ? It certainly appears to us indeterminate, and as if, even with an unchanging object, we might make more or less, as we choose. If it be really indeterminate, our future acts are ambiguous or unpredestinate : in common parlance, our ivills are free. If the amount of effort be not indeterminate, but be related in a fixed manner to the objects themselves, in such wise that whatever object at any time fills our consciousness was from eternity bound to fill it then and there, and compel from us the exact effort, neither more nor less, which we bestow upon it, — then our wills are not free, and all our acts are foreordained. The question of fact in the free-will controversy is thus extremely simple. It relates solely to the amount of effort of attention or consent which we can at any time put forth. Are the duration and intensity of this effort fixed functions of the object, or are they not ? Now, as I just said, it seems as if the effort were an inde pendent variable, as if we might exert more or less of it in any given case. When a man has let his thoughts go for 572 PSYCHOLOGY. days and weeks until at last they culminate in some par ticularly dirty or cowardly or cruel act, it is hard to per suade him, in the midst of his remorse, that he might not have reined them in ; hard to make him believe that this whole goodly universe (which his act so jars upon) required and exacted it of him at that fatal moment, and from eternity made aught else impossible. But, on the other hand, there is the certainty that all his effortless volitions are resultants of interests and associations whose strength and sequence are mechanically determined by the structure of that physical mass, his brain ; and the general continuity of things and the monistic conception of the world may lead one irresist ibly to postulate that a little fact like effort can form no real exception to the overwhelming reign of deterministic law. Even in effortless volition we have the consciousness of the alternative being also possible. This is surely a de lusion here ; why is it not a delusion everywhere ? My own belief is that the question of free-will is in soluble on strictly psychologic grounds. After a certain amount of effort of attention has been given to an idea, it is manifestly impossible to tell whether either more or less of it might have been given or not. To tell that, we should have to ascend to the antecedents of the effort, and denn ing them with mathematical exactitude, prove, by laws of which we have not at present even an inkling, that the only amount of sequent effort which could possibly comport with them was the precise amount which actually came. Measurements, whether of psychic or of neural quantities, and deductive reasonings such as this method of proof im plies, will surely be forever beyond human reach. No seri ous psychologist or physiologist will venture even to sug gest a notion of how they might be practically made. We are thrown back therefore upon the crude evidences of in trospection on the one hand, with all its liabilities to de ception, and, on the other hand, upon a priori postulates and probabilities. He who loves to balance nice doubts need be in no hurry to decide the point. Like Mephis- topheles to Faust, he can say to himself, " dazu hast du noch eine lange Frist," for from generation to generation the reasons adduced on both sides will grow more voluminous, WILL. 573 and the discussion more refined. But if our speculative delight be less keen, if the love of a parti pris outweighs that of keeping questions open, or if, as a French philoso pher of genius says, " V amour de la vie qui s'indigne de tant de discours" awakens in us, craving the sense of either peace or power, — then, taking the risk of error on our head, we must project upon one of the alternative views the attribute of reality for us ; we must so fill our mind with the idea of it that it becomes our settled creed. The present writer does this for the alternative of freedom, but since the grounds of his opinion are ethical rather than psychological, he prefers to exclude them from the present book.* A few words, however, may be permitted about the logic of the question. The most that any argument can do for determinism is to make it a clear and seductive concep tion, which a man is foolish not to espouse, so long as he stands by the great scientific postulate that the world must be one unbroken fact, and that prediction of all things without exception must be ideally, even if not actually, possible. It is a moral postulate about the Universe, the postulate that what ought to be can be, and that bad acts cannot be fated, but that good ones must be possible in their place, which would lead one to espouse the contrary view. But when scientific and moral postulates war thus with each other and objective proof is not to be had, the only course is voluntary choice, for scepticism itself, if sys tematic, is also voluntary choice. If, meanwhile, the will be undetermined, it would seem only fitting that the belief in its indetermination should be voluntarily chosen from amongst other possible beliefs. Freedom's first deed should be to affirm itself. We ought never to hope for any other method of getting at the truth if indeterminism be a fact. Doubt of this particular truth will therefore probably be open to us to the end of time, and the utmost that a *They will be found indicated, in somewhat popular form, in a lecture on 'The Dilemma of Determinism,' published in the Unitarian Review (of Boston) for September 1884 (vol. xxn. p. 193). 574 PSYCHOLOGY. believer in free-will can ever do will be to show that the deterministic arguments are not coercive. That they are seductive, I am the last to deny ; nor do I deny that effort may be needed to keep the faith in freedom, when they press upon it, upright in the mind. There is a fatalistic argument for determinism, however, which is radically vicious. When a man has let himself go time after time, he easily becomes impressed with the enormously preponderating influence of circumstances, hereditary habits, and temporary bodily dispositions over what might seem a spontaneity born for the occasion. " All is fate," he then says ; " all is resultant of what pre exists. Even if the moment seems original, it is but the instable molecules passively tumbling in their preappointed way. It is hopeless to resist the drift, vain to look for any new force coming in ; and less, perhaps, than anywhere else under the sun is there anything really mine in the decisions which I make/' This is really no argument for simple determinism. There runs throughout it the sense of a force which might make things otherwise from one moment to another, if it were only strong enough to breast the tide. A person who feels the impotence of free effort in this way has the acutest notion of what is meant by it, and of its possible independent power. How else could he be so conscious of its absence and of that of its effects ? But genuine deter minism occupies a totally different ground ; not the impo tence but the unthinkability of free-will is what it affirms. It admits something phenomenal called free effort, which seems to breast the tide, but it claims this as a portion of the tide. The variations of the effort cannot be independent, it says ; they cannot originate ex nihilo, or come from a fourth dimension; they are mathematically fixed functions of the ideas themselves, which are the tide. Fatalism, which conceives of effort clearly enough as an independent varia ble that might come from a fourth dimension if it would come, but that does not come, is a very dubious ally for determinism. It strongly imagines that very possibility which determinism denies. But what, quite as much as the inconceivability of absolutely independent variables, persuades modern men WILL. 675 of science that their efforts must be predetermined, is the continuity of the latter with other phenomena whose pre determination no one doubts. Decisions with effort merge so gradually into those without it that it is not easy to say where the limit lies. Decisions without effort merge again into ideo-motor, and these into reflex acts ; so that the temptation is almost irresistible to throw the formula which covers so many cases over absolutely all. Where there is effort just as where there is none, the ideas them selves which furnish the matter of deliberation are brought before the mind by the machinery of association. And this machinery is essentially a system of arcs and path&, a reflex system, whether effort be amongst its incidents or not. The reflex way is, after all, the universal way of conceiving the business. The feeling of ease is a passive result of the way in which the thoughts unwind themselves. Why is not the feeling of effort the same? Professor Lipps, in his admirably clear deterministic statement, so far from admitting that the feeling of effort testifies to an increment of force exerted, explains it as a sign that force is lost. We speak of effort, according to him, whenever a force expends itself (wholly or partly) in neutralizing another force, and so fails of its own possible outward effect. The outward effect of the antagonistic force, how ever, also fails in corresponding measure, " so that there is no effort without counter-effort, . . . and effort and coun ter-effort signify only that causes are mutually robbing each other of effectiveness." Where the forces are ideas, both sets of them, strictly speaking, are the seat of effort — both those which tend to explode, and those which tend to check them. We, however, call the more abundant mass of ideas ourselves; and, talking of its effort as our effort, and of that of the smaller mass of ideas as the resistance^ we say that our effort sometimes overcomes the resistances offered by the inertias of an obstructed, and sometimes * See Grundtatsachen des Seelenlebens, pp. 594-5 ; and compare the conclusion of our own chapter on Attention, Vol. I. pp. 448-454. f Thus at least 1 interpret Prof. Lipps's words: " Wir wissen tins natur- gemass iu jedeiii tttreben umsomehr aktiv, je mehr uuser gauzes Ich bei dem Striibr.n belheiligt 1st," u. s. w. (p. 601). 670 PSYCHOLOGY. those presented by the impulsions of an explosive, wilL Pteally both effort and resistance are ours, and the identifi cation of our self with one of these factors is an illusion and a trick of speech. I do not see how anyone can fail (especially when the mythologic dynamism of separate 1 ideas,' which Professor Lipps cleaves to, is translated into that of brain-processes) to recognize the fascinating sim plicity of some such view as his. Nor do I see why for scientific purposes one need give it up even if indeter minate amounts of effort really do occur. Before their inde- terminism, science simply stops. She can abstract from it altogether, then ; for in the impulses and inhibitions with which the effort has to cope there is already a larger field of uniformity than she can ever practically cultivate. Her prevision will never foretell, even if the effort be completely predestinate, the actual way in which each individual emer gency is resolved. Psychology will be Psychology,* and Science Science, as much as ever (as much and no more) in this world, whether free-will be true in it or not. Science, however, must be constantly reminded that her purposes are not the only purposes, and that the order of uniform causation which she has use for, and is therefore right in postulating, may be enveloped in a wider order, on which she has no claims at all. We can therefore leave the free-will question altogether out of our account. As we said in Chapter YI (p. 453), the operation of free effort, if it existed, could only be to hold some one ideal object, or part of an object, a little longer or a little more intensely before the mind. Amongst the alternatives which present themselves as genuine possi- * Such ejaculations as Mr. Spencer's : " Psychical changes either conform to law or they do not. If they do not, this work, in common with all works on the subject, is sheer nonsense: no science of Psychology is possible " (Principles of Psychology, i. 503),— are beneath criticism. Mr. Spencer's work, like all the other 'works on the subject,' treats of those general conditions of possible conduct within which ari our real decisions must fall no matter whether their effort be small or great. However closely psychical changes may conform to law, it is safe to say that indi vidual histories and biographies will never be written in advance no matter how ' evolved ' psychology may become. WILL. 577 bles, it would thus make one effective.* And although such quickening of one idea might be morally and historically momentous, yet, if considered dynamically, it would be an operation amongst those physiological infinitesimals which calculation must forever neglect. But whilst eliminating the question about the amount of * Caricatures of the kind of supposition which free will demands abound in deterministic literature. The following passage from John Fiske's Cos mic Philosophy (pt. n. chap, xvn) is an example: "If volitions arise without cause, it necessarily follows that we cannot infer from them the character of the antecedent states of feeling. If, therefore, a murder has been committed, we have a priori no better reason for suspecting the worst enemy than the best friend of the murdered man. If we see a man jump from a fourth-story window, we must beware of too hastily inferring his insanity, since he may be merely exercising his free-will ; the intense love of life implanted in the human breast being, as it seems, unconnected with attempts at suicide or at self-preservation. We can thus frame no theory of human actions whatever. The countless empirical maxims of every-day life, the embodiment as they are of the inherited and organized sagacity of many generations, become wholly incompetent to guide us ; and nothing which any one may do ought ever to occasion surprise. The mother may strangle her first-born child, the miser may cast his long- treasured gold into the sea, the sculptor may break in pieces his lately- finished statue, in the presence of no other feelings than those which before led them to chersish, to hoard, and to create. " To state these conclusions is to refute their premise. Probably no defender of the doctrine of free-will could be induced to accept them, even to save the theorem with which they are inseparably wrapped up. Yet the dilemma cannot be avoided. Volitions are either caused or they are not. If they are not caused, an inexorable logic brings us to the absurdities just mentioned. If they are caused, the free-will doctrine is annihilated. In truth, the immediate corollaries of the free-will doctrine are so shock ing, not only to philosophy but to common-sense, that were not accurate thinking a somewhat rare phenomenon, it would be inexplicable how any credit should ever have been given to such a dogma. This is but one of the many instances in which by the force of words alone men have been held subject to chronic delusion. . . . Attempting, as the free-will phi losophers do, to destroy the science of history, they are compelled by an inexorable logic to pull down with it the cardinal principles of ethics, politics, and jurisprudence. Political economy, if rigidly dealt with on their theory, would fare little better ; and psychology would become chaotic jargon. . . . The denial of causation is the affirmation of chance, and ' between the theory of Chance and the theory of Law there can be no compromise, no reciprocity, no borrowing and lending.' To write history on any method furnished by the free-will doctrine would be utterly impossible."— All this comes from Mr. Fiske's not distinguishing between the possibles which really tempt a man and those which tempt him not at all. Free-will, like psychology, deals with the former possibles exclusively, 578 PSYCHOLOGY. our effort as one which psychology will never have a prac tical call to decide, I must say one word about the extra ordinarily intimate and important character which the phenomenon of effort assumes in our own eyes as individ ual men. Of course we measure ourselves by many stand ards. Our strength and our intelligence, our wealth and even our good luck, are things which warm our heart and make us feel ourselves a match for life. But deeper than all such things, and able to suffice unto itself without them, is the sense of the amount of effort which we can put forth. Those are, after all, but effects, products, and reflections of the outer world within. But the effort seems to belong to an altogether different realm, as if it were the substantive thing which we are, and those were but externals which we carry. If the ' searching of our heart and reins ' be the purpose of this human drama, then what is sought seems to be what effort we can make. He who can make none is but a shadow ; he who can make much is a hero. The huge world that girdles us about puts all sorts of questions to us, and tests us in all sorts of ways. Some of the tests we meet by actions that are easy, and some of the questions we answer in articulately formulated words. But the deepest question that is ever asked admits of no reply but the dumb turning of the will and tightening 01 our heart strings as we say, " Yes, I will even have it so!" When a dreadful object is presented, or when life as a whole turns up its dark abysses to our view, then the worth less ones among us lose their hold on the situation alto gether, and either escape from its difficulties by averting their attention, or if they cannot do that, collapse into yielding masses of plaintiveness and fear. The effort required for facing and consenting to such objects is be yond their power to make. But the heroic mind does differently. To it, too, the objects are sinister and dread ful, unwelcome, incompatible with wished-for things. But it can face them if necessary, without for that losing its hold upon the rest of life. The world thus finds in the heroic man its worthy match and mate ; and the effort which he is able to put forth to hold himself erect and keep his heart unshaken is the direct measure of his worth WILL. 679 and function in the game of human life. He can stand this Universe. He can meet it and keep up his faith in it in presence of those same features which lay his weaker breth ren low. He can still find a zest in it, not by ' ostrich-like forge tfulness,' but by pure inward willingness to face the world with those deterrent objects there. And hereby he becomes one of the masters and the lords of life. He must be counted with henceforth ; he forms a part of human destiny. Neither in the theoretic nor in the practical sphere do we care for, or go for help to, those who have no head for risks, or sense for living on the perilous edge. Our religious life lies more, our practical life lies less, than it used to, on the perilous edge. But just as our courage .is so often a reflex of another's courage, so our faith is apt to be, as Max Miiller somewhere says, a faith in some one else's faith. We draw new life from the heroic example. The prophet has drunk more deeply than anyone of the cup of bitterness, but his countenance is so unshaken and he speaks such mighty words of cheer that his will becomes our will, and our life is kindled at his own. Thus not only our morality but our religion, so far as the latter is deliberate, depend on the effort which we can make. " Will you or won't you have it so ? " is the most prob ing question we are ever asked ; we are asked it every hour of the day, and about the largest as well as the smallest, the most theoretical as well as the most practical, things. We answer by consents or non-consents and not by words. What wonder that these dumb responses should seem our deepest organs of communication with the nature of things ! What wonder if the effort demanded by them be the meas ure of our worth as men ! What wonder if the amount which we accord of it bo the one strictly underived and original contribution which we make to the world ! THE EDUCATION" OF THE WILL. The education of the will may be taken in a broader or a narrower sense. In the broader sense, it means the whole of one's training to moral and prudential conduct, and of one's learning to adapt means to ends, involving the ' asso ciation of ideas,' in all its varieties and complications, to- 580 PSYCHOLOGY. gether with the power of inhibiting impulses irrelevant to the ends desired, and of initiating movements contributory thereto. It is the acquisition of these latter powers which I mean by the education of the will in the narrower sense. And it is in this sense alone that it is worth while to treat the matter here.* Since a willed movement is a movement preceded by an idea of itself, the problem of the will's education is the prob lem of how the idea of a movement can arouse the move ment itself. This, as we have seen, is a secondary kind of process ; for framed as we are, we can have no a priori idea of a movement, no idea of a movement which we have not already performed. Before the idea can be generated, the movement must have occurred in a blind, unexpected way, And left its idea behind. Reflex, instinctive, or random exe cution of a movement must, in other words, precede its vol untary execution. Reflex and instinctive movements have Already been considered sufficiently for the purposes of this book. ' Random ' movements are mentioned so as to in clude quasi - accidental reflexes from inner causes, or movements possibly arising from such overflow of nutri tion in special centres as Prof. Bain postulates in his ex planation of those ' spontaneous discharges ' by which he sets such great store in his derivation of the voluntary life.f Now how can the sensory process which a movement has previously produced, discharge, when excited again, into the centre for the movement itself? On the movement's original occurrence the motor discharge came first and the sensory process second ; now in the voluntary repetition the sen sory process (excited in weak or ' ideational * form) comes first, and the motor discharge comes second. To tell how this comes to pass would be to answer the problem of the education of the will in physiological terms. Evidently the problem is that of the formation of new paths; and the *On the education of the Will from a pedagogic point of view, see an article by G. Stanley Hall in the Princeton Review for November 1882. and some bibliographic references there contained. f See his Emotions and Will, ' The Will,' chap. i. I take the name of random movements from Sully, Outlines of Psychology, p. 593. WILL. 581 only thing to do is to make hypotheses, till we find some which seem to cover all the facts. How is a fresh path ever formed ? All paths are paths of discharge, and the discharge always takes place in the direction of least resistance, whether the cell which dis charges be * motor ' or * sensory.' The connate paths of least resistance are the paths of instinctive reaction ; and I sub mit as my first hypothesis that these paths aU run one way, that is from 'sensory ' cells into 'motor' cells and, from motor cells into muscles, without ever taking the reverse direction. A motor cell, for example, never awakens a sensory cell di rectly, but only through the incoming current caused by the bodily movements to which its discharge gives rise. And a sensory cell always discharges or normally tends to discharge towards the motor region. Let this direction be called the ' forward ' direction. I call the law an hypothe sis, but really it is an indubitable truth. No impression or idea of eye, ear, or skin comes to us without occasioning a movement, even though the movement be no more than the accommodation of the sense-organ ; and all our trains of sensation and sensational imagery have their terms alternated and interpenetrated with motor processes, of most of which we practically are unconscious. Another way of stating the rule is to say that, primarily or connately, all currents through the brain run towards the Kolandic re gion, and that there they run out, and never return upon themselves. From this point of view the distinction of sensory and motor cells has no fundamental significance. All cells are motor ; we simply call those of the Kolandic region, those nearest the mouth of the funnel, the motor cells par excellence. A corollary of this law is that ' sensory ' cells do not awaken each other connately ; that is, that no one sensi ble property of things has any tendency, in advance of experience, to awaken in us the idea of any other sen sible properties which in the nature of things may go with it. There is no a priori calling up of one l idea ' by an other ; the only a priori couplings are of ideas with move ments. All suggestions of one sensible fact by another 582 PSYCHOLOGY. take place by secondary paths which experience has formed. The diagram (Fig. 87) shows what happens in a nervous system ideally reduced to the fewest possible terms. A stimulus reaching the sense-organ awakens the sensory cell, S ; this by the connate or instinctive path discharges the motor cell, M, which makes the muscle contract; and the contraction arouses the second sensory cell, K, which Motor Cell f >^ ^( sfe__. Sensory Cell - Kineesthetic Cell /\— Sense-organ Muscle -^\^^x* FIG. 87.* may be the organ either of a * resident ' or ' kinaesthetic,' or of a ' remote,' sensation. (See above, p. 488.) This cell K again discharges into M. If this were the entire nervous mechanism, the movement, once begun, would be self -maintaining, and would stop only when the parts were exhausted. And this, according to M. Pierre Janet, is what actually happens in catalepsy. A cataleptic patient is an aesthetic, speechless, motionless. Consciousness, so far as we can judge, is abolished. Nevertheless the limbs will retain whatever position is impressed upon them from without, and retain it so long that if it be a strained and unnatural position, the phenomenon is regarded by Char- cot as one of the few conclusive tests against hypnotic subjects shamming, since hypnotics can be made catalep- * This figure and the following ones are purely schematic, and must not be supposed to involve any theory about protoplasmatic and axis-cylin der processes. The latter, according to Golgi and others, emerge from the base of the cell, and each cell has but one. They alone form a nervous network. The reader will of course also understand that none of the hypothetical constructions which I make from now to the end of the chap ter are proposed as definite accounts of whnt linppens. All I aim at is to make it clear in some more or less symbolic fashion that the formation of new paths, the learning of habits, etc., is in some mechanical way con ceivable. Compare what was said in Vol. I. p. 81, note. WILL. 583 tic, and then keep their limbs outstretched for a length of time quite unattainable by the waking will. M. Janet thinks that in all these cases the outlying ideational processes in the brain are temporarily thrown out of gear. The kinsesthetic sensation of the raised arm, for example, is produced in the patient when the operator raises the arm, this sensation discharges into the motor cell, which through the muscle reproduces the sensation, etc., the currents running in this closed circle until they grow so weak, by exhaustion of the parts, that the member slow ly drops. We may call this circle from the muscle to K, from K to M, and from M to the muscle again, the * motor circle.' We should all be cataleptics and never stop a mus cular contraction once begun, were it not that other processes simultaneously going on inhibit the contraction. Inhibition is therefore not an occasional accident; it is an essential and unre mitting element of our cerebral life. It is interesting to note that Dr. Mercier, by a different path of reasoning, is also led to conclude that we owe to outside inhibitions exclu sively our power to arrest a movement once begun.* One great inhibiter of the discharge of K into M seems to be the painful or otherwise displeasing quality of the sensation itself of K ; and conversely, when this sensation is distinctly pleasant, that fact tends to further K's dis charge into M, and to keep the primordial motor circle agoing. Tremendous as the part is which pleasure and pain play in our psychic life, we must confess that absolute ly nothing is known of their cerebral conditions. It is hard to imagine them as having special centres ; it is harder still to invent peculiar forms of process in each and every centre, to which these feelings may be due. And let one try as one will to represent the cerebral activity in exclusively mechanical terms, I, for one, find it quite impossible to enumerate what seem to be the facts and yet to make no mention of the psychic side which they possess. However it be with other drainage currents and discharges, the drain age currents and discharges of the brain are not purely physical facts. They are psycho-physical facts, and the * The Nervous System and the Mind (1888), pp. 75-6. f>;U PSYCHOLOGY. spiritual quality of them seems a codeterminant of their mechanical effectiveness. If the mechanical activities in a cell, as they increase, give pleasure, they seem to increase all the more rapidly for that fact ; if they give displeasure, the displeasure seems to damp the activities. The psychic side of the phenomenon thus seems, somewhat like the ap plause or hissing at a spectacle, to be an encouraging or ad verse comment on what the machinery brings forth. The soul presents nothing herself ; creates nothing ; is at the mercy of the material forces for all possibilities; but amongst these possibilities she selects; and by reinforcing one and checking others, she figures not as an ' epiphenomenon,' but as something from which the play gets moral support. I shall therefore never hesitate to invoke the efficacy of the conscious comment, where no strictly mechanical reason appears why a current escaping from a cell should take one path rather than another.* But the existence of the current, and its tendency towards either path, I feel bound to account for by mechanical laws. Having now considered a nervous system reduced to its lowest possible terms, in which all the paths are connate, and the possibilities of inhibition not extrinsic, but due solely to the agreeableness or disagreeableness of the feeling aroused, let us turn to the conditions under which new paths may be formed. Potentialities of new paths are furnished by the fibres which connect the sensory cells amongst themselves ; but these fibres are not originally pervious, and have to be made so by a process which I proceed hy- pothetically to state as follows : Each discharge from a sen sory cell in the forward direction-^ tends to drain the cells lying behind the discharging one of ivhatever tension they may possess. The drainage from the rearward cells is what for the first time makes the fibres pervious. The result is a new-formed 'path,' running from the cells which were ' rearward ' to the cell which was ' forward ' on that occasion ; which path, if on future occa sions the rearward cells are independently excited, will tend to carry off their activity in the same direction so as to excite the * Compare Vol. I. pp. 137, 142. f That is, the direction towards the motor cells. WILL. 585 forward cell, and will deepen itself more and more every time it is used. Now the ' rearward cells,' so far, stand for all the sen sory cells of the brain other than the one which is discharg ing ; but such an indefinitely broad path would practically be no better than no path, so here I make a third hypoth esis, which, taken together with the others, seems to me to cover all the facts. It is that the deepest paths are formed from the w,ost drainable to the most draining cells; that the most drainable cells are those tvhich have just been discharging , and that the most draining cells are those which are now dis charging or in which the tension is rising towards the point of discharge.* Another diagram, Fig. 88, will make the matter clear. Take the operation represented by the previous diagram at the moment when, the muscular contrac tion having occurred, the cell K is discharging forward into M. Through the dotted line p it will, according to our third hypothesis, drain S (which, in the supposed case, has just dis charged into M by the connate path P, and caused the mus cular contraction), and the result is that p will now remain as a new path open from S to K. When next S is excited from without it will tend not only to discharge into M, but into K as well. K thus gets excited directly by S before it gets excited by the incoming current from the muscle ; or, translated into psychic terms : when a sensation has once produced a movement in us, the next time we have the sen sation, it tends to suggest the idea of the movement, even before the movement occurs.^ * This brain-scheme seems oddly enough to give a certain basis of reality to those hideously fabulous performances of the Herbartian Vorstellungen. Herbart says that when one idea is inhibited by another it fuses with that other and thereafter helps it to ascend into consciousness. Inhibition is thus the basis of association in both schemes, for the ' draining ' of which the text speaks is tantamount to an inhibition of the activity of the cells which are drained, which inhibition makes the inhibited revive the in- hibiter on later occasions. f See the luminous passage in Mtinsterberg : Die Willenshandlung, pp. 144-5. \ PSYCHOLOGY. The same principles also apply to the relations of K and M. M, lying in the forward direction, drains K, and the path KM, even though it be no primary or connate path, becomes a secondary or habitual one. Hereafter K may be aroused in any way whatsoever (not as before from S or from without) and still it will tend to discharge into M ; or, to express it again in psychic terms, the idea of the move ment M's sensory effects will have become an immediately ante cedent condition to the production of the movement itself. Here, then, we have the answer to our original question of how a sensory process which, the first time it occurred, was the effect of a movement, can later figure as the move ment's cause. It is obvious on this scheme that the cell which we have marked K may stand for the seat of either a resident or a remote sensation occasioned by the motor discharge. It may indifferently be a tactile, a visual, or an auditory cell. The idea of how the arm feels when raised may cause it to rise ; but no less may the idea of some sound which it makes in rising, or of some optical impression which it produces. Thus we see that the ' mental cue ' may belong to either of various senses ; and that what our diagrams lead us to infer is what really happens ; namely, that in our move- ' ments, such as that of speech, for example, in some of us it is the tactile, in others the acoustic, Effeetsbfld, or memory- image, which seems most concerned in starting the articula tion (Vol. I. pp. 54-5). The primitive ' starters,' however, of all our movements are not EffectsUlder at all, but sensations and objects, i*nd subsequently ideas derived therefrom. Let us now turn to the more complex and serially con catenated movements which oftenest meet us in real life. The object of our will is seldom a single muscular contrac tion ; it is almost always an orderly sequence of contractions, ending with a sensation which tells us that the goal is reached. But the several contractions of the sequence are not each distinctly willed ; each earlier one seems rather, by the sensation it produces, to call its follower up, after the fashion described in Chapter VI, where we spoke of WILL. 587 habitual concatenated movements being due to a series of secondarily organized reflex arcs (Vol. I. p. 116). The first contraction is the one distinctly willed, and after willing it we let the rest of the chain rattle off of its own accord. How now is such an orderly concatenation of movements Originally learned? or in other words, how are paths formed for the first time between one motor centre and an other, so that the discharge of the first centre makes the others discharge in due order all along the line ? The phenomenon involves a rapid alternation of motor discharges and resultant afferent impressions, for as long a time as it lasts. They must be associated in one definite order ; and the order must once have been learned, i.e., it must have been picked out and held to more and more exclusively out of the many other random orders which first presented themselves. The random afferent impres sions fell out, those that felt right were selected and grew together in the chain. A chain which we actively teach ourselves by stringing a lot of right-feeling impressions together differs in no essential respect from a chain which we passively learn from someone else who gives us im pressions in a certain order. So to make our ideas more precise, let us take a particular concatenated movement for an example, and let it be the recitation of the alphabet, which someone in our childhood taught us to say by heart. What we have seen so far is how the idea of the sound or articulatory feeling of A may make us say * A,' that of B, ' B,' and so on. But what we now want to see is why the sensation that A is uttered should make us say l B, why the sen sation that B is uttered should make us say l (7,' and so on. To understand this we must recall what happened when we first learned the letters in their order. Someone re peated A, B, C, D to us over and over again, and we imi tated the sounds. Sensory cells corresponding to each letter were awakened in succession in such wise that each one of them (by virtue of our second law) must have ' drained ' the cell just previously excited and left a path by which that cell tended ever afterwards to discharge into the cell that drained it. Let Sa, S6, Sc in figure 89 stand for three of these cells. Each later one of them, as it discharges 588 PSYCHOLOGY. motorwards, draws a current from the previous one, Sb from Ba, and S° from Sb. Cell Sb having thus drained Sa, if Sa ever gets excited again, it tends to discharge into Sb; whilst FIG. Sc having drained Sb, Sb later discharges into S°, etc., etc. — all through the dotted lines. Let now the idea of the letter A arise in the mind, or, in other words, let Sa be aroused : what happens ? A current runs from Sa not only into the motor cell Ma for pronouncing that letter, but also into the cell Sb. When, a moment later, the effect of Ma's discharge comes back by the afferent nerve and re-excites Sa, this latter cell is inhibited from discharging again into Ma and reproducing the 'primordial motor circle' (which FIG. 90. in this case would be the continued utterance of the letter A), by the fact that the process in S6, already under head way and tending to discharge into its own motor associate Mb, is, under the existing conditions, the stronger drainage- channel for Sa's excitement. The result is that Mb dis charges and the letter B is pronounced ; whilst at the same time Sc receives some of Sb's overflow ; and, a moment later WILL. 589 when the sound of B enters the ear, discharges into the motor cell for pronouncing C, by a repetition of the same mechanism as before ; and so on ad libitum. Figure 90 represents the entire set of processes involved. The only thing that one does not immediately see is the reason why ' under the existing conditions ' the path from Sa to S& should be the stronger drainage-channel for Sa's excitement. If the cells and fibres in the figure constituted the entire brain we might suppose either a mechanical or a psychical reason. The mechanical reason might lie in a general law that cells like Sb and M6, whose excitement is in a rising phase, are stronger drainers than cells like Ma, which have just discharged ; or it might lie in the fact that an irradiation of the current beyond Sb into Sc and Mc has already begun also ; and in a still farther law that drainage tends in the direction of the widest irra diations. Either of these suppositions would be a suffi cient mechanical reason why, having once said A, we should not say it again. But we must not forget that the process has a psychical side, nor close our eyes to the possibility that the sort of feeling aroused by incipient currents may be the reason why certain of them are in stantly inhibited and others helped to flow. There is no doubt that before we have uttered a single letter, the gen eral intention to recite the alphabet is already there ; nor is there any doubt that to that intention corresponds a wide spread premonitory rising of tensions along the entire system of cells and fibres which are later to be aroused. So long as this rise of tensions feds good, so long every current which increases it is furthered, and every current which diminishes it is checked; and this may be the chief one of the 'existing conditions' which make the drainage-channel from Sa to S6 temporarily so strong.* The new paths between the sensory cells of which we have studied the formation are paths of ' association,' and we now see why associations run always in the forward * L. Lange's and Miinsterberg's experiments with 'shortened ' or ' mus cular' reaction -time (see Vol. I. p. 432) show how potent a fact dynami cally this anticipatory preparation of a whole set of possible drainage- channels is. 590 PSYCHOLOGY. direction ; why, for example, we cannot say the alphabet backward, and why, although S6 discharges into Sc, there is no tendency for Sc to discharge into S&, or at least no more than for it to discharge into Sa.* The first-formed paths had, according to the principles which we invoked, to run from cells that had just discharged to those that were discharging ; and now, to get currents to run the other way, we must go through a new learning of our letters with their order reversed. There will then be two sets of asso ciation-pathways, either of them possible, between the sen sible cells. I represent them in Fig. 91, leaving out the motor features for simplicity's sake. The dotted lines are the paths in the backward direction, newly organized from FIG. 91. the reception by the ear of the letters in the order C B A. The same principles will explain the formation of new paths successively concatenated to no matter how great an extent, but it would obviously be folly to pretend to illus trate by more intricate examples. I will therefore only bring back the case of the child and flame (Vol. I. p. 25), to show how easily it admits of explanation as a ' purely cortical transaction ' (ibid. p. 80). The sight of the flame stimu lates the cortical centre S1 which discharges by an instinc tive reflex path into the centre M1 for the grasping-move- * Even as the proofs of these pages are passing through my hands, I receive Heft 2 of the Zeitschrift fiir Psychologic u. Physiologic der Sin- nesorgane, in which the irrepressible young Munsterberg publishes experi ments to show that there is no association between successive ideas, apart from intervening movements. As my explanations have assumed that an earlier excited sensory cell drains a later one, his experiments and infer ences would, if sound, upset all my hypotheses. I therefore can (at this late moment) only refer the reader to Herr M. 's article, hoping to review the subject again myself in another place. WILL. 591 ment. This movement produces the feeling of burn, as its effects come back to the centre S2 ; and this centre by a FIG. 92. second connate path discharges into Ma, the centre for withdrawing the hand. The movement of withdrawal stimulates the centre S3, and this, as far as we are concerned, is the last thing that happens. Now the next time the child sees the candle, the cortex is in possession of the secondary paths which the first experience left behind. S2, having been stimulated immediately after S1, drained the latter, and now S1 discharges into S2 before the discharge of M1 has had time to occur ; in other words, the sight of the flame suggests the idea of the burn before it produces its own natural reflex ef fects. The result is an inhibition of M1, or an overtaking of it before it is completed, by M*. — The characteristic phy siological feature in all these acquired systems of paths lies in the fact that the new-formed sensory irradiations keep draining things for ward, and so breaking up the ' motor circles ' which would otherwise accrue. But, even apart from catalepsy, we see the ' motor circle ' every now and then come back. An infant learning to execute a simple move ment at will, without regard to other movements beyond it, keeps repeating it till tired. How reiteratively they babble each new-learned word ! And we adults often catch ourselves reiterating some meaningless word over and over again, if by chance we once begin to utter it ' absent-mind edly,' that is, without thinking of any ulterior train of words to which it may belong. One more observation before closing these already too protracted physiological speculations. Already (Yol. I. p. 71) I have tried to shadow forth a reason why collateral inner- 592 PSYCHOLOGY. vation should establish itself after loss of brain-tissue, and why incoming stimuli should find their way out again, after an interval, by their former paths. I can now explain this a little better. Let S1 be the dog's hearing-centre when he receives the command ' Give your paw.' This used to discharge into the motor centre M1, of whose discharge S2 represents the kinsesthetic effect ; but now M1 has been de stroyed by an operation, so that S1 discharges as it can, into other movements of the body, whimpering, raising the wrong paw, etc. The kinsesthetic centre S2 meanwhile has M* FIG. 93. been awakened by the order S1, and the poor animal's mind tingles with expectation and desire of certain incoming sen sations which are entirely at variance with those which the really executed movements give. None of the latter sensa tions arouse a ' motor circle,' for they are displeasing and inhibitory. But when, by random accident, S1 and S2 do discharge into a path leading through M2, by which the paw is again given, and S2 is excited at last from without as well as from within, there are no inhibitions and the ' motor circle ' is formed : S1 discharges into M2 over and over again, and the path from the one spot to the other is so much deepened that at last it becomes organized as the regular channel of efflux when S1 is aroused. No other path has a chance of being organized in like degree. CHAPTEE XXVII. HYPNOTISM. MODES OF OPEBATING, AND SUSCEPTIBILITY. THE ' hypnotic,' ' mesmeric,' or * magnetic ' trance can be induced in various ways, each operator having his pet method. The simplest one is to leave the subject seated and general roadside raggedness, and revel in the beauty and picturesqueness of the other elements of the landscape, whilst to a newly- HYPNOTISM. arrived European the fences are so aggressively present as to spoil enjoyment. Messrs. Gurney, Janet, and Binet have shown that the ignored elements are preserved in a split-off portion of the subjects' consciousness which can be tapped in certain ways, and made to give an account of itself (see Vol. I. p. 209). Hypercesthesia of the senses is as common a symptom as. anesthesia. On the skin two points can be discriminated at less than the normal distance. The sense of touch is so delicate that (as M. Delbceuf informs me) a subject after simply poising on her finger-tips a blank card drawn from a pack of similar ones can pick it out from the pack again by its ' weight.' We approach here the line where, to many persons, it seems as if something more than the ordinary senses, however sharpened, were required in explanation. I have seen a coin from the operator's pocket repeatedly picked out by ths subject from a heap of twenty others,'3*' by its greater 'weight' in the subject's language. — Audi tory hypersesthesia may enable a subject to hear a watch tick, or his operator speak, in a distant room. — One of the most extraordinary examples of visual hyperaesthesia is that reported by Bergson, in which a subject who seemed to be reading through the back of a book held and looked at by the operator, was really proved to be reading the im age of the page reflected on the latter's cornea. The same subject was able to discriminate with the naked eye details in a microscopic preparation. Such cases of ' hypersesthe sia of vision ' as that reported by Taguet and Sauvaire, where subjects could see things mirrored by non-reflecting bodies, or through opaque pasteboard, would seem rather to belong to ' psychical research ' than to the present cate gory. — The ordinary test of visual hypera^ateness in hyp notism is the favorite trick of giving a subject the hallu cination of a picture on a blank sheet oi card-board, and then mixing the latter with a lot of other similar sheets. The subject will always find the picture on the original sheet again, and recognize infallibly if it has been turned * Precautions being taken against differences of temperature and other grounds of suggestion. 610 PSYCHOLOGY. over, or upside down, although the bystanders have to re sort to artifice to identify it again. The Subject notes pe culiarities on the card, too small for waking observation to detect* If it be said that the spectators guide him by their manner, their breathing, etc., that is only another proof of his hypersesthesia ; for he undoubtedly is con scious of subtler personal indications (of his operator's mental states especially) than he could notice in his waking state. Examples of this are. found in the so-called 'mag netic rapport: This is a name for the fact that in deep trance, or in lighter trance whenever the suggestion is made, the subject is deaf and blind to everyone but the operator or those spectators to whom the latter expressly awakens his senses. The most violent appeals from any one else are for him as if non-existent, whilst he obeys the faintest signals on the part of his hypnotizer. If in cata lepsy, his limbs will retain their attitude only when the operator moves them ; when others move them they fall down, etc. A more remarkable fact still is that the patient will often answer anyone whom his operator touches, or at whom he even points his finger, in however concealed a manner. All which is rationally explicable by expectation and suggestion, if only it be farther admitted that his senses are acutely sharpened for all the operator's move- ments.f He often shows great anxiety and restlessness if the latter is out of the room. A favorite experiment of Mr. E. Gurney's was to put the subject's hands through an opaque screen, and cause the operator to point at one finger. That finger presently grew insensible or rigid. A bystander pointing simultaneously at another finger, never made that insensible or rigid. Of course the elective rap- port with their operator had been developed in these * It should be said, however, that the bystander's ability to discrimi nate unmarked cards and sheets of paper from each other is much greater than one would naturally suppose. f I must repeat, however, that we are here on the verge of possibly un known forces and modes of communication. Hypnotization at a distance, with no grounds for expectation on the subject's part that it was to be tried, seems pretty well established in certain very rare cases. See in general, for information on these matters, the Proceedings of the Soc. for Psych. Research, passim. HYPNOTISM. 611 trained subjects during the hypnotic state, but the phe nomenon then occurred in some of them during the waking state, even when their consciousness was absorbed in ani mated conversation with a fourth party.* I confess that when I saw these experiments I was impressed with the necessity for admitting between the emanations from differ ent people differences for which we have no name, and a discriminative sensibility for them of the nature of which we can form no clear conception, but which seems to be developed in certain subjects by the hypnotic trance. — The enigmatic reports of the effect of magnets and metals, even if they be due, as many contend, to unintentional sugges tion on the operator's part, certainly involve hyperaesthetic perception, for the operator seeks as well as possible to conceal the moment when the magnet is brought into play, and yet the subject not only finds it out that moment in a way difficult to understand, but may develop effects which (in the first instance certainly) the operator did not expect to find. Unilateral contractures, movements, paralyses, hallu cinations, etc., are made to pass to the other side of the body, hallucinations to disappear, or to change to the com plementary color, suggested emotions to pass into their opposites, etc. Many Italian observations agree with the French ones, and the upshot is that if unconscious sugges tion lie at the bottom of this matter, the patients show an enormously exalted power of divining what it is they are expected to do. This hypersesthetic perception is what concerns us now.f its modus cannot yet be said to be de fined. * Here again the perception in question must take place below the threshold of ordinary consciousness, possibly in one of those split-off selves or ' second ' states whose existence we have so often to recognize. t I myself verified many of the above effects of the magnet on a blind folded subject on whom I was trying them for the first time, and whom I believe to have never heard of them before. The moment, however, an opaque screen was added to the blindfolding, the effects ceased to coincide with the approximation of the magnet, so that it looks as if visual percep tion had been instrumental in producing them. The subject passed from my observation, so that I never could clear up the mystery. Of course I gave him consciously no hint of what I was looking for. 612 PSYCHOLOGY. Changes in the nutrition of the tissues may be produced by suggestion. These effects lead into therapeutics — a subject which I do not propose to treat of here. But I may say that there seems no reasonable ground for doubting that in certain chosen subjects the suggestion of a congestion, a burn, a blister, a raised papule, or a bleeding from the nose or skin, may produce the effect. Messrs. Beaunis, Berjon, Bernheim, Bourru, Burot, Charcot, Delbceuf, Dumontpal- Her, Focachon, Forel, Jendrassik, Krafft-Ebing, Liebault, Liegeois, Lipp, Mabille, and others have recently vouched for one or other of these effects. Messrs. Delboeuf ancl Liegeois have annulled by suggestion, one the effects of a burn, the other of a blister. Delbceuf was led to his experi ments after seeing a burn on the skin produced by suggestion, at the Salpetriere, by reasoning that if the idea of a pain could produce inflammation it must be because pain was itself an inflammatory irritant, and that the abolition of it from a real burn ought therefore to entail the absence of inflammation. He applied the actual cautery (as well as vesi cants) to symmetrical places on the skin, affirming that no pain should be felt on one of the sides. The result was a dry scorch on that side, with (as he assures me) no after- mark, but on the other side a regular blister with suppura tion and a subsequent scar. This explains the innocuity of certain assaults made on subjects during trance. To test simulation, recourse is often had to sticking pins under their finger-nails or through their tongue, to inhalations of strong ammonia, and the like. These irritations, when not felt by the subject, seem to leave no after-consequences. One is reminded of the reported non-inflammatory character of the wounds made on themselves by dervishes in their pious or gies. On the other hand, the reddenings and bleedings of the skin along certain lines, suggested by tracing lines or press ing objects thereupon, put the accounts handed down to us of the stigmata of the cross appearing on the hands, feet, sides, and forehead of certain Catholic mystics in a new light. As so often happens, a fact is denied until a welcome inter pretation comes with it. Then it is admitted readily enough; and evidence judged quite insufficient to back a claim, so long as the church had an interest in making it, proves to HYPNOTISM. 613 be quite sufficient for modern scientific enlightenment, the moment it appears that a reputed saint can thereby be •classed as 'a case of hystero-epilepsy.' There remain two other topics, viz., post-hypnotic effects of suggestion, and effects of suggestion in the waking state. Post-hypnotic, or deferred, suggestions are such as are given to the patients during trance, to take effect after wak ing. They succeed with a certain number of patients even when the execution is named for a remote period — months or even a year, in one case reported by M. Liegeois. In this way one can make the patient feel a pain, or be para lyzed, or be hungry or thirsty, or have an hallucination, positive or negative, or perform some fantastic action after emerging from his trance. The effect in question may be ordered to take place not immediately, but after an interval of time has elapsed, and the interval may be left to the subject to measure, or may be marked by a certain signal. The moment the signal occurs, or the time is run out, the subject, who until then seems in a perfectly normal waking condition, will experience the suggested effect. In many instances, whilst thus obedient to the suggestion, he seems to fall into the hypnotic condition again. This is proved by the fact that the moment the hallucination or sug gested performance is over he forgets it, denies all knowl edge of it, and so forth ; and by the further fact that he is ' suggestible ' during its performance, that is, will receive new hallucinations, etc., at command. A moment later and this suggestibility has disappeared. It cannot be said, how ever, that relapse into the trance is an absolutely necessary condition for the post-hypnotic carrying out of commands, for the subject may be neither suggestible nor amnesic, and may struggle with all the strength of his will against the absurdity of this impulse which he feels rising in him, he knows not why. In these cases, as in most cases, he forgets the circumstance o-f the impulse having been suggested to him in •,. previous trance ; regards it as arising within him self ; and often improvises, as he yields to it, some more or less plausible or ingenious motive by which to justify it to PSYCHOLOGY. the lookers-on. He acts, in short, with his usual sense of per- sonal spontaneity and freedom ; and the disbelievers in the freedom of the will have naturally made much of these cases in their attempts to show it to be an illusion. The only really mysterious feature of these deferred sug gestions is the patient's absolute ignorance during the inter val preceding their execution that they have been deposited in his mind. They will often surge up at the preappointed time, even though you have vainly tried a while before to make him recall the circumstances of their production. The most important class of post-hypnotic suggestions are, of course, those relative to the patient's health— bowels, sleep, and other bodily functions. Among the most interesting (apart from the hallucinations) are those relative to future trances. One can determine the hour and minute, or the signal, at which the patient will of his own accord lapse into trance again. One can make him susceptible in future to another operator who may have been unsuccessful with him in the past. Or more important still in certain cases, one can, by suggesting that certain persons shall never be able hereafter to put him to sleep, remove him for all future time from hypnotic influences which might be dangerous. This, indeed, is the simple and natural safeguard against those ' dangers of hypnotism ' of which uninstructed persons talk so vaguely. A subject who knows himself to be ultra-sus ceptible should never allow himself to be entranced by an operator in whose moral delicacy he lacks complete confi dence ; and he can use a trusted operator's suggestions to protect himself against liberties which others, knowing his weakness, might be tempted to take with him. The mechanism by which the command is retained until the moment for its execution arrives is a mystery which has given rise to much discussion. The experiments of Gurney and the observations of M. Pierre Janet and others on cer tain hysterical somnabulists seem to prove that it is stored up in consciousness ; not simply organically registered, but that the consciousness which thus retains it is split off, dissociated from the rest of the subject's mind. We have here, in short, an experimental production of one of those 'second' states of the personality of which we have spoken so often. Only here the HYPNOTISM. 615 second state coexists as well as alternates with the first. Gurney had the brilliant idea of tapping this second con sciousness by means of the planchette. He found that certain persons, who were both hypnotic subjects and auto matic writers, would if their hands were placed on a plan chette (after being wakened from a trance in which they had received ths suggestion of something to be done at a later time) write ^ut unconsciously the order, or something con nected with it. This shows that something inside of them, which could express itself through the hand alone, was continuing to think of the order, and possibly of it alone. These researches have opened a new vista of possible ex perimental investigations into the so-called ' second ' states of the personality. Some subjects seem almost as obedient to suggestion in the waking state as in sleep, or even more so, according to certain observers. Not only muscular phenomena, but changes of personality and hallucinations are recorded as the result of simple affirmation on the operator's part, with out the previous ceremony of ' magnetizing ' or putting into the ' mesmeric sleep.' These are all trained subjects, how ever, so far as I know, and the affirmation must apparently be accompanied by the patient concentrating his attention and gazing, however briefly, into the "eyes of the operator. It is probable therefore that an extremely rapidly induced condition of trance is a prerequisite for success in these experiments. I have now made mention of all the more important phenomena of the hypnotic trance. Of their therapeutic or forensic bearings this is not the proper place to speak. The recent literature of the subject is quite voluminous, but much of it consists in repetition. The best compendious work on the subject is ' Der Hypnotism us,' by Dr. A. Moll (Berlin, 1889 ; and just translated into English, N. T., 1890), which is extraordinarily complete and judicious. The other writings most recommendable are subjoined in the note.* *Binetand Fere, ' Animal Magnetism,' in the International Scientific Series ; A. Bernheim, ' Suggestive Therapeutics ' (N.T., 1889); J. Liegeois, 616 PSYCHOLOGY. Most of them contain a historical sketch and much bib liography. A complete bibliography has been published by M. Dessoir (Berlin, 1888). ' De la Suggestion ' (1889) ; E. Gurney, two articles in Mind, vol. ix. — la the recent revival of interest in the history of this subject, it seems a pity that the admirably critical and scientific work of Dr. John Kearsley Mitchell of Philadelphia should remain relatively so unknown. It is quite worthy to rank with Braid's investigations. See "Five Essays" by the above author, edited by S. Weir Mitchell, Philadelphia, 1859, pp. 141-274 CHAPTEK XXVIII. jtfECESSARY TRUTHS AND THE EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. IN this final chapter I shall treat of what has sometimes "been called psychogenesis, and try to ascertain just how far the connections of things in the outward environment can account for our tendency to think of, and to react upon, certain things in certain ways and in no others, even though personally we have had of the things in question no ex perience, or almost no experience, at all. It is a familiar truth that some propositions are necessary. We must attach the predicate ' equal ' to the subject ' opposite sides of a parallelogram ' if we think those terms together at all, whereas we need not in any such way attach the predicate ' rainy,' for example, to the subject « to-morrow.' The dubious sort of coupling of terms is universally admitted to be due to ' experience '; the certain sort is ascribed to the ' organic structure ' of the mind. This structure is in turn supposed by the so-called apriorists to be of transcendental origin, or at any rate not to be explicable by experience ; whilst by evolutionary empiricists it is supposed to be also due to ex perience, only not to the experience of the individual, but to that of his ancestors as far back as one may please to go. Our emotional and instinctive tendencies, our irresist ible impulses to couple certain movements with the percep tion or thought of certain things, are also features of our •connate mental structure, and like the necessary judgments, are interpreted by the apriorists and the empiricists in the same warring ways. I shall try in the course of the chapter to make plain three things : 1) That, taking the word experience as it is universally understood, the experience of the race can no more account 617 618 PSYCHOLOGY. for our necessary or a priori judgments than the experience of the individual can ; 2) That there is no good evidence for the belief that our instinctive reactions are fruits of our ancestors' edu cation in the midst of the same environment, transmitted to us at birth. 3) That the features of our organic mental structure cannot be explained at all by our conscious intercourse with the outer environment, but must rather be understood as congenital variations, ' accidental ' * in the first instance, but then transmitted as fixed features of the race. On the whole, then, the account which the apriorists give of the facts is that which I defend ; although I should contend (as will hereafter appear) for a naturalistic view of their cause. The first thing I have to say is that all schools (however they otherwise differ) must allow that the elementary qualities of cold, heat, pleasure, pain, red, blue, sound, silence, etc., are original, innate, or a priori properties of our subjective nature, even though they should require the touch of experience to waken them into actual consciousness, and should slumber, to all eternity, without it. This is so on either of the two Irypotheses we may make concerning the relation of the feelings to the realities at whose touch they become alive. For in the first place, if a feeling do not mirror the reality which wakens it and to which we say it corresponds, if it mirror no reality whatever outside of the mind, it of course is a purely mental product. By its very definition it can be nothing else. But in the second place, even if it do mirror the reality exactly, stil] it is not that reality itself, it is a duplication of it, the result of a mental reaction. And that the mind should have the power of reacting in just that duplicate way can only be stated as a harmony between its nature and the nature of the truth outside of it, a harmony whereby it follows that the qualities of both parties match. * ' Accidental ' in the Darwinian sense, as belonging to a cycle of cau sation inaccessible to tlie present order of research. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 619 The originality of these elements is not, then, a question for dispute. The warfare of philosophers is exclusively rela tive to their FORMS OF COMBINATION. The empiricist main tains that these forms can only follow the order of com bination in which the elements were originally awakened by the impressions of the external world ; the apriorists insist, on the contrary, that some modes of combination, at any rate, follow from the natures of the elements them selves, and that no amount of experience can modify this result. WHAT IS MEANT BY EXPEHIENCE P The phrase ' organic mental structure ' names the mat ter in dispute. Has the mind such a structure or not ? Are its contents arranged from the start, or is the arrange ment they may possess simply due to the shuffling of them by experience in an absolutely plastic bed ? Now the first thing to make sure of is that when we talk of 'experience,' we attach a definite meaning to the word. Experience means experience of something foreign supposed to impress m, whether spontaneously or in consequence of our own exertions and acts. Impressions, as we well know, affect certain orders of sequence and coexistence, and the mind's habits copy the habits of the impressions, so that our images of things assume a time- and space-arrangement which resembles the time- and space-arrangements outside. To uniform outer coexistences and sequences correspond constant con junctions of ideas, to fortuitous coexistences and sequences casual conjunctions of ideas. We are sure that fire Avill burn and water wet us, less sure that thunder will come after lightning, not at all sure whether a strange dog will bark at us or let us go by. In these ways experience moulds us every hour, and makes of our minds a mirror of the time- and space-connections between the things in the world. The principle of habit within us so fixes the copy at last that we find it difficult even to imagine how the out ward order could possibly be different from what it is, and we continually divine from the present what the future is to be. These habits of transition, from one thought to another, are features of mental structure which were lack- 620 PSYCHOLOGY. ing in us at birth ; we can see their growth under experi ence's moulding finger, and we can see how often experience undoes her own work, and for an earlier order substitutes a new one. ' The order of experience,' in this matter of the time- and space-conjunctions of things, is thus an indis putably vera causa of our forms of thought. It is our edu cator, our sovereign helper and friend ; and its name, standing for something with so real and definite a use, ought to be kept sacred and encumbered with no vaguer meaning. If all the connections among ideas in the mind could be interpreted as so many combinations of sense-data wrought into fixity in this way from without, then experi ence in the common and legitimate sense of the word would be the sole fashioner of the mind. The empirical school in psychology has in the main contended that they can be so interpreted. Before our generation, it was the experience of the individual only which was meant. But when one nowadays says that the human mind owes its present shape to experience, he means the experience of ancestors as well. Mr. Spencer's state ment of this is the earliest emphatic one, and deserves quotation in full : * " The supposition that the inner cohesions are adjusted to the outer persistences by accumulated experience of those outer persistences is in harmony with all our actual knowledge of mental phenomena. Though in so far as reflex actions and instincts are concerned, the experience- hypothesis seems insufficient; yet its seeming insufficiency occurs only where the evidence is beyond our reach. Nay, even here such few facts as we can get point to the conclusion that automatic psychical connec tions result from the registration of experiences continued for number less generations. 4 ' In brief, the case stands thus : It is agreed that all psychical relations, save the absolutely indissoluble, are determined by experiences. Their various strengths are admitted, other things equal, to be propor tionate to the multiplication of experiences. It is an unavoidable * The passage is in § 207 of the Principles of Psychology, at the end of the chapter entitled 'Reason.' I italicize certain words in order to show that the essence of this explanation is to demand numerically frequent ex periences. The bearing of this remark will later appear. (Cf. pp 641-2, infra.} NECESSARY TRUTRT— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 621 corollary that an infinity of experiences will produce a psychical relation that is indissoluble. Though such infinity of experiences cannot be received by a single individual, yet it may be received by the succession of individuals forming a race. And if there is a transmission of induced tendencies in the nervous system, it is inferrible that all psychical rela tions whatever, from the necessary to the fortuitous, result from the experiences of the corresponding external relations ; and are so brought into harmony with them. "Thus, the experience-hypothesis furnishes an adequate solution. The genesis of instinct, the development of memory and reason out of it, and the consolidation of rational actions and inferences into in stinctive ones, are alike explicable on the single principle that the cohesion between psychical states is proportionate to the frequency with which the relation between the answering external phenomena has been repeated in experience. " The universal law that, other things equal, the cohesion of psy chical states is proportionate to the frequency with which they have followed one another in experience, supplies an explanation of the so- • called ' forms of thought,' as soon as it is supplemented by the law that habitual psychical successions entail some hereditary tendency to such successions, which, under persistent conditions, will become cumulative in generation after generation. We saw that the establishment of those compound reflex actions called instincts is comprehensible on the prin ciple that inner relations are, by perpetual repetition, organized into correspondence with outer relations. We have now to observe that the establishment of those consolidated, those indissoluble, those instinctive mental relations constituting our ideas of Space and Time is compre hensible on the same principle. For if even to external relations that are often experienced during the life of a single organism, answer ing internal relations are established that become next to automatic — if such a combination of psychical changes as that which guides a savage in hitting a bird with an arrow becomes, by constant repetition, so or ganized as to be performed almost without thought of the processes of adjustment gone through— and if skill of this kind is so far transmissible that particular races of men become characterized by particular apti tudes, which are nothing else than partially-organized psychical connec tions ; then, if there exist certain external relations which are experienced by all organisms at all instants of their waking lives — relations which are absolutely constant, absolutely universal — there will be established answering internal relations that are absolutely constant, absolutely universal. Such relations we have in those of Space and Time. The organization of subjective relations adjusted to these objec tive relations has been cumulative, not in each race of creatures only, but throughout successive races of creatures ; and such subjective rela tions have, therefore, become more consolidated than all others. Being experienced in every perception and every action of each creature, these connections among outer existences must, for this reason too, ba 622 PSYCHOLOCY. responded to by connections among inner feelings, that are, above all others, indissoluble. As the substrata of all other relations in the non- ego, they must be responded to by conceptions that are the substrata of all other relations in the ego. Being the constant and infinitely- repeated elements of thought, they must become the automatic elements of thought— the elements of thought which it is impossible to get rid of — the ' forms of intuition. ' " Such, it seems to me, is the only possible reconciliation between the experience-hypothesis and the hypothesis of the transcendentalists ; neither of which is tenable by itself. Insurmountable difficulties are presented by the Kantian doctrine (as we shall hereafter see) ; and the antagonist doctrine, taken alone, presents difficulties that are equally insurmountable. To rest with the unqualified assertion that, antece dent to experience, the mind is a blank, is to ignore the questions— whence comes the power of organizing experiences ? whence arise the different degrees of that power possessed by different races of organisms, and different individuals of the same race ? If, at birth, there exists noth ing but a passive receptivity of impressions, why is not a horse as educable as a man ? Should it be said that language makes the differ ence, then why do not the cat and the dog, reared in the same house hold, arrive at equal degrees and kinds of intelligence ? Understood in its current form, the experience-hypothesis implies that the presence of a definitely-organized nervous system is a circumstance of no moment — a fact not needing to be taken into account ! Yet it is the all-impor tant fact — the fact to which, in one sense, the criticisms of Leibnitz and others pointed— the fact without which an assimilation of experiences is inexplicable. Throughout the animal kingdom in general, the actions are dependent on the nervous structure. The physiologist shows us that each reflex movement implies the agency of certain nerves and ganglia ; that a development of complicated instincts is accompanied by complication of the nervous centres and their commissural connections ; that the same creature in different stages, as larva and imago for example, changes its instincts as its nervous structure changes ; and that as we advance to creatures of high intelligence, a vast increase in the size and in the complexity of the nervous system takes place. What is the obvious inference ? It is that the ability to co-ordinate impres sions and to perform the appropriate actions always implies the pre- existence of certain nerves arranged in a certain way. What is the meaning of the human brain ? It is that the many established relations among its parts stand for so many established relations among the psy chical changes. Each of the constant connections among the fibres of tlie cerebral masses answers to some constant connection of phenomena in the experiences of the race. Just as the organized arrangement sub sisting between the sensory nerves of the nostrils and the motor nerves of the respiratory muscles not only makes possible a sneeze, but also, in the newly-born infant, implies sneezings to be hereafter performed ; so, all the organized arrangements subsisting among the nerves of the NECESSARY TRUTHS -EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 623 infant's brain not only make possible certain combinations of impres sions, but also imply that such combinations will hereafter be made— imply that there are answering combinations in the outer world — imply a preparedness to cognize these combinations — imply faculties of com prehending them. It is true that the resulting compound psychical changes do not take place with the same readiness and automatic pre cision as the simple reflex action instanced — it is true that some indi vidual experiences seem required to establish them. But while this is partly due to the fact that these combinations are highly involved, extremely varied in their modes of occurrence, made up therefore of psychical relations less completely coherent, and hence need further repetitions to perfect them ; it is in a much greater degree due to the fact that at birth the organization of the brain is incomplete, and does not cease its spontaneous progress for twenty or thirty years afterwards. Those who contend that knowledge results wholly from the experiences of the individual, ignoring as they do the mental evolution which accompanies the autogenous development of the nervous system, fall into an error as great as if they were to ascribe all bodily growth and struc ture to exercise, forgetting the innate tendency to assume the adult form. Were the infant born with a full-sized and completely-constructed brain, their position would be less untenable. But, as the case stands, the gradually-increasing intelligence displayed throughout childhood and youth is more attributable to the completion of the cerebral organ ization than to the individual experiences— a truth proved by the fact that in adult life there is sometimes displayed a high endowment of some faculty which, during education, was never brought into play. Doubtless, experiences received by the individual furnish the concrete materials for all thought. Doubtless, the organized and semi-organized arrangements existing among the cerebral nerves can give no knowledge until there has been a presentation of the external relations to which they correspond. And doubtless the child's daily observations and reasonings aid the formation of those involved nervous connections that are in process of spontaneous evolution ; just as its daily gambols aid the development of its limbs. But saying this is quite a different thing from saying that its intelligence is wholly produced by its experiences. That is an utterly inadmissible doctrine— a doctrine which makes the presence of a brain meaningless — a doctrine which makes idiotcy unac countable. 44 In the sense, then, that there exist in the nervous system certain pre-established relations answering to relations in the environment, there is truth in the doctrine of ' forms of intuition '—not the truth which its defenders suppose, but a parallel truth. Corresponding to absolute external relations, there are established in the structure of the nervous system absolute internal relations — relations that are potentially present before birth in the shape of definite nervous connections ; that are antecedent to, and independent of, individual experiences ; and that are automatically disclosed along with the first cognitions. And, 624 PSYCHOLOGY. as here understood, it is not only these fundamental relations which are thus predetermined, but also hosts of other relations of a more or less constant kind, which are congenitally represented by more or less complete nervous connections. But these predetermined internal relations, though independent of the experiences of the individual, are not independent of experiences in general : they have been determined by the experiences of preceding organisms. The corollary here drawn from the general argument is that the human brain is an organized register of infinitely-numerous experiences received during the evolution of life, or rather during the evolution of that series of organisms through which the human organism has been reached. The effects of the most uniform and frequent of these experiences have been succes sively bequeathed, principal and interest ; and have slowly amounted to that high intelligence which lies latent in the brain of the infant— which the infant in after-life exercises and perhaps strengthens or fur ther complicates— and which, with minute additions, it bequeaths tc future generations. And thus it happens that the European inherits from twenty to thirty cubic inches more brain than the Papuan. Thub it happens that faculties, as of music, which scarcely exist in somb inferior human races, become congenital in superior ones. Thus it hap pens that out of savages unable to count up to the number of their fin gers, and speaking a language containing only nouns and verbs, arise at length our Newtons and Shakspeares. " This is a brilliant and seductive statement, and it doubtless includes a good deal of truth. Unfortunately it fails to go into details ; and when the details are scrutinized, as they soon must be by us, many of them will be seen to be inexplicable in this simple way, and the choice will then remain to us either of denying the experiential origin of certain of our judgments, or of enlarging the meaning of the word experience so as to include these cases among its effects. TWO MODES OP ORIGIN OF BRAIN STRUCTURE. If we adopt the former course we meet with a contro versial difficulty. The ' experience-philosophy ' has from time immemorial been the opponent of theological modes of thought. The word experience has a halo of anti-super- naturalism about it ; so that if anyone express dissatisfac tion with any function claimed for it, he is liable to be treated as if he could only be animated by loyalty to the NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 625 catechism, or in some way have the interests of obscuran tism at heart. I am entirely certain that, on this ground alone, what I have erelong to say will make this a sealed chapter to many of my readers. " He denies experience ! " they will exclaim, "denies science; believes the mind created by miracle; is a regular old partisan of innate ideas ! That is enough ! we'll listen to such antediluvian twaddle no more." Regrettable as is the loss of readers capable of such wholesale discipleship, I feel that a definite meaning for the word experience is even more important than their company. * Experience ' does not mean every natural, as opposed to every supernatural, cause. It means a particular sort of natural agency, alongside of which other more recondite natural agencies may perfectly well exist. With the scien tific animus of anti-supernaturalism we ought to agree, but we ought to free ourselves from its verbal idols and bugbears. Nature has many methods of producing the same effect She may make a * born ' draughtsman or singer by tipping in a certain direction at an opportune moment the mole cules of some human ovum ; or she may bring forth a child ungifted and make him spend laborious but successful years at school. She may make our ears ring by the sound of a bell, or by a dose of quinine ; make us see yellow by spreading a field of buttercups before our eyes, or by mixing a little santonine powder with our food ; fill us with terror of certain surroundings by making them really dan gerous, or by a blow which produces a pathological altera tion of our brain. It is obvious that we need two words to designate these two modes of operating. In the one case the natural agents produce perceptions which take cognizance of the agents themselves ; in the other case, they produce percep tions which take cognizance of something else. What is taught to the mind by the ' experience,' in the first case, is the order of the experience itself — the ' inner relation ' (in Spencer's phrase) ' corresponds ' to the ' outer relation * wkich produced it, by remembering and knowing the latter. But in the case of the other sort of natural agency, what is taught to the mind has nothing to do with the agency 626 PSYCHOLOGY. itself, but with some different outer relation altogether. A diagram will express the alternatives. B stands for our human brain in the midst of the world. All the little o's FIG with arrows proceeding from them are natural objects (like sunsets, etc.), which impress it through the senses, and in the strict sense of the word give it experience, teaching it by habit and association what is the order of their ways. AU the little a?'s inside the brain and all the little x's outside of it are other natural objects and processes (in the ovum, in the blood, etc.), which equally modify the brain, but mould it to no cognition of themselves. The tinnitus aurium discloses no properties of the quinine ; the musical endow ment teaches no embryology ; the morbid dread (of solitude, perhaps) no brain-pathology ; but the way in which a dirty sunset and a rainy morrow hang together in the mind copies and teaches the sequences of sunsets and rainfall in the outer world. In zoological evolution we have two modes in which an animal race may grow to be a better match for its environ ment. First, the so-called way of ' adaptation,* in which the environment may itself modify its inhabitant by exercis ing, hardening, and habituating him to certain sequences, and these habits may, it is often maintained, become hered itary. Second, the way of ' accidental variation,' as Mr. Darwin termed it, in which certain young are born with peculiarities that help them and their progeny to survive. That varia tions of this sort tend to become hereditary, no one doubts. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 627 The first mode is called by Mr. Spencer direct, the second indirect, equilibration. Both equilibrations must of course be natural and physical processes, but they belong to entirely different physical spheres. The direct influences are obvious and accessible things. The causes of variation in the young are, on the other hand, molecular and hidden. The direct influences are the animal's 'ex periences,' in the widest sense of the term. Where what is influenced by them is the mental organism, they are con scious experiences, and become the objects as well as the causes of their effects. That is, the effect consists in a ten dency of the experience itself to be remembered, or to have its elements thereafter coupled in imagination just as they were coupled in the experience. In the diagram these ex periences are represented by the o's exclusively. The #'s, on the other hand, stand for the indirect causes of mental modification — causes of which we are not immediately con scious as such, and which are not the direct objects of the effects they produce. Some of them are molecular acci dents before birth ; some of them are collateral and remote combinations, unintended combinations, one might say, of more direct effects wrought in the unstable and intricate brain-tissue. Such a result is unquestionably the suscepti bility to music, which some individuals possess at the pres ent day. It has no zoological utility ; it corresponds to no object in the natural environment ; it is a pure incident of having a hearing organ, an incident depending on such in- stable and inessential conditions that one brother may have it and another brother not. Just so with the susceptibility to sea-sickness, which, so far from being engendered by long experience of its ' object ' (if a heaving deck can be called its object) is erelong annulled thereby. Our higher aesthetic, moral, and intellectual life seems made up of affections of this collateral and incidental sort, which have entered the mind by the back stairs, as it were, or rather have not entered the mind at all, but got surreptitiously born in the house. No one can successfully treat of psychogene- sis, or the factors of mental evolution, without distinguish ing between these two ways in which the mind is assailed. 628 PSYCHOLOGY. The way of ' experience ' proper is the front door, the door of the five senses. The agents which affect the brain in this way immediately become the mind's objects. The other agents do not. It would be simply silly to say of two men with perhaps equal effective skill in drawing, one an un taught natural genius, the other a mere obstinate plodder in the studio, that both alike owe their skill to their ' ex perience.' The reasons of their several skills lie in wholly disparate natural cycles of causation.* / will then, with the reader's permission, restrict the word ' experience ' to processes which influence the mind by the front-door-way of .simple habits and association. What the back-door-effects may be will probably grow clearer * Principles of Biology, part in. chaps, xi, xn. — Goltz and Loeb have found that dogs become mild in character when their occipital, and fierce when their frontal, brain-lobes are cut off. "A dog which originally was sross in an extreme degree, never suffering himself to be touched, and 5-ren refusing, after two days' fasting, to take a piece of bread from my hand, became, after a bilateral operation on the occipital lobes, perfectly trustful and harmless. He underwent five operations on these parts. . . . Each one of them made him more good-natured; so that at last (just as Goltz observed of his dogs) he would let other dogs take away the very bones which he was gnawing " (Loeb, Pfliiger's Archiv, xxxix. 300). A course of kind treatment and training might have had a similar effect. But how absurd to call two such different causes by the same name, and to say both times that the beast's ' experience of outer relations ' is what educates him to good-nature. This, however, is virtually what all writers do who ignore the distinction between the ' front-door ' and the ' back door ' manners of producing mental change. One of the most striking of these back-door affections is susceptibility to tlie charm of drunkenness. This (taking drunkenness in the broadest sense, as teetotalers use the word) is one of the deepest functions of human nature. Half of both the poetry and the tragedy of human life would vanish if alcohol were taken away. As it is, the thirst for it is such that in the United States the cash-value of its sales amounts to that of the sales' of meat and of bread put together. And yet what ancestral 'outer rela tion ' is responsible for this peculiar reaction of ours? The only ' outer relation ' could be the alcohol itself, which, comparatively speaking, came into the environment but yesterday, and which, so far from creating, is tending to eradicate, the love of itself from our mental structure, by letting only those families of men survive in whom it is not strong. The love of drunkenness is a purely accidental susceptibility of a brain, evolved for entirely different uses, and its causes are to be sought in the molecular realm, rather than in any possible order of ' outer relations. ' NECESSARY TRUTHS -EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 629 as we proceed ; so I will pass right on to a scrutiny of the actual mental structure which we find. THE GENESIS OF THE ELEMENTARY MENTAL CATEGORIES. We find : 1. Elementary sorts of sensation, and feelings of personal activity ; 2. Emotions ; desires ; instincts ; ideas of worth ; aes thetic ideas ; 3. Ideas of time and space and number ; 4. Ideas of difference and resemblance, and of their de grees. 5. Ideas of causal dependence among events; of end and means ; of subject and attribute. 6. Judgments affirming, denying, doubting, supposing any of the above ideas. 7. Judgments that the former judgments logically in- yolve, exclude, or are indifferent to, each other. Now we may postulate at the outset that all these forms of thought have a natural origin, if we could only get at it. That assumption must be made at the outset of every scientific investigation, or there is no temptation to pro ceed. But the first account of their origin which we are likely to hit upon is a snare. All these mental affections are ways of knowing objects. Most psychologists nowa days believe that the objects first, in some natural way, en gendered a brain from out of their midst, and then imprinted these various cognitive affections upon it. But how ? The ordinary evolutionist answer to this question is exceedingly simple-minded. The idea of most speculators seems to be that, since it suffices now for us to become acquainted with a complex object, that it should be simply present to us often enough, so it must be fair to assume universally that, with time enough given, the mere presence of the various objects and relations to be known must end by bringing about the latter's cognition, and that in this way all mental structure was from first to last evolved. Any ordinary Spencerite will tell you that just as the experience of blue objects wrought into our mind the color blue, and hard objects got it to feel hardness, so the presence of large and small objects in the world gave it the notion of 630 PSYCHOLOGY. size, moving objects made it aware of motion, and objective successions taught it time. Similarly in a world with dif ferent impressing things, the mind had to acquire a sense of difference, whilst the like parts of the world as they fell upon it kindled in it the perception of similarity. Outward sequences which sometimes held good, and sometimes failed, naturally engendered in it doubtful and uncertain forms of expectation, and ultimately gave rise to the dis junctive forms of judgment; whilst the hypothetic form, 'if a, then &,' was sure to ensue from sequences that were invariable in the outer world. On this view, if the outer order suddenly were to change its elements and modes, we should have no faculties to cognize the new order by. At most we should feel a sort of frustration and confusion. But little by little the new presence would work on us as the old one did ; and in course of time another set of psychic categories would arise, fitted to take cognizance of the altered world. This notion of the outer world inevitably building up a sort of mental duplicate of itself if we only give it time, is so easy and natural in its vagueness that one hardly knows how to start to criticise it. One thing, however, is obvious, namely that the manner in which we now become acquainted with complex objects need not in the least resemble the man ner in which the original elements of our consciousness grew i with this scene, associates fitted to combine with them in what we call a .-.-itional train of thought ? — rational because it leads to a conclusion we li.ive some organ to appreciate. We have no organ or faculty to appreciate the simply given order. The real world as it is given at this moment is the sum total of all its beings and events now. But can we think of such a sum ? Can we realize for an instant what a cross- section of all existence at a deiinite point of time would be? While I talk nod the flies buzz, a sea gull catches a fish at the mouth of the Amazon, a tree falls in the Adirondack wilderness, a man sneezes in Germany, a horse dies in Tartary, and twins are born in France. What does that mean ? Does the contem poraneity of these events with each other and with a million more as dis jointed as they form a rational bond between them, and unite them into anything that means for us a world ? Yet just such a collateral contem poraneity, and nothing else, is the real order of the world. It is an order with which we have nothing to do but to get away from it as fast as pos sible. As I said, we break it : we break it into histories, and we break it into arts, and we break it into sciences ; and then we begin to feel at home. We make ten thousand separate serial orders of it. On any one of these, we may react as if the rest did not exist. We discover among its parts re lations that were never given to sense at all, — mathematical relations, tan gents, squares, and roots and logarithmic functions, — and out of an infinite number of these we call certain ones essential and lawgiving, and ignore the rest. Essential these relations are, but only/or our purpose, the other relations being just as real and present as they ; and our purpose is to con ceive simply and to foresee Are not simple conception and prevision subject ive ends, pure and simple ? They are the ends of what we call science ; and the miracle of miracles, a miracle not yet exhaustively cleared up by any philosophy, is that the given order lends itself to the remodelling. It shows itself plastic to many of our scientific, to many of our aesthetic, to many of our practical purposes and ends." Cf. also Hodgson : Philos. of Kefl., ch. v ; Lotze : Logik, §§ 342-351 ; Sigwart : Logik, §§ 60-63, 105. 636 PSYCHOLOGY. enough) applicable to it. That is, it yields expressions which, at given places and times, can be translated into real values, or interpreted as definite portions of the chaos that falls upon our sense. It becomes thus a practical guide to our expectations as well as a theoretic delight. But I do not see how any one with a sense for the facts can possibly call our systems immediate results of ' experience ' in the ordinary sense. Every scientific conception is in the first instance a * spontaneous variation ' in some one's brain.* Tor one that proves useful and applicable there are a thou sand that perish through their worthlessness. Their gene sis is strictly akin to that of the flashes of poetry and sallies of wit to which the instable brain-paths equally give rise. But whereas the poetry and wit (like the science of the ancients) are their l own excuse for being,' and have to run the gauntlet of no farther test, the 'scientific' conceptions must prove their worth by being 'verified.' This test, how ever, is the cause of their preservation, not tha.t of their pro duction ; and one might as well account for the origin of Artemus Ward's jokes by the 'cohesion' of subjects with predicates in proportion to the 'persistence of the outer relations ' to which they ' correspond ' as to treat the genesis of scientific conceptions in the same ponderously unreal way. The most persistent outer relations which science be lieves in are never matters of experience at all, but have to be disengaged from under experience by a process of elimi nation, that is, by ignoring conditions which are always present. The elementary laws of mechanics, physics, and chemistry are all of this sort. The principle of uniformity in nature is of this sort ; it has to be sought under and in spite of the most rebellious appearances ; and our convic- * In an article entitled ' Great Men, Great Thoughts, and the Environ ment,' published in the Atlantic Monthly for October 1880, the reader •will find some ampler illustrations of these remarks. I have there tried to show that both mental and social evolution are to be conceived after the Darwinian fashion, and that the function of the environment properly so called is much more that of selecting forms, produced by invisible forces, than producing of such forms,— producing being the only function thought of by the pre-Darwinian evolutionists, and the only one on which stress is laid by such contemporary ones as Mr. Spencer and Mr. Allen. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 637 tion of its truth is far more like a religious faitli than like assent to a demonstration. The only cohesions which ex perience in the literal sense of the word produces in our mind are, as we contended some time back, the proximate laws of nature, and habitudes of concrete things, that heat melts ice, that salt preserves meat, that fish die out of water, and the like.* Such ' empirical truths ' as these we * " It is perfectly true that our world of experience begins with such associations as lead us to expect that what has happened to us will happen again. These associations lead the babe to look for milk from its nurse and not from its father, the child to believe that the apple he sees will taste good; and whilst they make him wish for it, they make him fear the bottle which contains his bitter medicine. But whereas a part of these associations grows confirmed by frequent repetition, another part is de stroyed by contradictory experiences; and the world becomes divided for us into two provinces, one in which we are at home and anticipate with confidence always the same sequences; another filled with alternating, variable, accidental occurrences. "... Accident is, in a wide sphere, such an every-day matter that we need not be surprised if it sometimes invades the territory where order is the rule. And one personification or another of the capricious power of chance easily helps us over the difficulties which further reflection might find in the exceptions. Yes, indeed, Exception has a peculiar fascination; it is a subject of astonishment, a Qavjua, and the credulity with which in this first stage of pure association we adopt our supposed rules is matched by the equal credulity with which we adopt the miracles that interfere with them. " The whole history of popular beliefs about nature refutes the notion that the thought of an universal physical order can possibly have arisen through the purely passive reception and association of particular percep tions. Indubitable as it is that all men infer from known cases to unknown, it is equally certain that this procedure, if restricted to the phenomenal materials that spontaneously offer themselves, would never have led to the belief in a general uniformity, but only to the belief that law and law lessness rule the world in motley alternation. From the point of view of strict empiricism nothing exists but the sum of particular perceptions with their coincidences on the one hand, their contradictions on the other. " That there is more order in the world than appears at first sight is not discovered till the order is looked for. The first impulse to look for it pro ceeds from practical needs: where ends must be attained, we must know Trustworthy means which infallibly possess a property or produce a result. But the practical need is only the first occasion for our reflection on the conditions of a true knowledge; even were there no such need, motives would still be present to carry us beyond the stage of mere association. For not with an equal interest, or rather with an equal lack of interest, does man contemplate those natural processes in which like is joined to like, and those in which like and unlike are joined; the former processes 638 PSYCHOLOGY. admitted to form an enormous part of human wisdom. The 1 scientific ' truths have to harmonize with these truths, or be given up as useless ; but they arise in the mind in no such passive associative way as that in which the simpler truths arise. Even those experiences which are used to prove a scientific truth are for the most part artificial expe riences of the laboratory gained after the truth itself has been conjectured. Instead of experiences engendering the 4 inner relations,' the inner relations are what engender the experiences here. What happens in the brain after experience has done its utmost is what happens in every material mass which has been fashioned by an outward force, — in every pudding or mortar, for example, which I may make with my hands. The fashioning from without brings the elements into collo cations which set new internal forces free to exert their effects in turn. And the random irradiations and resettle ments of our ideas, which supervene upon experience, and constitute our free mental play, are due entirely to these secondary internal processes, which vary enormously from brain to brain, even though the brains be exposed to exactly the same ' outer relations.' The higher thought- processes owe their being to causes which correspond far more to the sourings and fermentations of dough, the setting of mortar, or the subsidence of sediments in mixtures, than to the manipulations by which these physical aggregates came to be compounded. Our study of similar association and reasoning taught us that the whole superiority of man depended on the facility with which in his brain the paths worn by the most frequent outer cohesions could be rup tured. The causes of the instability, the reasons why now this point and now that become in him the seat of rupture, harmonize with the conditions of his thinking, the latter do not; in the former his concepts, judgments, inferences apply to realities, in the latter they have no such application. And thus the intellectual satisfac lion which at first comes to him without reflection, at last excites in him the conscious wish to rind realized throughout the entire phenomenal world those rational continuities, uniformities, and necessities which are the fun damental element and guiding principle of his own thought." (C. Sigwart: Logik, ii 380-2.) NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 639 we saw to be entirely obscure. (Vol. I. p. 580 ; Yol. II. p. 364.) The only clear thing about the peculiarity seems to be its interstitial character, and the certainty that no mere appeal to man's ' experience ' suffices to explain it. When we pass from scientific to aesthetic and ethical systems, every one readily admits that, although the ele ments are matters of experience, the peculiar forms of relation into which they are woven are incongruent with the order of passively received experience. The world of aesthetics and ethics is an ideal world, a Utopia, a world which the outer relations persist in contradicting, but which we as stubbornly persist in striving to make actual. Why do we thus invincibly crave to alter the given order of nature ? Simply because other relations among things are far more interesting to us and more charming than the mere rates of frequency of their time- and space-conjunctions. These other relations are all secondary and brain-born, * spontaneous variations ' most of them, of our sensibility, whereby certain elements of experience, and certain arrange ments in time and space, have acquired an agreeableness which otherwise would not have been felt. It is true that habitual arrangements may also become agreeable. But this agreeableness of the merely habitual is felt to be a mere ape and counterfeit of real inward fitness ; and one sign of intelligence is never to mistake the one for the other. There are then ideal and inward relations amongst th# o5- jects of our thought which can in no intelligible sense whatever be interpreted as reproductions of the order of outer experi ence. In the aesthetic and ethical realms they conflict with its order — the early Christian with his kingdom of heaven, and the contemporary anarchist with his abstract dream of justice, will tell you that the existing order must perish, root and branch, ere the true order can come. Now the peculiarity of those relations among the objects of our thought which are dubbed ' scientific * is this, that although they no. more are inward reproductions of the outer order thfiii the ethical and aesthetic relations are, yet they do not conflict with that order, but, once having sprung up by the play of the inward forces, are found — some of them at least, namely the only ones which have survived long enough to 640 PSYCHOLOGY. be matters of record — to be congruent with the time- and space-relations which our impressions affect. In other words, though nature's materials lend them selves slowly and discouragingly to our translation of them into ethical forms, but more readily into aesthetic forms ; to translation into scientific forms they lend themselves with relative ease and completeness. The translation, it is true, will probably never be ended. The perceptive order does not give way, nor the right conceptive substitute for it arise, at our bare word of command.* It is often a deadly fight • and many a man of science can say, like Johannes Miiller' after an investigation, ' Es klebt Blut an der Arbeit.' But victory after victory makes us sure that the essential doom of our enemy is defeat.f * Cf. Hodgson : Philosophy of Reflection, book n, chap. v. f The aspiration to be ' scientific ' is such an idol of the tribe to the present generation, is so sucked in with his mother's milk by every one of us, that we find it hard to conceive of a creature who should not feel it, and harder still to treat it freely as the altogether peculiar and one-sided subjective interest which it is. But as a matter of fact, few even of the cultivated members of the race have shared it ; it was invented but a gen eration or two ago. In the middle ages it meant only impious magic ; and the way in which it even now strikes orientals is charmingly shown in the letter of a Turkish cadi to an English traveller asking him for statistical information, which Sir A. Layard prints at the end of his ' Nineveh and Babylon. ' The document is too full of edification not to be given in full. It runs thus : • My Illustrious Friend, and Joy of my Liver! "The thing you ask of me is both difficult and useless. Although I fiave passed all my days in this place, I have neither counted the houses aor inquired into the number of the inhabitants; and as to what one person loads on his mules and the other stows away in the bottom of his ship, that is no business of mine. But, above all, as to the previous history of this city, God only knows the amount of dirt and confusion that the infidels may have eaten before the coming of the sword of Islam. It were un profitable for us to inquire into it. "O my soul 1 O my lamb ! seek not after the things which concern thee not. Thou earnest unto us and we welcomed thee : go in peace. " Of a truth thou hast spoken many words ; and there is no harm done, < r>r the speaker is one and the listener is another. After the fashion of thy people thou hast wandered from one place to another, until thou art happy *nd content in none. We (praise be to God) were born here, and never Desire to quit it. Is it possible, then, that the idea of a general intercourse NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 041 THE GENESIS OF THE PURE SCIENCEb. I have now stated in general terms the relation of the natural sciences to experience strictly so called, and shall complete what I have to say by reverting to the subject on , a later page. At present I will pass to the so-called pure! or a priori sciences of Classification, Logic, and Mathematics/ My thesis concerning these is that they are even less than the natural sciences effects of the order of the world as it comes to our experience. THE PURE SCIENCES EXPRESS RESULTS OF COMPARISON exclusively ; comparison is not a conceivable effect of the order in which outer impressions are experienced — it is one of the house-born (p. 627) portions of our mental structure; t tier ef ore the pure sciences form a body of proposi tions with whose genesis experience has nothing to do. First, consider the nature of comparison. The relations of resemblance and difference among things have nothing to do with the time- and space-order in which we may experience the latter. Suppose a hundred beings created by God and gifted with the faculties of memory and comparison. Suppose that upon each of them the same lot of sensa tions are imprinted, but in different orders. Let some between mankind should make any impression on our understandings ? God forbid ! "Listen, O my son ! There is no wisdom equal unto the belief in God I He created the world, and shall we liken ourselves unto Him in seeking to penetrate into the mysteries of His creation ? Shall we say, Behold this star spinneth round that star, and this other star with a tail goeth and cometh in so many years ! Let it go ! He from whose hand it came will guide and direct it. ' • But thou wilt say unto me, Stand aside, O man, for I am more learned than thou art, and have seen more things. If thou thinkest that thou art in this respect better than I am, thou art welcome. I praise God that I seek not that which I require not, Thou art learned in the things I care not for ; and as for that which thou hast seen, I spit upon it. Wil] much knowledge create thee a double belly, or wilt thou seek Paradise with thine eyes ? " O my friend ! if thou wilt be happy, say, There is no God but God ! Do no evil, and thus wilt thou fear neither man nor death ; for surely thine hour will come ! " The meek in spirit (El Fakir) ALI ZADI." 642 PSYCHOLOGY. of them have no single sensation more than once. Let some have this one and others that one repeated. Let every conceivable permutation prevail. And then let the magic-lantern show die out, and keep the creatures in a void eternity, with naught but their memories to muse upon. Inevitably in their long leisure they will begin to play with the items of their experience and rearrange them, make classificatory series of them, place gray between white and black, orange between red and yellow, and trace all other degrees of resemblance and difference. And this new con struction will be absolutely identical in all the hundred creatures, the diversity of the sequence of the original ex periences having no effect as regards this rearrangement. Any and every form of sequence will give the same result, because the result expresses the relation between the inward natures of the sensations ; and to that the question of their outward succession is quite irrelevant. Black will differ from white just as much in a world in which they always come close together as in one in which they always come far apart ; just as much in one in which they appear rarely as in one in which they appear all the time. But the advocate of ' persistent outer relations ' may still return to the charge : These are what make us so sure that white and black differ, he may say ; for in a world where sometimes black resembled white and sometimes differed from it, we could never be so sure. It is because in this world black and white have always differed that the sense of their difference has become a necessary form of thought. The pair of colors on the one hand and the sense of differ ence on the other, inseparably experienced, not only by our selves but by our ancestors, have become inseparably con nected in the mind. Not through any essential structure of the mind, which made difference the only possible feel ing which they could arouse ; no, but because they simply did differ so often that at last they begat in us an impotency to imagine them doing anything else, and made us accept such a fabulous account as that just presented, of creatures to whom a single experience would suffice to make us feel the necessity of this relation. NECESSARY TRUTHS- EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 643 I know not whether Mr. Spencer would subscribe to this or not ; — nor do I care, for there are mysteries which press more for solution than the meaning of this vague writer's words. But to me such an explanation of our difference-judgment is absolutely unintelligible. We now find black and white different, the explanation says, be cause we have always have so found them. But why should we always have so found them ? Why should difference have popped into our heads so invariably with the thought of them ? There must have been either a subjective or an objective reason. The subjective reason can only be that our minds were so constructed that a sense of difference was the only sort of conscious transition possible between black and white; the objective reason can only be that difference was always there, with these colors, outside the mind as an objective fact. The subjective reason explains outer frequency by inward structure, not inward structure by outer frequency ; and so surrenders the experience- theory. The objective reason simply says that if an outer difference is there the mind must needs know it — which is no explanation at all, but a mere appeal to the fact that somehow the mind does know what is there. The only clear thing to do is to give up the sham of a pretended explanation, and to fall back on the fact that the sense of difference has arisen, in some natural manner doubtless, but in a manner which we do not understand. It was by the back-stairs way, at all events ; and, from the very first, happened to be the only mode of reaction by which consciousness could feel the transition from one term to another of what (in consequence of this very reaction) we now call a contrasted pair. In noticing the differences and resemblances of things, and their degrees, the mind feels its own activity, and has given the name of comparison thereto. It need not compare its materials, but if once roused to do so, it can compare them with but one result, and this a fixed consequence of the nature of the materials themselves. Difference and re semblance are thus relations between ideal objects, or con ceptions as such. To learn whether black and white differ, 644 PSYCHOLOGY. I need not consult the world of experience at all ; the mere ideas suffice. What I mean by black differs from what 1 mean by white, whether such colors exist extra mentem meam or not. If they ever do so exist, they will differ. White things may blacken, but the black of them will differ from the white of them, so long as I mean anything definite bj these three words.* / shall now in what follows call aU propositions ivhich ex press time- and space-relations empirical propositions ; and 1 shall give the name of rational propositions to all propositions which express the results of a comparison. The latter denomi nation is in a sense arbitrary, for resemblance and differ ence are not usually held to be the only rational relations between things. I will next proceed to show, however, how many other rational relations commonly supposed dis tinct can be resolved into these, so that my definition of rational propositions will end, I trust, by proving less arbi trary than it now appears to be. SERIES OF EVEN DIFFERENCE AND MEDIATE COMPARISON. In Chapter XII we saw that the mind can at successive moments mean the same, and that it gradually comes into possession of a stock of permanent and fixed meanings, ideal objects, or conceptions, some of which are universal qualities, like the black and white of oui example, and some, individual things. We now see that not only are the objects permanent mental possessions, but the results of their com parison are permanent too. The objects and their differ ences together form an immutable system. The same ob jects, compared in the same way, always give the same results ; " Though a man in a fever should from sugar have a bitter taste which at another time would produce a sweet one, yet the idea of bitter in that man's mind would be as clear and distinct from the idea of sweet as if he had tasted only gall. Nor does it make any more confusion between the two ideas of sweet and bitter that the same sort of body produces at one time one and at another time another idea by the taste, than it makes a confusion in two ideas of white and sweet, or white and round, that the same piece of sugar produces them both in the mind at the same time. * Locke's Essay, bk. n. ch. xi. § 3. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE, 645 if the result be not the same, then the objects are not those originally meant. This last principle, which we may call the axiom of con- stant result, holds good throughout all our mental opera tions, not only when we compare, but when we add, divide, class, or infer a given matter in any conceivable way. Its most general expression would be " the Same operated on in the same way gives the Same." In mathematics it takes the form of " equals added to, or subtracted from, equals give equals," and the like. We shall meet with it again. The next thing which we observe is that tlie operation of comparing may be repeated on its own results ; in other words, that we can think of the various resemblances and differences which we find and compare them with each other, making differences and resemblances of a higher order. The mind thus becomes aware of sets of similar differ ences, and forms series of terms with the same kind and amount of difference between them, terms which, as they succeed each other, maintain a constant direction of serial increase. This sense of constant direction in a series of operations we saw in Chapter XIII (p. 490) to be a cardinal mental fact. "A differs from B differs from C differs from D, etc.," makes a series only when the differences are in the same direction. In any such difference-series all terms differ in just the same way from their predecessors. The num bers 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... the notes of the chromatic scale in music, are familiar examples. As soon as the mind grasps such a series as a whole, it perceives that two terms taken far apart differ more than two terms taken near together, and that any one term differs more from a remote than from a near successor, and this no matter what the terms may be, or what the sort of difference may be, provided it is always the same sort. This PRINCIPLE OF MEDIATE COMPARISON might be briefly (though obscurely) expressed by the formula "more than the more is more than the less " — the words more and less standing simply for degrees of increase along a constant direction of differences. Such a formula would cover all possible cases, as, earlier than early is earlier than late, 646 PSYCHOLOGY worse than bad is worse than good, east of east is east of west ; etc., etc., ad libitum.* Symbolically, we might write itasa<&, 3 ; and bk. in. chap. xxiv. § 5. PS YCHOL OOT. Mill is himself compelled to say, to find the number four in it, and so on. The relation of numbers to experience is just like that of < kinds ' in logic. So long as an experience will keep its kind we can handle it by logic. So long as it will keep its number we can deal with it by arithmetic. Sensibly, how ever, things are constantly changing their numbers, just as they are changing their kinds. They are forever breaking apart and fusing. Compounds and their elements are never numerically identical, for the elements are sensibly many and the compounds sensibly one. Unless our arithmetic is to remain without application to life, we must somehow make more numerical continuity than we spontaneously find. Accordingly Lavoisier discovers his weight-units which re main the same in compounds and elements, though volume- units and quality-units all have changed. A great discovery ! And modern science outdoes it by denying that compounds exist at all. There is no such thing as 'water' for 'science;' that is only a handy name for H2 and O when they have got into the position H-O-H, and then affect our senses in a novel way. The modern theories of atoms, of heat, and of gases are, in fact, only intensely artificial devices for gaining that constancy in the numbers of things which sensible experience will not show. " Sensible things are not the things for me," says Science, "because in their changes they will not keep their numbers the same. Sensible qualities are not the qualities for me, because they can with difficulty be numbered at all. These hypothetic atoms, however, are the things, these hypothetic masses and velocities are the qualities for me ; they will stay num bered all the time." By such elaborate inventions, and at such a cost to the imagination, do men succeed in making for themselves a world in which real things shall be coerced per fas aut nefas under arithmetical law. The other branch of mathematics is geometry. Its ob jects are also ideal creations. Whether nature contain circles or not, I can know what I mean by a circle and can stick to my meaning ; and when I mean two circles I NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 657 mean two things of an identical kind. The axiom of con stant results (see above, p. 645) holds in geometry. The same forms^ treated in the same way (added, subtracted, or compared), give the same results — how shouldn't they ? The axioms of mediate comparison (p. 645), of logic (p. 648), and of number (p. 654) all apply to the forms which we imagine in space, inasmuch as these resemble or differ from each other, form kinds, and are numerable things. But in addition to these general principles, which are true of space-forms only as they are of other mental conceptions, there are certain axioms relative to space-forms exclusively, which we must briefly consider. Three of them give marks of identity among straight lines, planes, and parallels. Straight lines which have two points, planes which have three points, parallels to a given line which have one point, in common, coalesce throughout. Some say that the certainty of our belief in these axioms is due to repeated experiences of their truth ; others that it is due to an intuitive acquaintance with the properties of space. It is neither. We experience lines enough which pass through two points only to separate again, only we won't call them straight. Similarly of planes and parallels, We have a definite idea of what we mean by each of these words ; and when something different is offered us, we see the difference. Straight lines, planes, and parallels, as they figure in geometry, are mere inventions of our faculty for apprehending serial increase. The farther continuations of these forms, we say, shall bear the same relation to their last visible parts which these did to still earlier parts. It thus follows (from that axiom of skipped intermediaries which obtains in all regular series) that parts of these figures separated by other parts must agree in direction, just as contiguous parts do. This uniformity of direction throughout is, in fact, all that makes us care for these forms, gives them their beauty, and stamps them into fixed conceptions in our mind. But obviously if two lines, or two planes, with a common segment, were to part company beyond the segment, it could only be because the direction of at least one of them had changed. Parting company in lines and planes means changing direction, means assuming 658 PSYCHOLOGY. a new relation to the parts that pre-exist ; and assuming a new relation means ceasing to be straight or plane. If we mean by a parallel a line that will never meet a second line ; and if we have one such line drawn through a point, any new line drawn through that point which does not coalesce with the first must be inclined to it, and if inclined to it must approach the second, i.e., cease to be parallel with it. No properties of outlying space need come in here : only a definite conception of uniform direction, and constancy in sticking to one's point. The other two axioms peculiar to geometry are that figures can be moved in space without change, and that no variation in the way of subdividing a given amount of space alters its total quantity.* This last axiom is similar to what we found to obtain in numbers. ' The whole is equal to its parts ' is an abridged way of expressing it. A man is not the same biological whole if we cut him in two at the neck as if we divide him at the ankles ; but geometrically he is the same whole, no matter in which place we cut him. The axiom about figures being movable in space is rather a postulate than an axiom. So far as they are so movable, then certain fixed equalities and differences obtain between forms, 710 matter ivhere placed. But if translation through space warped or magnified forms, then the relations of equality, etc., would always have to be expressed with a position-qualification added. A geometry as absolutely certain as ours could be invented on the supposition of such a space, if the laws of its warping and deformation were fixed. It would, however, be much more complicated than our geometry, which makes the simplest possible sup position ; and finds, luckily enough, that it is a supposition with which the space of our experience seems to agree. By means of these principles, all playing into each other's hands, the mutual equivalences of an immense num ber of forms can be traced, even of such as at first sight bear hardly any resemblance to each other. We move and * The subdivision itself consumes none of the space. In all practical experience our subdivisions do consume space. They consume it in our geometrical figures. But for simplicity's sake, in geometry we postulate subdivisions which violate experience and consume none of it. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 659 turn them mentally, and find that parts of them will super pose. We add imaginary lines which subdivide or enlarge them, and find that the new figures resemble each other in ways which show us that the old ones are equivalent too. We thus end by expressing all sorts of forms in terms of other forms, enlarging our knowledge of the kinds of things which certain other kinds of things are, or to which they are equivalent. The result is a new system of mental objects which can be treated as identical for certain purposes, a new series of iVs almost indefinitely prolonged, just like the series of equivalencies among numbers, part of which the multipli cation-table expresses. And all this is in the first instance regardless of the coexistences and sequences of nature, and regardless of whether the figures we speak of have ever been outwardly experienced or not. CONSCIOUSNESS OF SEKIES IS THE BASIS OF KATIONALITY. Classification, logic, and mathematics all result, then, from the mere play of the mind comparing its conceptions, no matter whence the latter may have come. The essential condition for the formation of all these sciences is that we should have grown capable of apprehending series as such, and of distinguishing them as homogeneous or hetero geneous, and as possessing definite directions of what I have called 'increase.' This consciousness of series is a human perfection which has been gradually evolved, and which varies greatly from man to man. There is no accounting for it as a result of habitual associations among outward impressions, so we must simply ascribe it to the factors, whatever they be, of inward cerebral growth. Once this consciousness attained to, however, mediate thought be comes possible ; with our very awareness of a series may go an awareness that dropping terms out of it will leave identical relations between the terms that remain ; and thus arises a perception of relations between things so naturally separate that we should otherwise never have compared them together at all. The axiom of skipped intermediaries applies, however, only to certain particular series, and among them to those 660 PSYCHOLOGY. which we have considered, in which the recurring relation is either of difference, of likeness, of kind, of numerical ad dition, or of prolongation in the same linear or plane direc tion. It is therefore not a purely formal law of thinking,, but flows from the nature of the matters thought about. It will not do to say universally that in all series of homo geneously related terms the remote members are related to each other as the near ones are ; for that will often be untrue. The series A is not B is not C is not D . . . does not permit the relation to be traced between remote terms. From two negations no inference can be drawn. Nor, to become more concrete, does the lover of a woman generally love her beloved, or the contradictor of a contradictor con tradict whomever he contradicts. The slayer of a slayer does not slay the latter's victim ; the acquaintances or ene mies of a man need not be each other's acquaintances or enemies ; nor are two things which are on top of a third thing necessarily on top of each other. All skipping of intermediaries and transfer of relations occurs within homogeneous series. But not all homoge neous series allow of intermediaries being skipped and re lations transferred. It depends on which series they are, on what relations they contain.* Let it not be said that it is a mere matter of verbal association, due to the fact that language sometimes permits us to transfer the name of a relation over skipped intermediaries, and sometimes does not ; as where we call men ' progenitors ' of their remote as well as of their immediate posterity, but refuse to call them * fathers ' thereof. There are relations which are intrinsi cally transferable, whilst others are not. The relation of condition, e.g., is intrinsically transferable. What conditions a condition conditions what it conditions — " cause of cause is cause of effect." The relations of negation and frustration, on the other hand, are not transferable : what frustrates a frustration does not frustrate what it frustrates. No changes of terminology would annul the intimate difference between these two cases. * Cf . A. de Morgan : Syllabus of a proposed System of Logic (1860), pp, 46-56. NECESSARY TRUTHS-EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 661 Nothing but the clear sight of the ideas themselves shows whether the axiom of skipped intermediaries applies to them or not. Their connections, immediate and remote, flow from their inward natures. We try to consider them in certain ways, to bring them into certain relations, and we find that sometimes we can and sometimes we cannot. The question whether there are or are not inward and essential connections between conceived objects as such, really is the same thing as the question whether we can get any new perception from mentally coupling them together, or pass from one to another by a mental operation which gives a result. In the case of some ideas and operations we get a result ; but no result in the case of others. Where a result comes, it is due exclusively to the nature of the ideas and of the opera tion. Take blueness and yellowness, for example. We can operate on them in some ways, but not in other ways. We can compare them ; but we cannot add one to or subtract it from the other. We can refer them to a common kind, color ; but we cannot make one a kind of the other, or infer one from the other. This has nothing to do with experience. For we can add blue pigment to yellow pigment, and sub^ tract it again, and get a result both times. Only we know perfectly that this is no addition or subtraction of the blue -and yellow qualities or natures themselves.* There is thus no denying the fact that the mind is filed with necessary and eternal relations ivhich it finds betiveen cer tain of its ideal conceptions, and, ivhich form a determinate system, independent of the order of frequency in which experience may have associated the conception's originals in time and space. Shall we continue to call these sciences 'intuitive,' 'in nate,' or ' a priori ' bodies of truth, or not ?f Personally * Cf. Locke's Essay, bk. n. chap. xvn. § 6. f Some readers may expect me to plunge into the old debate as to whether the a priori truths are ' analytic ' or ' synthetic.' It seems to me that the distinction is one of Kant's most unhappy legacies, for the reason that it is impossible to make it sharp. No one will say that such analytic judgments as " equidistant lines can nowhere meet " are pure tautologies. The predicate is a somewhat new way of conceiving as well as of naming the subject. There is something ' ampliative ' in our greatest truisms, our state of mind is richer after than before we have uttered them. This 662 PSYCHOLOGY. I should like to do so. But I hesitate to use the terms, on account of the odium which controversial history has made the whole of their connotation for many worthy per sons. The most politic way not to alienate these readers is to flourish the name of the immortal Locke. For in truth I have done nothing more in the previous pages than to make a little more explicit the teachings of Locke's fourth book : k'The immutability of the same relations between the same im mutable things is now the idea that shows him that if the three angles of a triangle were once equal to two right angles, they will always be equal to two right ones. And hence he comes to be certain that what was once true in the case is always true ; what ideas once agreed will always agree . . . Upon this ground it is that particular demonstrations in mathematics afford general knowledge. If, then, the perception that the same ideas will eternally have the same habitudes and relations be not a sufficient ground of knowledge, there could be no knowledge of general propositions in mathematics. ... All general knowledge lies only in our own thoughts, and consists barely in the contemplation of our abstract ideas. Wherever we perceive any agreement or disagree ment amongst them, there we have general knowledge ; and by putting the names of those ideas together accordingly in propositions, can with certainty pronounce general truths. . . . What is once known of such ideas will be perpetually and forever true. So that, as to all general knowledge, we must search and find it only in our own minds and it is only the examining of our own ideas that furnisheth us with that. Truths belonging to essences of things (that is, to abstract ideas) are being the case, the question "at what point does the new state of mind cease to be implicit in the old ? " is too vague to be answered. The only sharp way of denning synthetic propositions would be to say that they ex press a relation between two data at least. But it is hard to find any prop osition which cannot be construed as doing this. Even verbal definitions do it. Such painstaking attempts as that latest one by Mr. D. G. Thomp son to prove all necessary judgments to be analytic (System of Psychology, ii. pp. 232 ff.) seem accordingly but nugce difficiles, and little better than wastes of ink and paper. All philosophic interest vanishes from the question, the moment one ceases to ascribe to any a priori truths (whether analytic or synthetic) that " legislative character for all possible experience " which Kant believed in. We ourselves have denied such legislative character, and contended that it was for experience itself to prove whether its data can or cannot be assimilated to those ideal terms between which a priori relations obtain. The analytic-synthetic debate is thus for us devoid of all significance. On the whole, the best recent treat ment of the question known to me is in one of A. Spir's works, his Denkeu und Wirklichkeit, I think, but 1 cannot now find the page. NECESSARY TRUTHS-EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 663 eternal, and are to be found out only by the contemplation of those essences. . . . Knowledge is the consequence of the ideas (be they what they will) that are in our minds, producing there certain general proposi tions. . . . Such propositions are therefore called 'eternal truths,' . . . because, being once made about abstract ideas so as to be true, they will, whenever they can be supposed to be made again, at anytime past or to come, by a mind having those ideas, always actually be true. For names being supposed to stand perpetually for the same ideas, and the same ideas having immutably the same habitudes one to another, prop ositions concerning any abstract ideas that are once true must needs be eternal verities.'1 But what are these eternal verities, these * agreements,' which the mind discovers by barely considering its own fixed meanings, except what I have said ? — relations of like ness and difference, immediate or mediate, between the terms of certain series. Classification is serial comparison, logic mediate subsumption, arithmetic mediate equality of different bundles of attention-strokes, geometry mediate equality of different ways of carving space. None of these eternal verities has anything to say about facts, about what is or is not in the world. Logic does not say whether Soc rates, men, mortals or immortals exist; arithmetic does not tell us where her 7's, 5's, and 12's are to be found; ge ometry affirms not that circles and rectangles are real. All that these sciences make us sure of is, that if these things are anywhere to be found, the eternal verities will obtain of them. Locke accordingly never tires of telling us that the " universal propositions of whose truth or falsehood we can have cer tain knowledge, concern not existence. . . . These universal and self- evident principles, being only our constant, clear, and distinct knowl edge of our own ideas more general or comprehensive, can assure us of nothing that passes without the mind; their certainty is founded only upon the knowledge of each idea by itself, and of its distinction from others ; about which we cannot be mistaken whilst they are in our minds. . . . The mathematician considers the truth and properties belonging to a rectangle or circle only as they are in idea in his own mind. For it is possible he never found either of them existing mathe matically, i.e., precisely true, in his life. But yet the knowledge he has of any truths or properties belonging to a circle, or any other math ematical figure, are nevertheless true and certain even of real things existing; because real things are no farther concerned nor intended to be meant by any such propositions, than as things really agree to those archetypes in his mind. Is it true of the idea of a triangle, that its 664 PSYCHOLOGY. three angles are equal to two right ones ? It is true also of a triangle wherever it really exists. Whatever other figure exists that is not ex actly answerable to that idea in his mind is not at all concerned in that proposition. And therefore he is certain all his knowledge concerning such ideas is real knowledge: because, intending things no farther than they agree with those his ideas, he is sure what he knows concerning those figures when they have barely an ideal existence in his mind will hold true of them also when they have a real existence in matter. " But "that any or what bodies do exist, that we are left to our senses to discover to us as far as they can." * Locke accordingly distinguishes between ' mental truth ' and 'real truth.' t The former is intuitively certain; the latter dependent on experience. Only hy pathetically can we affirm intuitive truths of real things — by supposing, namely, that real things exist which correspond exactly with the ideal subjects of the intuitive propositions. If our senses corroborate the supposition all goes well. But note the strange descent in Locke's hands of the dig nity of a priori propositions. By the ancients they were considered, without farther question, to reveal the constitu tion of Keality. Archetypal things existed, it was assumed, in the relations in which we had to think them. The mind's necessities were a warrant for those of Being ; and it was not till Descartes' time that scepticism had so advanced (in ' dog matic ' circles) that the warrant must itself be warranted, and the veracity of the Deity invoked as a reason for hold ing fast to our natural beliefs. But the intuitive propositions of Locke leave us as re gards outer reality none the better for their possession. We still have to "go to our senses" to find what the reality is. The vindication of the intuitionist position is thus a barren victory. The eternal verities which the very structure of our mind lays hold of do not neces sarily themselves lay hold on extra-mental being, nor have they, as Kant pretended later,:): a legislating character even * Book iv. chaps, ix. § 1; vn. 14. t Chap. v. §§ 6, 8. £ Kant, by the way, made a strange tactical blunder in his way of showing that the forms of our necessary thought are underived from ex perience. He insisted on thought-forms with which experience largely agrees, forgetting that the only forms which could not by any possibility NECESSARY TRUTHS-EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE, 665 lor all possible experience. They are primarily interesting only as subjective facts. They stand waiting in the mind, forming a beautiful ideal network ; and the most we can say is that we hope to discover outer realities over which the network may be flung so that ideal and real may coincide. And this brings us back to ' science ' from which we di- Terted our attention so long ago (see p. 640). Science thinka that she has discovered the outer realities in question, Atoms and ether, with no properties but masses and veloc ities expressible by numbers, and paths expressible by an alytic formulas, these at last are things over which the mathematico-logical network may be flung, and by suppos ing which instead of sensible phenomena science becomes yearly more able to manufacture for herself a world about which rational propositions may be framed. Sensible phe nomena are pure delusions for the mechanical philosophy. The * things ' and qualities we instinctively believe in dc not exist. The only realities are swarming solids in ever- lasting motion, undulatory or continued, whose expression less and meaningless changes of position form the history of the world, and are deducible from initial collocations and habits of movement hypothetically assumed. Thous ands of years ago men started to cast the chaos of nature's sequences and juxtapositions into a form that might seem intelligible. Many were their ideal prototypes of rational order : teleological and aesthetic ties between things, causal and substantial bonds, as well as logical and mathematical relations. The most promising of these ideal systems at first were of course the richer ones, the sentimental ones. The baldest and least promising were the mathematical ones; but the history of the latter's application is a history of steadily advancing successes, whilst that of the sentimentally richer be the results of experience would be such as experience violated. The first thing a Kantian ought to do is to discover forms of judgment to which no order in ' things ' runs parallel. These would indeed be features native to the mind. 1 owe this remark to Herr A. Spir, in whose 'Denken und Wirklichkeit ' it is somewhere contained. I have myself already to some extent proceeded, and in the pages which follow shall proceed still farther, to show the originality of the mind's structure In this way. 666 PSYCHOLOGY. systems is one of relative sterility and failure.* Take those aspects of phenomena which interest you as a human being most, and class the phenomena as perfect and imperfect, as -ends and means to ends, as high and low, beautiful and ugly, positive and negative, harmonious and discordant, fit and unfit, natural and unnatural, etc., and barren are all your results. In the ideal world the kind * precious ' has char acteristic properties. What is precious should be pre served ; unworthy things should be sacrificed for its sake ; exceptions made on its account ; its preciousness is a rea son for other things' actions, and the like. But none of these things need happen to your ' precious ' object in the real world. Call the things of nature as much as you like by sentimental, moral, and aesthetic names, no natural consequences follow from the naming. They may be of the kinds you allege, but they are not of l the kind's Jcind': and the last great system-maker of this sort, Hegel, was obliged explicitly to repudiate logic in order to make any inferences at all from the names he called things by. But when you give things mathematical and mechanical names and call them just so many solids in just such posi tions, describing just such paths with just such velocities, all is changed. Your sagacity finds its reward in the veri fication by nature of all the deductions which you may next proceed to make. Your ' things ' realize all the consequences of the names by which you classed them. The modern mechanico-physical philosophy of which we are all so proud, because it includes the nebular cosmogony, the conservation of energy, the kinetic theory of heat and * Yet even so late as Berkeley's time one could write : " As in reading other books a wise man will choose to fix his thoughts on the sense and apply it to use, rather than lay them out in grammatical remarks on the language : so in perusing the volume of nature methinks it is beneath the dignity of the mind to affect an exactness in reducing each particular phe nomenon to general rules, or showing how it follows from them. We should propose to ourselves nobler views, namely, to recreate and exalt the mind with a prospect of the beauty, order, extent, and variety of natural things : hence, by proper inferences, to enlarge our notions of the grau- deur, wisdom, and beneficence of the Creator," etc. , etc., etc. (Principles of Human Knowledge, § 109.) NECESSARY TRUTHS-EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 667 gases, etc., etc., begins by saying that the only facts are collocations and motions of primordial solids, and the only laws the changes of motion which changes in collocation bring. The ideal which this philosophy strives after is a mathematical world-formula, by which, if all the colloca tions and motions at a given moment were known, it would be possible to reckon those of any wished-for future mo ment, by simply considering the necessary geometrical, arithmetical, and logical implications. Once we have the world in this bare shape, we can fling our net of a priori relations over all its terms, and pass from one of its phases to another by inward thought-necessity. Of course it is a world with a very minimum of rational sfuff. The senti mental facts and relations are butchered at a blow. But the rationality yielded is so superbly complete inform that to many minds this atones for the loss, and reconciles the thinker to the notion of a purposeless universe, in which all the things and qualities men love, dulcissima mundi nomina, are but illusions of our fancy attached to accidental clouds of dust which will be dissipated by the eternal cosmic weather as carelessly as they were formed. The popular notion that ' Science ' is forced on the mind ab extra, and that our interests have nothing to do with its constructions, is utterly absurd. The craving to believe that the things of the world belong to kinds which are rela ted by inward rationality together, is the parent of Science as well as of sentimental philosophy; and the original in vestigator always preserves a healthy sense of how plastic the materials are in his hands. " Once for all," says Helmholtz in beginning that little work of his which laid the foundations of the 'conservation of energy,' "it is the task of the physical sciences to seek for laws by which particular pro cesses in nature may be referred to general rules, and deduced from such again. Such rules (for example the laws of reflection or refrac tion of light, or that of Mariotte and Gay-Lussac for gas- volumes) are evidently nothing but generic-concepts for embracing whole classes of phenomena. The search for them is the business of the experimental division of our Science. Its theoretic division, on the other hand, tries to discover the unknown causes of processes from their visible effects ; tries to understand them by the law of causality. . . . The ultimate goal of theoretic physics is to find the last unchanging causes 668 PSYCHOLOGY. of the processes in Nature. Whether all processes be really ascribable to such causes, whether, in other words, nature be completely intelligible, or whether there be changes which would elude the law of a necessary causality, and fall into a realm of spontaneity or freedom, is not here the place to determine ; but at any rate it is clear that the Science whose aim it is to make nature appear intelligible [die Natur zu, begreifen] must start with the assumption of her intelligibility, and draw consequences in conformity with this assumption, until irrefu table facts show the limitations of this method. . . . The postulate that natural phenomena must be reduced to changeless ultimate causes next shapes itself so that forces unchanged by time must be found to be these causes. Now in Science we have already found portions of mat ter with changeless forces (indestructible qualities), and called them (chemical) elements. If, then, we imagine the world composed of ele ments with inalterable qualities, the only changes that can remain possible in such a world are spatial changes, i.e. movements, and the only outer relations which can modify the action of the forces are spatial too . or, in other words, the forces are motor forces dependent for their effect only on spatial relations. More exactly still : The phe nomena of nature must be reduced to [zuruckgefuhrt, conceived as, classed as] motions of material points with inalterable motor forces acting according to space-relations alone. . . . But points have no mutual space-relations except their distance, . . . and a motor force which they exert upon each other can cause nothing but a change of distance — i.e. be an attractive or a repulsive force. . . . And its inten sity can only depend on distance. So that at last the task of Physics resolves itself into this, to refer phenomena to inalterable attractive and repulsive forces whose intensity varies with distance. The solu tion of this task would at the same time be. the condition of Nature's complete intelligibility."* The subjective interest leading to the assumption could not be more candidly expressed. What makes the assump tion ' scientific ' and not merely poetic, what makes a Helm- holtz and his kin discoverers, is that the things of Nature turn out to act as if they were of the kind assumed. They behave as such mere drawing and driving atoms would be have ; and so far as they have been distinctly enough trans lated into molecular terms to test the point, so far a certain fantastically ideal object, namely, the mathematical sum containing their mutual distances and velocities, is found to be constant throughout all their movements. This sum is called the total energy of the molecules considered. Its con- *Die Erhaltung der Kraft (1847), pp. 2-6. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 669 stancy or ' conservation ' gives the name to the hypothesis of molecules and central forces from which it was logically deduced. Take any other mathematico-mechanical theory and it is the same. They are all translations of sensible experi ences into other forms, substitutions of items between which ideal relations of kind, number, form, equality, etc., obtain, for items between which no such relations obtain ; coupled with declarations that the experienced form is false and the ideal form true, declarations which are justified by the ap pearance of new sensible experiences at just those times and places at which we logically infer that their ideal cor relates ought to be. Wave-hypotheses thus make us pre dict rings of darkness and color, distortions, dispersions, changes of pitch in sonorous bodies moving from us, etc. ; molecule-hypotheses lead to predictions of vapor- density, freezing point, etc., — all which predictions fall true. Thus the world grows more orderly and rational to the mind, which passes from one feature of it to another by de ductive necessity, as soon as it conceives it as made up of so few and so simple phenomena as bodies with no proper ties but number and movement to and fro. METAPHYSICAL AXIOMS. But alongside of these ideal relations between terms which the world verifies, there are other ideal relations not as yet so verified. I refer to those propositions (no longer expressing mere results of comparison) which are formu lated in such metaphysical and aesthetic axioms as " The Principle of things is one ; " " The quantity of existence is unchanged ; " " Nature is simple and invariable ; " " Nature acts by the shortest ways ; " " Ex nihilo nihil fit ; " " Noth ing can be evolved which was not involved ; " " Whatever is in the effect must be in the cause ; " "A thing can only work where it is ; " " A thing can only affect another of its own kind ; " " Cessante causa, cessat et effectus ; " " Nature makes no leaps ; " " Things belong to discrete and perma nent kinds ; " " Nothing is or happens without a reason ; " " The world is throughout rationally intelligible ; " etc., 670 PSYCHOLOGY. etc., etc. Such principles as these, which might be multi plied to satiety,* are properly to be called postulates of rationality, not propositions of fact. If nature did obey them, she would be pro tanto more intelligible ; and we seek meanwhile so to conceive her phenomena as to show that she does obey them. To a certain extent we succeed. For example, instead of the ' quantity of existence ' so vaguely postulated as unchanged, Nature allows us to suppose that curious sum of distances and velocities which for want of a better term we call ' energy.' For the effect being 'con tained in the cause/ nature lets us substitute ' the effect is the cause,' so soon as she lets us conceive both effect and cause as the same molecules, in two successive positions.— But all around these incipient successes (as all around the molecular world, so soon as we add to it as its ' effects ' those illusory ' things ' of common-sense which we had to butcher for its sake), there still spreads a vast field of irrationalized fact whose items simply are together, and from one to another of which we can pass by no ideally ' rational ' way. It is not that these more metaphysical postulates of rationality are absolutely barren — though barren enough they were when used, as the scholastics used them, as immediate propositions of fact.f They have a fertility as * Perhaps the most influential of all these postulates is that the nature of the world must be such that sweeping statements may be made about it. f Consider, e.g., the use of the axioms 'nemo potest supra seipsum,' and ' nemo dat quod non Jiabet,' in this refutation of 'Darwinism,' which I take from the much-used scholastic compendium of Logic and Metaphysics of Liberatore, 3d ed. (Rome, 1880): " Haec hypothesis . . . aperte contra- dicit principiis Metaphysicae, quae docent essentias rerum esse immuta- biles, et effectum non posse superare causam. Et sane, quando, juxta Darwin, species inferior se evolvit in superiorem, unde trahit muiorcm illam nobilitatem? Ex ejus careutia. At nihil dat quod non habet ; et minus gignere nequit plus, aut negatio positionem. Praeterea in transformation e quae fingitur, natura prioris speciei, servatur aut destruitur? Si primum, mutatio erit tantum accidentalis, qualem reapse videmus in diversis stirpi- bus animantium. Sin alterum asseritur, ut reapse fert hypothesis darwin- iana, res tenderet ad seipsam destruendam ; cum contra omnia naturaliter tendant ad sui conservation em. et nonnisi per actionem contrarii agentis corruant." It is merely a question of fact whether these ideally proper relations do or do not obtain between animal and vegetable ancestors and descendants. If they do not, what happens? simply this, that we cannot continue to class animal and vegetal facts under the kinds between which NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 671 ideals, and keep us uneasy and striving always to recast the world of sense until its lines become more congruent with theirs. Take for example the principle that * nothing can happen without a cause.' We have no definite idea of what we mean by cause, or of what causality consists in. But the principle expresses a demand for some deeper sort of inward connection between phenomena than their merely habitual time-sequence seems to us to be. The word ' cause ' is, in short, an altar to an unknown god ; an empty pedes tal still marking the place of a hoped-for statue. Any really inward belonging-together of the sequent terms, if discovered, would be accepted as what the word cause was meant to stand for. So we seek, and seek ; and in the molecular systems we find a sort of inward belonging in the notion of identity of matter with change of collocation. Perhaps by still seeking we may find other sorts of inward belonging, even between the molecules and those * secondary qualities,' etc., which they produce upon our minds. It cannot be too often repeated that the triumphant application of any one of our ideal systems of rational rela tions to the real world justifies our hope that other sys tems may be found also applicable. Metaphysics should take heart from the example of physics, simply confessing that hers is the longer task. Nature may be remodelled, nay, certainly will be remodelled, far beyond the point at present reached. Just how far ? — is a question which only the whole future history of Science and Philosophy can answer.* Our task being Psychology, we cannot even cross the threshold of that larger problem. Besides the mental structure which results in such those ideal relations obtain. Thus, we can no longer call animal breeds by the name of 'species '; cannot call generating a kind of 'giving,' or treat a descendant as an ' effect ' of his ancestor. The ideal scheme of terms and relations can remain, if you like ; but it must remain purely mental, and without application to life, which 'gangs its aiu gait' regardless of ideal schemes. Most of us, however, would prefer to doubt whether such abstract axioms as that ' a thing cannot tend to its own destruction ' express ideal relations of an important sort at all. * Compare A. Riehl: Der Philosophische Kriticismus, Bd. n. Thl. i. Abschn. i. Cap. in. § 6. 672 PSYCHOLOGY. metaphysical principles as those just considered, there is a mental structure which expresses itself in ESTHETIC AND MORAL PRINCIPLES. The aesthetic principles are at bottom such axioms as that a note sounds good with its third and fifth, or that potatoes need salt. We are once for all so made that when certain impressions come before our mind, one of them will seem to call for or repel the others as its companions. To a certain extent the principle of habit will explain these aesthetic connections. When a conjunction is repeatedly experienced, the cohesion of its terms grows grateful, or at least their disruption grows unpleasant. But to explain all aesthetic judgments in this way would be absurd ; for it is notorious how seldom natural experiences come up to our aesthetic demands. Many of the so-called metaphysical principles are at bottom only expressions of aesthetic feel ing. Nature is simple and invariable ; makes no leaps, or makes nothing but leaps ; is rationally intelligible ; neither increases nor diminishes in quantity ; flows from one prin ciple, etc., etc., — what do all such principles express save our sense of how pleasantly our intellect would feel if it had a Nature of that sort to deal with ? The subjectivity of which feeling is of course quite compatible with Nature also turning out objectively to be of that sort, later on. The moral principles which our mental structure en genders are quite as little explicable in toto by habitual experiences having bred inner cohesions. Eightness is not mere usualness, wrongness not mere oddity, however numer ous the facts which might be invoked to prove such identity. Nor are the moral judgments those most invariably and emphatically impressed on us by public opinion. The most characteristically and peculiarly moral judgments that a man is ever called on to make are in unprece dented cases and lonely emergencies, where no popular rhetorical maxims can avail, and the hidden oracle alone can speak ; and it speaks often in favor of conduct quite unusual, and suicidal as far as gaining popular approbation goes. The forces which conspire to this resultant are subtle harmonies and discords between the NECESSARY TRUTHS- EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 673 elementary ideas which form the data of the case. Some of these harmonies, no doubt, have to do with habit ; but in respect to most of them our sensibility must assuredly be a phenomenon of supernumerary order, correlated with a brain-function quite as secondary as that which takes, cognizance of the diverse excellence of elaborate musical compositions. No more than the higher musical sensibili ty can the higher moral sensibility be accounted for by the frequency with which outer relations have cohered.* Take judgments of justice or equity, for example. Instinctively, one judges everything differently, according as it pertains to one's self or to some one else. Empirically one notices that everybody else does the same. But little by little there dawns in one the judgment " nothing can be right for me which would not be right for another similarly placed ;" or " the fulfilment of my desires is intrinsically no more im perative than that of anyone else's ; " or " what it is reason able that another should do for me, it is also reasonable that I should do for him ; " t and forthwith the whole mass of the habitual gets overturned. It gets seriously over turned only in a few fanatical heads. But its overturning is due to a back-door and not to a front-door process. Some minds are preternaturally sensitive to logical con sistency and inconsistency. When they have ranked a thing under a kind, they must treat it as of that kind's kind, or feel all out of tune. In many respects we do class ourselves with other men, and call them and ourselves by a common name. They agree with us in having the same Heavenly Father, in not being consulted about their birth, * As one example out of a thousand of exceptionally delicate idiosyn crasy in this regard, take this: "I must quit society. I would rather un dergo twice the danger from beasts and ten times the danger from rocks. It is not pain, it is not death, that I dread,— it is the hatred of a man; there is something in it so shocking that I would rather submit to any injury than incur or increase the hatred of a man by revenging it Another sufficient reason for suicide is that I was this morning out of temper with Mrs. Douglas (for no fault of hers). I did not betray myself in the least, but I reflected that to be exposed to the possibility of such an event once a year, was evil enough to render life intolerable. The disgrace of using an impatient word is to me overpowering." (Elton Hammond, quoted in Henry Crabb Robinson's Diary, vol. i. p. 424.) f Compare H. Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, bk. in. chap. xm. § 3. 674 PSYCHOLOGY. in not being themselves to thank or blame for their natural gifts, in having the same desires and pains and pleasures, in short in a host of fundamental relations. Hence, if these things be our essence, we should be substitutable for other men, and they for us, in any proposition in which either of us is involved. The more fundamental and common the essence chosen, and the more simple the reasoning,* the more mildly radical and unconditional will the justice be which is aspired to. Life is one long struggle between conclusions based on abstract ways of conceiving cases, and opposite conclusions prompted by our instinctive percep tion of them as individual facts. The logical stickler for justice always seems pedantic and mechanical to the man who goes by tact and the particular instance, and who usually makes a poor show at argument. Some times the abstract conceiver's way is better, sometimes that of the man of instinct. But just as in our study of reason ing we found it impossible to lay down any mark whereby to distinguish right conception cf a concrete case from con- fusion (see pp. 336, 350), so here we can give no general rule for deciding when it is morally useful to treat a con crete case as sui generis, and when to lump it with others in an abstract class.f * A gentleman told me that he had a conclusive argument for opening the Harvard Medical School to women. It was this: "Are not women human ?"— which major premise of course had to be granted. " Then are they not entitled to all the rights of humanity ?" My friend said that he had never met anyone who could successfully meet this reasoning. f You reach the Mephistophelian point of view as well as the point of view of justice by treating cases as if they belonged rigorously to abstract classes. Pure rationalism, complete immunity from prejudice, consists in re fusing to see that the case before one is absolutely unique. It is always possi ble to treat the country of one's nativity, the house of one's fathers, the bed in which one's mother died, nay, the mother herself if need be, on a naked equality with all other specimens of so many respective genera. It shows the world in a clear frosty light from which all fuliginous mists of affec tion, all swamp-lights of sentimentality, are absent. Straight and immedi ate action becomes easy then — witness a Napoleon's or a Frederick's career. But the question always remains, "Are not the mists and vapors worth re taining?" The illogical refusal to treat certain concretes by the mere law of their genus has made the drama of human history. The obstinate insist ing that tweedledum is not tweedledee is the bone and marrow of life Look at 'he Jews and the Scots, with their miserable factions and sec- NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 675 An adequate treatment of the way in which we come by our aesthetic and moral judgments would require a separate chapter, which I cannot conveniently include in this book. Suffice it that these judgments express inner harmonies and discords between objects of thought ; and that whilst outer cohesions frequently repeated will often seem har monious, all harmonies are not thus engendered, but our feeling of many of them is a secondary and incidental func tion of the mind. Where harmonies are asserted of the real world, they are obviously mere postulates of ration ality, so far as they transcend experience. Such postulates are exemplified by the ethical propositions that the indi vidual and universal good are one, and that happiness and goodness are bound to coalesce in the same subject. SUMMABY OF WHAT PRECEDES. I will now sum up our progress so far by a short sum mary of the most important conclusions which we have reached. tarian disputes, their loyalties and patriotisms and exclusions, — their an nals now become a classic heritage, because men of genius took part and sang in them. A thing is important if any one think it important. The process of history consists iu certain folks becoming possessed of the mania that certain special things are important infinitely, whilst other folks can not agree in the belief. The Shah of Persia refused to be taken to the Derby Day, saying " It is already known to me that one horse can run faster than another." He made the question "which horse?" immaterial. Any question can be made immaterial by subsuming all its answers under a common head. Imagine what college ball-games and races would be if the teams were to forget the absolute distinctness of Harvard from Yale and think of both as One in the higher genus College. The sovereign road to indifference, whether to evils or to goods, lies in the thought of the higher genus. "When we have meat before us," says Marcus Aurelius, seeking indifference to that kind of good, "we must receive the impression that tbis is the dead body of a fish, and this is the dead body of a bird or of a pig- and again that this Falernian is only a little grape- juice, and this pur ple robe some sheep's wool dyed with the blood of a shell-fish. Such, then, are these impressions, and they reach the things themselves and penetrate them, and we see what kind of things they are. Just in the same way ought we to act through life, and where there are things which appear most worthy of our approbation, we ought to lay them bare and look at their worthlessness and strip them of all the words by which they are ex alted." (Long's Translation, vi. 13.) 676 PSYCHOLOGY. The mind has a native structure in this sense, that cer tain of its objects, if considered together in certain ways, give definite results ; and that no other ways of consider ing, and no other results, are possible if the same objects be taken. The results are ' relations ' which are all expressed by judgments of subsumption and of comparison. The judgments of subsumption are themselves sub sumed under the laivs of logic. Those of comparison are expressed in classifications, and in the sciences of arithmetic and geometry. Mr. Spencer's opinion that our consciousness of classifi- catory, logical, and mathematical relations between ideas is due to the frequency with which the corresponding ' outer relations ' have impressed our minds, is unintelligible. Our consciousness of these relations, no doubt, has a natural genesis. But it is to be sought rather in the inner » forces which have made the brain grow, thanin any mere i paths of ' frequent ' association which outer stimuli may I have ploughed in that organ. But let our sense for these relations have arisen as it may, the relations themselves form a fixed system of lines of cleavage, so to speak, in the mind, by which we naturally pass from one object to another ; and the objects connected by these lines of cleavage are often not connected by any regular time- and space-associations. We distinguish, therefore, between the empirical order of things, and this their rational order of comparison ; and, so far as possible, we seek to translate the former into the latter, as being the more congenial of the two to our intellect. Any classification of things into kinds (especially if the kinds form series, or if they successively involve each other) is a more rational way of conceiving the things than is that mere juxtaposition or separation of them as indi viduals in time and space which is the order of their crude perception. Any assimilation of things to terms between which such classificatory relations, with their remote and mediate transactions, obtain, is a way of bringing the things into a more rational scheme. Solids in motion are such terms ; and the mechanical NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 677 philosophy is only a way of conceiving nature so as to arrange its items along some of the more natural lines of cleavage of our mental structure. Other natural lines are the moral and aesthetic relations. Philosophy is still seeking to conceive things so that these relations also may seem to obtain between them. As long as things have not successfully been so con ceived, the moral and aesthetic relations obtain only between entia rationis, terms in the mind ; and the moral and aesthetic principles remain but postulates, not propositions, with regard to the real world outside. There is thus a large body of a priori or intuitively necessary truths. As a rule, these are truths of comparison -only, and in the first instance they express relations be tween merely mental terms. Nature, however, acts as if some of her realities were identical with these mental terms. So far as she does this, we can make a priori propo sitions concerning natural fact. The aim of both science and philosophy is to make the identifiable terms more numerous. So far it has proved easier to identify nature's things with mental terms of the mechanical than with men tal terms of the sentimental order. The widest postulate of rationality is that the world is rationally intelligible throughout, after the pattern of some ideal system. The whole war of the philosophies is over that point of faith. Some say they can see their way already to the rationality; others that it is hopeless in any other but the mechanical way. To some the very fact that there is a world at all seems irrational. Nonentity would be a more natural thing than existence, for these minds. One philosopher at least says that the relatedness of things to each other is irrational anyhow, and that a world of rela tions can never be made intelligible.* With this I may be assumed to have completed the programme which I announced at the beginning of the chap ter, so far as the theoretic part of our organic mental struc- * " An sich, in seinem eignen Wesen, ist jedes reale Object mit sich selbst identisch und unbedingt "—that is, the " a llgemeinste Einsicht a priori," and the " allgemeinste aus Erfahrung" is " Alles erkennbare ist bedingt." (A. Spir : Denken und Wirklichkeit. Compare also Herbart and Hegel.) 678 PSYCHOLOGY. ture goes. It can be due neither to our own nor to our an cestors' experience. I now pass to those practical parts of our organic mental structure. Things are a little different here ; and our conclusion, though it lies in the same direc tion, can be by no means as confidently expressed. To be as short and simple as possible, I will take the case of instincts, and, supposing the reader to be familiar with Chapter XXIY, I will plunge in medias res. THE ORIGIN OF INSTINCTS. Instincts must have been either 1) Each specially created in complete form, or 2) Gradually evolved. As the first alternative is nowadays obsolete, I proceed directly to the second. The two most prominent sugges tions as to the way in which instincts may have been evolved are associated with the names of Lamarck and Darwin. Lamarck's statement is that animals have wants, and contract, to satisfy them, habits which transform themselves gradually into so many propensities which they can neither resist nor change. These propensities, once acquired, prop agate themselves by way of transmission to the young, so that they come to exist in new individuals, anteriorly to all exercise. Thus are the same emotions, the same habits, the same instincts, perpetuated without variation from one generation to another, so long as the outward conditions of existence remain the same.* Mr. Lewes calls this the theory of 'lapsed intelligence.' Mr. Spencer's words are clearer than Lamarck's, so that I will quote from him : f * Philosophic Zoologique, 3me partie, chap, v., 'de 1'Instinct.' f It should be said that Mr. Spencer's most formal utterance about in stinct is in his Principles of Psychology, in the chapter under that name. Dr. Romanes has reformulated and criticised the doctrine of this chapter in his Mental Evolution in Animals, chapter xvn. I must confess my in ability to state its vagueness in intelligible terms. It treats instincts as a further development of reflex actions, and as forerunners of intelligence, — which is probably true of many. But when it ascribes their formation to the mere 'multiplication of experiences,' which, at first simple, mould the nervous system to 'correspond to outer relations' by simple reflex actions, and, afterwards complex, make it ' correspond ' by ' compound reflex actions,' it becomes too mysterious to follow without more of a key than is given. The whole thing becomes perfectly simple if we suppose the reflex actions to be accidental inborn idiosyncrasies preserved. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 679 "Setting out with the unquestionable assumption, that every new form of emotion making its appearance in the individual or the race is a modification of some pre-existing emotion, or a compounding of several pre-existing emotions, we should be greatly aided by knowing what always are the pre-existing emotions. When, for example, we find that very fewT, if any, of the lower animals show any love of accu mulation, and that this feeling is absent in infancy ; when we see that an infant in arms exhibits anger, fear, wonder, while yet it manifests no desire of permanent possession ; and that a brute which has no ac quisitive emotion can nevertheless feel attachment, jealousy, love of ap probation, — we may suspect that the feeling which property satisfies is compounded out of simpler and deeper feelings. We may conclude that as when a dog hides a bone there must exist in him a prospective gratification of hunger, so there must similarly, at first, in all cases where anything is secured or taken possession of, exist an ideal excite ment of the feeling which that thing will gratify. WTe may further con clude that when the intelligence is such that a variety of objects come to be utilized for different purposes ; when, as among savages, divers wants are satisfied through the articles appropriated for weapons, shelter, clothing, ornament, — the act of appropriating comes to be one con stantly involving agreeable associations, and one which is therefore pleasurable, irrespective of the end subserved. And when, as in civ ilized life, the property acquired is of a kind not conducing to one order of gratifications, but is capable of ministering to all gratifications, the pleasure of acquiring property grows more distinct from each of the \arious pleasures subserved — is more completely differentiated into a' separate emotion.* It is wrell known that on newly-discovered islands not inhabited by man, birds are so devoid of fear as to allow them selves to be knocked over with sticks, but that in the course of genera- * This account of acquisitiveness differs from our own. Without de nying the associationist account to be a true description of a great deal of our proprietary feeling, we admitted in addition an entirely primitive form of desire. (See above, p. 420 ff .) The reader must decide as to the plausibili ties of the case. Certainly appearances are in favor of there being in us some cupidities quite disconnected with the ulterior uses of the things appro priated. The source of their fascination lies in their appeal to our aesthetic sense, and we wish thereupon simply to own them. Glittering, hard, metallic, odd, pretty things ; curious things especially ; natural objects that look as if they were artificial, or that mimic other objects, — these form a class of things which human beings snatch at as magpies snatch rags. They simply fascinate us. What house does not contain some drawer or cup board full of senseless odds and ends of this sort, \vith which nobody knows what to do, but which a blind instinct saves from the ash-barrel ? Witness people returning from a walk on the sea-shore or in the woods, each carrying some lusus natures in the shape of stone or shell, or strip of bark or odd-shaped fungus, which litter the house and grow daily more unsightly, until at last reason triumphs over blind propensity and sweeps them away. 680 PSYCHOLOGY. tions they acquire such a dread of man as to fly on his approach, and that this dread is manifested by young as well as old. Now unless this change be ascribed to the killing off of the least fearful, and the preser vation and multiplication of the more fearful, which, considering the small number killed by man, is an inadequate cause, it must be ascribed to accumulated experiences, and each experience must be held to have a share in producing it. We must conclude that in each bird that es capes with injuries inflicted by man, or is alarmed by the outcries of •other members of the flock, . . . there is established an association of ideas between the human aspect and the pains, direct and indirect, suf fered from human agency. And we must further conclude that the state of consciousness which impels the bird to take flight is at first nothing more than an ideal reproduction of those painful impressions which before followed man's approach ; that such ideal reproduction becomes more vivid and more massive as the painful experiences, direct or sympathetic, increase ; and that thus the emotion, in its incipient state, is nothing else than an aggregation of the revived pains before experienced. As, in the course of generations, the young birds of this race begin to display a fear of man before they have been injured by him, it is an unavoidable inference that the nervous system of the race has been organically modified by these experiences ; we have no choice but to conclude that when a young bird is thus led to fly, it is because the impression produced on its senses by the approaching man entails, through an incipiently reflex action, a partial excitement of all those nerves which, in its ancestors, had been excited under the like con ditions ; that this partial excitement has its accompanying painful con sciousness ; and that the vague painful consciousness thus arising con stitutes emotion proper— emotion undecomposable into specific experi ences, and therefore seemingly homogeneous. If such be the expla nation of the fact in this case, then it is in all cases. If the emotion is so generated here, then it is so generated throughout. If so, we must perforce conclude that the emotional modifications displayed by dif ferent nations, and those higher emotions by which civilized are dis tinguished from savage, are to be accounted for on the same principle. And, concluding this, we are led strongly to suspect that the emotions in general have severally thus originated." * Obviously the word ' emotion ' here means instinct as well, — the actions we call instinctive are expressions or manifestations of the emotions whose genesis Mr. Spencer describes. Now if habit could thus bear fruit outside the individual life, and if the modifications so painfully ac quired by the parents' nervous systems could be found ready-made at birth in those of the young, it would be hard * Review of Bain in H. Spencer: Illustrations of Universal Progress {New York, 1864), pp. 311, 315. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 681 to overestimate the importance, both practical and theo retical, of such an extension of its sway. In principle, in stincts would then be assimilated to ' secondarily-automatic ' habits, and the origin of many of them out of tentative ex periments made during ancestral lives, perfected by repe tition, addition, and association through successive genera tions, would be a comparatively simple thing to understand. Contemporary students of instinct have accordingly been alert to discover all the facts which would seem to establish the possibility of such an explanation. The list is not very long, considering what a burden of conclusions it has to bear. Let acquisitiveness and fear of man, as just argued for by Spencer, lead it off. Other cases of the latter sort are the increased shyness of the woodcock noticed to have occurred within sixty years' observation by Mr. T. A. Knight, and the greater shyness everywhere shown by large than by small birds, to which Darwin has called attention. Then we may add — The propensities of * pointing,' < retrieving,' etc., in sporting dogs, which seem partly, at any rate, to be due to training, but which in well-bred stock are all but innate. It is in these breeds considered bad for a litter of young if its sire or dam have not been trained in the field. Docility of domestic breeds of horses and cattle. Tameness of young of tame rabbit — young wild rabbits being invincibly timid. Young foxes are most wary in those places where they are most severely hunted. Wild ducks, hatched out by tame ones, fly off. But if kept close for some generations, the young are said to be come tame.* Young savages at a certain age will revert to the woods. English greyhounds taken to the high plateau of Mexico could not at first run well, on account of rarefied air. Their whelps entirely got over the difficulty. Mr. Lewes somewhere t tells of a terrier pup whose parents had been taught to ' beg,' and who constantly * Ribot : De 1'Heredite, 2me ed. p. 26. f Quoted (without reference) in Spencer's Biology, vol. i. p. 247. 682 PSYCHOLOGY. threw himself spontaneously into the begging attitude. Darwin tells of a French orphan- child, brought up out of France, yet shrugging like his ancestors.* Musical ability often increases from generation to gen eration in the families of musicians. The hereditarily epileptic guinea-pigs of Brown-Se- quard, whose parents had become epileptic through surgical operations on the spinal cord or sciatic nerve. The adults often lose some of their hind toes, and the young, in addi tion to being epileptic, are frequently born with the corre sponding toes lacking. The offspring of guinea-pigs whose cervical sympathetic nerve has been cut on one side will have the ear larger, the eyeball smaller, etc., just like their parents after the operation. Puncture of the ' restif orm body ' of the medulla will, in the same animal, congest and enlarge one eye, and cause gangrene of one ear. In the young of such parents the same symptoms occur. Physical refinement, delicate hands and feet, etc., ap pear in families well-bred and rich for several generations. The * nervous ' temperament also develops in the de scendants of sedentary brain-working people. Inebriates produce offspring in various ways degener ate. Nearsightedness is produced by indoor occupation for generations. It has been found in Europe much more fre quent among schoolchildren in towns than among children of the same age in the country. These latter cases are of the inheritance of structural rather than of functional peculiarities. But as structure gives rise to function it may be said that the principle is the same. Amongst other inheritances of adaptivef struc tural change may be mentioned : The * Yankee ' type. Scrofula, rickets, and other diseases of bad conditions of life. * Expression of Emotions (N. Y.), p. 287. f ' Adaptive ' changes are those produced by the direct effect of out ward conditions on an organ or organism. Sunburned complexion, horny hands, muscular toughness, are illustrations. NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 683 The udders and permanent milk of the domestic breeds of cow. The 'fancy' rabbit's ears, drooping through lack of need to erect them. Dog's, ass's, etc., in some breeds ditto. The obsolete eyes of mole and various cave-dwelling animals. The diminished size of the wing-bones of domesticated ducks, due to ancestral disuse of flight.* These are about all the facts which, by one author or another, have been invoked as evidence in favor of the ' lapsed intelligence ' theory of the origin of instincts. Mr. Darwin's theory is that of the natural selection of accidentally produced tendencies to action. "It would," says he, " be the most serious error to suppose that the greater number of instincts have been acquired by habit in one genera tion, and then transmitted by inheritance in succeeding generations. It can clearly be shown that the most wonderful instincts with which we are acquainted, namely, those of the hive-bee and of many ants, could not possibly have been thus acquired, f It will be universally ad mitted that instincts are as important as corporeal structure for the wel fare of each species, under its present conditions of life. Under changed conditions of life, it is at least possible that slight modifications of in stinct might be profitable to a species ; and if it can be shown that in stincts do vary ever so little, then I can see no difficulty in natural selection preserving and continually accumulating variations of instinct to any extent that may be profitable. It is thus, as I believe, that all the most complex and wonderful instincts have arisen. ... I believe that the effects of habit are of quite subordinate importance to the effects of the natural selection of what may be called accidental variations of instincts ;— that is, of variations produced by the same unknown causes which produce slight deviations of bodily structure." \ * For these and other facts cf. Th. Ribot : De l'Heredit6 ; W B Car penter : Contemporary Review, vol. 21, p. 295, 779, 867; H Spencer- Princ. of Biol. pt. n. ch. v, vm, ix, x ; pt. m. ch. xi, xii ; C. Darwin' Animals and Plants under Domestication, ch. xii, xm, xiv ; Sam'l But ler : Life and Habit; T. A. Knight: Philos. Trans. 1887; B Dupuy Popular Science Monthly, vol. xi. p. 332 ; F. Papfflon : Nature and Life' p. 330 ; Crothers, in Pop. Sci. M., Jan. (or Feb.) 1889. f [Because, being exhibited by neuter insects, the effects of mere prac- tice cannot accumulate from one generation to another.— W. J.l \ Origin of Species, chap. vn. 684 PSYCHOLOGY. The evidence for Mr. Darwin's view is too complex to be given in this place. To my own mind it is quite con vine- ing. If, with the Darwinian theory in mind, one re-reads the list of examples given in favor of the Lamarckian theory, one finds that many of the cases are irrelevant, and that some make for one side as well as for the other. This is so obvious in many of the cases that it is needless to point it out in detail. The shrugging child and the begging pup, e.g., prove somewhat too much. They are examples so unique as to suggest spontaneous variation rather than in herited habit. In other cases the observations much need corroboration, e.g., the effects of not training for a generation in sporting dogs and race-horses, the difference between young wild rabbits born in captivity and young tame ones, the cumulative effect of many generations of captivity on wild ducks, etc. Similarly, the increased wariness of the large birds, of those on islands frequented by men, of the woodcock, of the foxes, may be due to the fact that the bolder families have been killed off, and left none but the naturally timid behind, or simply to the individual experience of older birds being imparted by example to the young so that a new educational tradition has occurred. — The cases of phy sical refinement, nervous temperament, Yankee type, etc., also need much more discriminating treatment than they have yet received from the Lamarckians. There is no real evidence that physical refinement and nervosity tend to ac cumulate from generation to generation in aristocratic or intellectual families ; nor is there any that the change in that direction which Europeans transplanted to America undergo is not all completed in the first generation of children bred on our soil. To my mind, the facts all point that way. Similarly the better breathing of the grey hounds born in Mexico was surely due to a post-natal adaptation of the pups' thorax to the rarer ail. Distinct neurotic degeneration may undoubtedly accumu late from parent to child, and as the parent usually in this case grows worse by his own irregular habits of life, the temptation lies near to ascribe the child's deterioration to this cause. This, again, is a hasty conclusion. For neurotic NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 685 degeneration is unquestionably a disease whose original causes are unknown ; and like other ' accidental variations ' it is hereditary. But it ultimately ends in sterility ; and it seems to me quite unfair to draw any conclusions from its natural history in favor of the transmission of acquired peculiarities. Nor does the degeneration of the children of alcoholics prove anything in favor of their having inherited the shattered nervous system which the alcohol has induced in their parents : because the poison usually has a chance to directly affect their own bodies before birth, by acting on the germinal matter from which they are formed whilst it is still nourished by the alcoholized blood of the parent. In many cases, moreover, the parental alcoholics are them selves degenerates neurotically, and the drink-habit is only a symptom of their disease, which in some form or other they also propagate to their children. There remain the inherited mutilations of the guinea- pig. But these are such startling exceptions to the ordinary rule with animals that they should hardly be used as ex amples of a typical process. The docility of domestic cattle is certainly in part due to man's selection, etc., etc. In a word, the proofs form rather a beggarly array. Add to this that the writers who have tried to carry out the theory of transmitted habit with any detail are always obliged somewhere to admit inexplicable variation. Thus Spencer allows that " Sociality can begin only where, through some slight variation, there is less tendency than usual for the individuals to disperse. . . . That slight variations of mental nature, sufficient to initiate this process, may be fairly assumed, all our domestic animals show us: differences in their characters and likings are conspicuous. Sociality having thus commenced, and survival of the fittest tending ever to maintain and increase it, it will be further strengthened by the inherited effects of habit.' * Again, in writing of the pleasure of pity, Mr. Spencer says : " This feeling is not one that has arisen through the inherited effects of experiences, but belongs to a quite different group, traceable to the survival of the fittest simply— to the natural selection of incidental variations. In this group are included all the bodily appetites, together with those simpler in stincts, sexual and parental, by which every race is maintained ; and which must exist before the higher processes of mental evolution can commence." t *Princ. of Psychol., n. 561. f Ibid. p. 623. 686 PSYCHOLOGY. The inheritance of tricks of manner and trifling peculi arities, such as handwriting, certain odd gestures when pleased, peculiar movements during sleep, etc., have also been quoted in favor of the theory of transmission of ac quired habits. Strangely enough ; for of all things in the world these tricks seem most like idiosyncratic variations. They are usually defects or oddities which the education of the individual, the pressure of what is really acquired by him, would counteract, but which are too native to be repressed, and breaks through all artificial barriers, in his children as well as in himself. I leave my text practically just as it was written in 1885. I proceeded at that time to draw a tentative conclusion to the effect that the origin of most of our instincts must cer tainly be deemed fruits of the back-door method of genesis, and not of ancestral experience in the proper meaning of the term. Whether acquired ancestral habits played any part at all in their production was still an open question in which it would be as rash to affirm as to deny. Already before that time, however, Professor Weismann of Freiburg had begun a very serious attack upon the Lamarckian theory,* and his polemic has at last excited such a widespread interest among naturalists that the whilom almost unhes itatingly accepted theory seems almost on the point of being abandoned. I will therefore add some of Weismann's criticisms of the supposed evidence to my own. In the first place, he has a captivating theory of descent of his own,f which makes him think it a priori impossible that any peculiarity acquired during lifetime by the parent should be transmitted to the germ. Into the nature of that theory this is not the place to go. Suffice to say that it has made him a keener critic of Lamarck's and Spencer's theory than he otherwise might have been. The only way in which the germinal products can be influenced whilst in the body of the parent is, accord- * Ueber die Vererbung (Jena, 1883). Prof. Weismanu's Essays on Heredity have recently (1889) been published in English in a collected form. f Best expressed in the Essay on the Continuitat des Keimplasmas (1885) NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 687 ing to Weismann, by good or bad nutrition. Through this they may degenerate in various ways or lose vitality alto gether. They may also be infected through the blood by small-pox, syphilis, or other virulent diseases, and other wise be poisoned. But peculiarities of neural structure and habit in the parents ivhich the parents themselves ivere not born with, they can never acquire unless perhaps accident ally through some coincidental variation of their own. Accidental variations develop of course into idiosyncrasies which tend to pass to later generations in virtue of the well-known law which no one doubts. Keferriug to the often-heard assertion that the increase of talent found in certain families from one generation to another is due to the transmitted effects of exercise of the faculty concerned (the Bachs, the Bernoullis, Mozart, etc.), he sensibly remarks, that the talent being kept in exercise, it ought to have gone on growing for an indefinite number of generations. As a matter of fact, it quickly reaches a maximum, and then we hear no more of it, which is what happens always when an idiosyncrasy is exposed to the ef fects of miscellaneous intermarriage. The hereditary epilepsy and other degenerations of the operated guinea-pigs are explained by Professor Weis mann as results of infection of the young by the parent's blood. The latter he supposes to undergo a pathologic change in consequence of the original traumatic injury. The obsolescence of disused organs he explains very satisfactor ily, without invoking any transmission of the direct effects of disuse, by his theory of panmixy, for which I must refer to his own writings. Finally, he criticises searchingly the stories we occasionally hear of inherited mutilations in animals (dogs' ears and tails, etc.), and cites a prolonged series of experiments of his own on mice, which he bred for many generations, cutting off both parental tails each time, without interfering in the least with the length of tail with which the young continued to be born. The strongest argument, after all, in favor of the La- marckian theory remains the a priori one urged by Spencer in his little work (much the solidest thing, by the way, which he has ever written) ' The Factors of Organic Evolution.' 688 PSYCHOLOGY. Since, says Mr. Spencer, the accidental variations of all parts of the body are independent of each other, if the entire organization of animals were due to such accidental variations alone, the amount of mutual adaptation and har mony that we now find there could hardly possibly have come about in any finite time. We must rather suppose that the divers varying parts brought the other parts into har mony with themselves by exercising them ad hoc, and that the effects of the exercise remained and were passed on to the young. This forms, of course, a great presumption against the all-sufficiency of the view of selection of accidental variations exclusively. But it must be admitted that in favor of the contrary view, that adaptive changes are in herited, we have as yet perhaps not one single unequivocal item of positive proof. I must therefore end this chapter on the genesis of our mental structure by reaffirming my conviction that the so- called Experience-philosophy has failed to prove its point. No more if we take ancestral experiences into account than if we limit ourselves to those of the individual after birth, can we believe that the couplings of terms within the mind are simple copies of corresponding couplings impressed upon it by the environment. This indeed is true of a small part of our cognitions. But so far as logical and mathe matical, ethical, sesthetical, and metaphysical propositions go, such an assertion is not only untrue but altogether unintelligible; for these propositions say nothing about the time- and space-order of things, and it is hard to un derstand how such shallow and vague accounts of them as Mill's and Spencer's could ever have been given by think ing men. The causes of our mental structure are doubtless natural, and connected, like all our other peculiarities, with those of our nervous structure. Our interests, our tendencies of at tention, our motor impulses, the aesthetic, moral, and theoretic combinations we delight in, the extent of our power of apprehending schemes of i elation, just like the elementary relations themselves, time, space, difference and similarity, and the elementary kinds of feeling, have all NECESSARY TRUTHS— EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE. 689 grown up in ways of which at present we can give no ac count. Even in the clearest parts of Psychology our insight is insignificant enough. And the more sincerely one seeks to trace the actual course of psychogenesis, the steps by which as a race we may have come by the peculiar mental attributes which we possess, the more clearly one per ceives " the slowly gathering twilight close in utter night." TEE END. ! INDEX. Authors the titles only of whose works are cited are not, as a rule, referred to in this index. ABBOTT, T. K., II. 221 Abstract ideas, I. 468, 508; II. 48 Abstract qualities, II. 329-37, 340 Abstraction, I. 505; II. 346 ff. See distraction Accommodation, feeling of, II. 93, 235 Acquaintance, I. 220 Acquired characters, see inheritance Acquisitiveness, II. 422, 679 Actors, their emotions whilst play ing, II. 464 Adaptation of mind to environment results in our knowing the im pressing circumstances, 625 ff. ^Esthetic principles, II. 639, 672 After-images, I. 645-7; II. 67, 200, 604 Agoraphobia, II. 421 Agraphia, I. 40, 62 ALFIERI, II. 543 ALLEN, G., I. 144; II. 631 Alteration of one impression by another one simultaneously tak ing place, II. 28 ff., 201 Alternating personality, I. 379 ff. Ambiguity of optical sensations, II. 231-7 AMIDON, I. 100 Amnesia in hysterical disease, 1. 384 ff. ; accompanies anaesthesia, 386, 682; in hypnotic trance, II. 602. See forgetting Amputated limbs, feeling of, II. j 38-9, 105 Anaesthesia, in hysterics, I. 203 ff.; involves correlated amnesia, 386; movements executed during, II. 105,489-92, 520-1: and emotion, 455-6; in hypnotism, 606-9 Analogies, the perception of, I. 530 Analysis, I. 502; II. 344 Anger, II. 409, 460, 478 Aphasia, motor, I. 37, 62; sensory, I. 53-4-5; optical, I. 60; amnesia in, 640, 684; II. 58 Apperception, II. 107 ff. Apperception, transcendental Unity of, I. 362 Appropriateness, characterizes men tal acts, I. 13 Apraxia, I. 52 A priori connections exist only be tween objects of perception and "movements, not between sensory ideas, II. 581. A priori ideas and experience, Chapter XXVIII. A •priori propositions, II. 661-5 ARCHER, W., II. 464 Arithmetic, II. 654. Articular sensibility, II. 189 ff. Association, Chapter XIV: is not of ideas, but of things thought of, I. 554; examples of, 555 ff. ; its rapidity, 557 ff.; by contiguity, 561; elementary law of,566;'mixed' association, 571; conditions of, 575 ff.; by similarity, 578; three kinds of association compared, 580; in voluntary thought, 583; by contrast, 593; history of the doc trine of, 594; association the means of localization, II. 158 ff. ; connec tion .of association by similarity with reasoning, 345 ff. Associationism, I. 161 Associationist theory of the self, I. 342, 350 ff.; of space-perception, II. 271 ff. Asymbolia, I. 52 Attention, Chapter XI — to how many things possible, I. 405 ff.; to simultaneous sight and sound, 411 ff.; its varieties, 416; pas sive, 417; voluntary, 42 ff.; its effects, 424 ff . ; its influence on re- 691 692 INDEX. action-time, 427-34; accompa nied by feelings of tension due to adaptation of sense-organs, 434-8; involves imagination or preper- ception of object, 438-44; con ceivable as a mere effect, 448 ff . AUBERT, H., II. 235 ' Ausfallserscheinungen,' I. 75 Auditory centre in brain, I. 52-6 Auditory type of imagination, II. 60 Automatic writing, I. 393 ff. AUSTEN, JANE, I. 571 Automaton-Theory, Chapter V: postulated rather than proved, I. 134-8; reasons against it, 138-144; applied to attention, 448 disregarded in this book, II. 583 AZAM, Dr., I. 380. Babe and caudle, scheme of, I. 25 Baby's first perception, II. 8, 34; his early instinctive movements, 404 ff. BAER, VON, I. 639 BAGEHOT, W., I. 582; II, 283, 308 BAIN, on series conscious of itself, I. 162; on self-esteem, 313; on self-love, 328, 354; on attention, 444; on association, 485. 530, 561, 589, 601, 653; II. 6, 12, 69, 186, 271, 282, 296, 319, 322, 372-3, 463, 466, 551, 554-5 BALLARD, I. 266 BALZAC, I. 374 B ARTELS, I. 432 BASTIAN, H. C.. II. 488 BAUMANN, II. 409 BAXT, I. 648 BEAUNIS, E., II. 492 BECHTEREW, I. 407 Belief, Chapter XXI: in sensations, II. 299 ff.; in objects of emotion, 306 ff.; in theories, 311 ff.; and will, 319. See BELL, C., II. 483, 492 BERGSON, J., II. 609 BERKELEY, I. 254, 469, 476; II. 43, 49, 77, 212, 240, 666 BERNHARDT, II. 502 BERNHEIM. I. 206 BERTRAND, A., II. 518 BESSEL, I. 413 BINET, A., I. 203 ff.; II. 71, 74, 128 ff., 130, 167, 491, 520 BLACK, R. W., II. 339 BLEEK, II. 358 Blind, the, their space-perception, II. 202 ff.; after restoration to sight, 211-2; hallucination of a blind man, 323; dreams of the, 44 Blindness, mental, I. 41, 50, 66. See ISigJit, Hemiopia, etc. BLIX, II. 170 BLOCK, II. 515 Blood, its exciting effect on the nerves, II. 412-3 BLOOD, B. P., II. 284 Blood-supply to brain, I. 97 BOURNE, A., I. 391 BOURRU, Dr.. I. 388 BOWDITCH, H. P., his reaction- timer, I. 87; on contrast in seen motion, II. 247; on knee-jerk, 380; comparison of touch and sight, 520 BOWEN, F., 214 BOWNE, B. P., on knowledge, I. 219 BRADLEY, F. H., I. 452, 474, 604; II. 7, 9, 284, 648 Brain, its functions, Chapter II: of frog, I. 14; of dog, 33; of monkey, 34; of man, 36; lower centres compared with hemispheres, 9-10, 75; circulation in, 97; instability, 139; its connection with Mind, 176; 'entire' brain not a real physical fact, 176; its changes as subtle as those of thought, 234; its dying vibrations operative in producing consciousness, 242 Influence of environment upon it, 626 ff. Brain-process, see neural process Brain-structure, the two modes of its genesis, II. 624 BRENTANO, I. 187, 547 BRIDGEMAN, LAURA, II. 62, 358, 420 Broca's convolution, I. 39, 54 BRODHUN, I. 542 BROWN, THOS., I. 248, 277, 371; II. 271 BROWN-SEQUARD, I. 43, 67, 69; II 695 Brutes, the intellect of, II. 348 ff. BUCKE, R. M., II. 460 BUBNOPF. I. 82 BURKE, II. 464. BURNHAM, W. H., I. 689 BUROT, Dr., I. 388 CAIRD, E., I. 366, 469, 471 IL ff. CALMEIL, A., II. 524 CAMPANELLA, II. 464 CAMPBELL, G., I. 261 CARDAILLAC, I. 247 CARLYLE, T., I. 311 INDEX. 693 CARPENTER, W. B., on formation of habits, I. 110; ethical remarks on habit, 120 : mistakes in speech, 257 ; lapses of memory, 374; on not feeling pain, 419; on ideo- motor action, II. 522 CARVILLE, I. 69 Catalepsy, I. 229; II. 583 CATTELL, on reaction-time, I. 92, 432; 524; on recognition, 407, 648; on attention, 420; on asso ciation-time, 558 ff. Cause, consciousness a, I. 137 ; II. 583, 592 Centres, cortical, I. 30 ff.; motor, 31; visual, 41 ; auditory, 52; olfac tory, 57; gustatory, 58; tactile, 58 Cerebral process, see neural pro cess Cerebrum, see Brain, Hemispheres CHADBOURNE, PA., II. 383 Characters, general, II. 329 ff. CHARCOT, I. 54-5; II. 58, 596 Chloroform, I. 531 Choice, see selection, interest Circulation in brain, I. 97; effects of sensory stimuli upon, II. 374 ff. ; in grief, 443-4 Classic and romantic, II. 469 Classifications, II. 646 CLAY, E. C. R., I. 609 Cleanliness, II. 434 Clearness, I. 426 CLIFFORD, I. 130-2 CLOUSTON, II. 114, 284-5, 537, 539 COBBE, F. P., I. 374 Cochlea, theory of its action, II. 169 Cognition, see knowing COHEN, H., I. 365 COLERIDGE, S. T., I. 572, 681 Collateral innervation, see vicarious function Comparison, Chapter XIII: rela tions discovered by comparison have nothing to do with the time and space order of their terms, II. 641; mediate, 489, 644; see difference, likeness Composition, of Mind out of its elements, see Mind-Stuff theory; differences due to, I. 491 COMTE, A., I. 187 Conceivability, I. 463 Conceptions, Chapter XII: defined, . 461;— their permanence, 464 ff.; do not develop of them selves, 466 ff.; abstract, 468; uni versal, 473; essentially teleologi- cal, II. 332 Conceptual order different from perceptual, I. 482 Concomitants, law of varying, I 506 Confusion, II. 352 Consciousness, its seat, I. 65; its distribution, 142-3; its function of selection, 139-41; is personal in form, 225; is continuous, 237, 488; of lack. 251; of self not essential, 273; of object comes first, 274; always partial and se lective, 284 ff., see Selection; of the process of thinking, 300 ff • the span of, 405 Consent, in willing, II. 568 Considerations, I. 20 Constructiveness, II. 426 Contiguity, association by, I. 561 Continuity of object of conscious ness, I. 488 Contrast, of colors, II. 13-27; of temperatures, 14; two theories of, 17 ff., 245; of movements, 245 ff., 250 Convolutions, motor, I. 41 Cortex, of brain, experiments on, I. 31 ff. Cramming, I. 663 Credulity, our primitive, II. 319 CUDWORTH, R., II. 9 ' Cue, 'the mental, II. 497, 518 CUMBERLAND, S., II. 525 Curiosity, II. 429 CZERMAK, II. 170, 175 - Darwinism, scholastic refutation of, II. 670 Data, the, of psychology, I. 184 DAVIDSON, T., I. 474 * Deaf-mute's thought in infancv I 266 Deafness, mental, I. 50, 55-6. See hearing DEAN, S., I. 394 Decision, five types of, II. 531 Degenerations, descending in nerve- centres, I. 37, 52 DELABARRE, E., II. 13-27, 71 DELBCEUF, J., 1. 455, 531 541 542, 548-9; II. 100, 189* 249* 264, 605. 609, 612 Deliberation, II. 528 ff. Delusions, insane, I. 375; II. 114 ff. Depth, see third dimension DESCARTES, I. 130, 200, 214, 344 DESTTJTT DE TRACY, I 247 Determinism must be postulated by psychology, II. 576 INDEX. DEWEY, J., I 473 Dichotomy in thinking, II. 654 DICKENS, C., I. 374 DIETZE, I. 407, 617 Difference, not resolvable into com position, I. 490 ; noticed most between species of a genus, 529 ; the magnitude of, 531; least dis cernible, !>37 if.; methods for ascertaining. 540 ff. local, II. 167 ff.; genesis of our perception of, 642 Diffusion of movements, the law of, II. 372 Dimension, third, II. 134 ff., 212 ff., 220 Dipsomania, II. 543 Disbelief, II. 284 Discrimination, Chapter XIII; conditions which favor it, I. 494; improves by practice, 508; spatial, II. 167 ff. See difference Dissociation, I. 486-7; law of, by varying concomitants, 506 , ditto, II. 345, 359 of one part of the mind from another, see Janet, Pierre Distance, between terms of a series, I. 530 in space, see third dimension^ Distraction, I. 404. See inattention Dizziness, see vertigo Dog's cortical centres, after Ferrier, I. 33; after Munk, I. 44-5; after Luciani, I. 46, 53, 58, 60; for special muscles, 64; hemispheres ablated, 70 DONALDSON, II. 170 DONDERS, II. 235 Double images, II. 225-30; 252 Doubt, II. 284, 318 ff.; the mania of, 545 DOUGAL, J. D., II. 222 Drainage of one brain-cell by an other, II. 583 ff . Dreams, II. 294 DROBISCH, I. 632. 660 Drunkard, II. 565 Drunkenness, I. 144; II. 543, 565, 628 Dualism of object and knower, I. 218, 220 Duality, of Brain, I. 390, 399 DUDLEY, A. T., on mental qualities of a^i athlete, II. 539 DUPOUR, II. 211 DUNAN, Ch., II. 176, 206, 208-9 Duration, the primitive object in time-perception, I. 609; our esti mate of short, 611 ff. 'Dynamogeny,' II. 379 ff., 491 EBBINGHAUS, H., I. 548, 676 Eccentric projection of sensations, II. 31 ff., 195 ff. Education of hemispheres, I. 76 See pedagogic remarks Effort, II. 534-7. Muscular effort, 562. Moral effort, 549, 561, 578-9 EGGER, V., I. 280-1-2; II. 256 Ego, Empirical, I. 291 ff. ; pure, 342 ff.; 'transcendental,' 362; criti cised, 364 Elementary factors of mind, see Units of consciousness ELSAS, 1. 548 EMERSON, R. W., I. 582, II. 307 Emotion, Chapter XXV: continuous with instinct, II. 442; description of typical emotions, 443-9; results from reflex effects of stimulus upon organism, 449 ff.; their class ification, 454; in anaesthetic sub jects, 455; in the absence of nor mal stimulus, 458-60; effects of expressing, 463 ff . ; of repressing, 466; the subtler, 469 ff.; the neu ral process in, 472; differences in individuals, 474; evolution of special emotions, 477 ff. Empirical ego, I. 290 Empirical propositions, II. 644 Emulation, II. 409 Ennui, I. 626 Entoptic sensations, I. 515 ff. Equation, personal, I. 413 ' Equilibration,' direct and indirect, 627 Essences, their meaning, II. 329 ff. ; sentimental and mechanical, 665 Essential qualities, see essences ESTEL, I. 613, 618 Evolutionism demands a ' mind- dust,' 146 EXNER, on human cortical centres I. 36; on ' circumvallation ' of centres, 65; his psychodometer, 87; on reaction-time, 91; on per- ception of rapid succession, 409; on attention, 439; on time-percep tion, 615, 638, 646; on feeling of motion, II. 172 Experience, I. 402, 487. Relation of experience to necessary judg ments. Chapter XXVIII. Experi- ence defined, II. 619 ff., 628 Experimentation in psychology, I. 192 Extradition of sensations, II. 31 ff., J95 ff INDEX. Fallacy, the Psychologist's, I. 196, 278, 153; II. 281 Familiarity, sense of, see recognition Fatalism, II. 574 Fatigue, diminishes span of con sciousness, I. 640 Fear, instinct of, II. 396, 415; the symptoms of, 446; morbid, 460; origin of, 478 FECUNER, I. 435-6, 533, 539 ff., 549, 616, 645; II. 50, 70, 137 ff., 178, 464 Feeling, synonym for consciousness in general in this book, I. 186; feelings of relation, 243 FELIDA X. , I. 380-4 FERE, CH., II. 68, 378 ff. FERRIER, D., I. 31, 46-7-8, 53, 57- 8-9, 445; II. 503 FERRIER, JAS., I. 274, 475 Fiat, of the will, II. 501, 526, 561, 564; 568. See decision FICHTE, I. 365 FICK, I. 150 FISKE, J., II. 577 Fixed ideas. See insistent ideas FLECHSIG'S Pyrarnidenbahn, I. 37 FLINT, R., II. 425 FLOURENS, P., I. 30 Force, supposed sense of, II. 518 Forgetting, I. 679 ff. ; II. 370-1. See amnesia FOUILLEE, A., II. 500, 570 FRANCOIS- FRANCE, I. 70 FRANKLIN, Mrs. C. L., II. 94 FRANZ, Dr., II. 62 Freedom, of the will, II. 569 ff. 1 Fringe ' of object, I. 258, 281-2, 471-2, 478 Frog's nerve-centres, I. 14 Fusion of feelings unintelligible, I. 157-62; II. 2. See Mind-stuff theory Fusion of impressions into one ob ject, I. 484, 502; II. 103, 183 GALTON, F., I. 254, 265, 685; on mental imagery, II. 51-7; on gre- gariousness, 430 General propositions, what they in volve, II. 337 ff. See universal conceptions Genesis of brain-structure, its two modes, II. 624 Genius, I. 423, 530; II. 110, 352, 360 Gentleman, the mind of the, II. 370 Geometry, II. 658 Giddiness, see vertigo GILMAN, B. I., I. 95 GLEY, E., II. 514-5, 525 GOLDSCHEIDER, II. 170, 192 ff. 200 GOLTZ, I. 9, 31, 33, 34, 45, 46, 58, 62, 67, 69, 70, 74, 77 Gorilla, II. 416 GRAEFE, A., II. 507, 510 GRASHEY, I. 640 GRASSMAN, R., II. 654 Gregariousuess, II. 430 GREEN, T, H., I. 247, 274, 366-8; II. 4, 10, 11 Grief, II. 443, 480 GRIESINGER, W., II. 298 GRUBELSUCHT, II. 284 Guiiiea-pigs, epileptic, etc., II. 682-7 GUISLAIN, II. 546 GURNEY, E., I. 209; II. 117, 130, 469, GUYAU, II. 414, 469 Habit, Chapter IV: due to plasticity of brain-matter, 1. 105; depends on paths in nerve-centres, 107; origi nation of, 109-13; mechanism of concatenated habits, 114-8; they demand some sensation, 118; ethi cal and pedagogic maxims, 121-7; is the ground of association, 566; of memory, 655 Habits may inhibit instincts, II. 394. Habit accounts for one large part of our knowledge, 632 HALL, G. S., I. 96-7, 558, 614, 616: II. 155, 247, 281, 423 Hallucination, sensation a veridical, II. 33; of lost limbs, 38, 105; of emotional feeling, 459 Hallucinations, II. 114 ff. ; hypna- gogic, 124; the brain-process in, 122 ff.; hypnotic, 604 HAMILTON, W., I. 214, 215, 274, 406, 419, 569, 578, 682; II. 113 HAMMOND, E , II. 673 Haploscopic method, II. 226 HARLESS, II. 497 HARTLEY, I. 553, 561, 564, 600 HARTMANN, R., II. 416 Hasheesh-delirium, II. 121 Hearing, its cortical centre, I. 52 Heat, of mental work, I. 100 HECKER. II. 480 HEGEL, I. 163, 265, 366, 369, 666 HEIDENHAIN, I. 82 HELMHOLTZ, H., I. 285; on atten tion, 422, 437, 441; on discrimi nation, 504, 516-21; time as a category, 627-8; after- images, 645, 648; on color-contrast, II. 17 ff.; on sensation, 33; on cochlea, 170; on convergence of eyes, 200; vision INDEX. with inverted head, 213; on what marks a sensation, 218 11'., 243-4; on eutoptic objects, 241-2; on contrast in seen movement, 247; on relief, 257; on measurement of the field of view, 266 fi. ; on theo ry of space-perception, 279; on feeling of innervation, 493, 507, 510 ; on conservation of energy, 667 Heiniamblyopia, I. 44 Hemianopsia, I. 41, 44; II. 73 Hemispheres, their distinction from lower centres, I. 20; their educa tion, 24, 67; localization of func tion in, 30; the exclusive seat of consciousness, 65; effects of de privation of, on frogs, 17, 72-3; on fishes, 73; on birds, 74, 77; on rodents, 74; on dogs, 70, 74; on primates, 75; not devoid of con nate paths, 76; their evolution from lower centres, 79 HENLE, J., II. 445, 461, 481 HERBART, I. 353, 418, 603, 608, 626 Hereditary transmission of acquired characters, see inheritance HERING, E., on attention, I. 438, 449; on comparing weights, 544; on pure sensation, II. 4 ; on color-contrast, 20 ff . ; on roomy character of sensations, 136 ff. ; on after-images and convergence, 200; on distance of double images, 230; on stereoscopy, 252; on reproduc tion in vision, 260 ff.; on move ments of closed eye, 510 HERZEN, I. 58; on reaction-time from a corn, 96; on cerebral ther- mometry, 100; on swooning, 273 HlTZIG, I, 31 HOBBES, T., I. 573, 587, 594 ff. HODGSON, R., I. 374, 398 HODGSON, S. H., on inertness of consciousness, I. 129-30, 133; on self, 341, 347; on conceptual order, 482; on association, 572 ff., 603; on voluntary redintegration, 588-9; on the ' present ' in time, 607 HOFFDING, H., I. 674; II. 455 HOLBROOK, M. H., I. 665 HOLMES, O. W., I. 88, 405, 582 HOLTEI, VON, I. 624 Horopter, II. 226 HORSLEY, V., I. 35, 59, 63 HORWICZ, I. 314, 325-7 HOWE, S. G., II. 358 Human intellect, compared with that of brute, II. 348 ff.; depends on association by similarity, 353 ff.; various orders of, 360; what brain-peculiarity it depends on, 366, 638 HUME, I. 254; on personal identity, 351-3, 360; association, 597; due to brain -laws, 564; on mental im ages, II. 45-6; on belief, 295-6, 302; on pleasure and will, 558 Hunting instinct, II. 411 HUXLEY, I. 130-1, 254; II. 46 HYATT, A., II. 102 Hylozoism, see Mind-stuff theory Hypera3Sthesia,iu hypnotism,!!. 609 Hypnotism, I. 407; H. 128, 351; gen eral account of, Chapter XXVII: methods, II. 593; theories of, 596; symptoms of trance, 602 ff. ; post- hypnotic suggestion, 613 Hysterics, their so-called ansesthe- sias, and unconsciousness, 1.202 ff. Ideal objects, eternal and necessary relations between, II. 639, 661. See conception 'Ideas, 'the theory of, I. 230; con founded with objects, 231, 276, 278, 399, 521; they do not exist as parts of our thought, 279, 405, 553; platonic, 462; abstract, 468 ff.; universal, 473 ff.; never come twice the same; 480-1 Ideation, no distinct centres for, I. 764; II. 73 Identity, sense of, I. 459; three prin ciples of, 460; not the foundation of likeness, 492 Identity, personal, I. 238, 330 ff.; based on ordinary judgment of sameness,334; due to resemblance and continuity of our feelings, 336; Lotzeon, 350; only relatively true, 372 Ideo-motor action the type of all volition, II. 522 Idiosyncrasy, II. 631 'Idomenians,' II. 214 Illusions, II. 85 ff., 129, 232 ff., 243- 66. See hallucination Images, double, in vision, II, 225-30 Images, mental, not lost in mental blindness, etc., I. 50, 66; II. 73 , are usually vague, II. 45; vis ual, 51 ff.; auditory, 160; motor, 61; tactile, 165; between sleep and waking, 124-6 Imagination, Chapter XVIII: it differs in individuals, II. 51 ff. ; sometimes leaves an after-image, 67; the cerebral process of, 68 ff.; not locally distinct from that of sensation, 73; is figured, 82 INDEX. 697 Imitation, II. 408 Immortality, I. 348-9 Impulses, morbid, II. 542 ff. See instincts Impulsiveness of all consciousness, II. 526 ff. Inattention, I. 404, 455 ff. Increase, serial, I. 490 Indeterminism, II. 509 ff. INGEHSOLL, It., II. 469 Inheritance of acquired characters, II. 367, 678 ff. Inhibition, I. 43, 67. 404; II. 126, 373; of instincts, 391, 394; of one cortical process by another, 583 Innervation, feeling of, II. 236, 493; it is unnecessary, 494 ff.; no evi dence for it. 499, 518 , collateral, see vicarious func- t'ion Insane delusions, I. 375; II. 113 Insistent ideas, II. 545 Instinct, Chapter XXIV.; defined, II. 384; is a retlex impulse, 385 ff. ; is neither blind uor invari able, 389; contrary instincts in same animal, 392; man has more than other mammals, 393, 441; their transitoriness, 398; special instincts, 404-441; the origin of instincts, 678 4 Integration ' of feelings, Spencer's theory of, I. 151 ff. Intelligence, the test of its presence, I. 8; of lower brain-centres, 78 ff. Intention to speak, I. 253 Interest, I. 140, 284 ff., 402-3, 482, 515 ff., 572, 594; II. 312 ff., 344-5, 634 Intermediaries, the axiom of skipped, II. 646 Introspection, 1. 185 Inverted head, vision with, II. 213 JACKSON, HUGHLINGS, I. 29, 64, 400; II. 125-6 JANKT. J.. I. 385 JANET, PAUL, I. 625; II. 40-1 JAIIBT, PIERRE, 1.203 ff., 227, 884 ff., 682; II. 456, 614 JASTHOW, 1. 88, 543, 545; II. 44, 135. 180 JKVONS, W. S., I. 406 Joints, their sensibility, II. 189 ff. Judgments, existential, II. 290 Justice, II. 673 KANDINSKY, V., II. 70, 110 KANT, I. 274, 331, 344, 347; his ' transcendental ' deduction of the categories. 360; his paralogisms, 362; criticised, 363-6; on time, 642; on symmetrical figures, II. 150; on space, 273 ff. ; on the real, 296; on synthetic judgments a priori, 661, and their relation to experience, 664 Kinaesthetic feelings, II. 488 ff., 493 * Kleptomania,' II. 425 Knee-jerk, II. 380 Knowing, I. 216 ff. ; psychology as sumes it, 218; not reducible to any other relation, 219, 471, 688 Knowledge, two kinds o", I. 221; of Self not essential to, 274; the ic!:>- tivity of, II. 9 ff. ; the genesis of, 630 ff. Knowledge-afowtf, I. 221 KONIG, I. 542 KKIES, VON, I. 96, 547; II. 253 KRISHABER, I. 377 KUSSMAUL, A., I. 684 LADD, G. T., I., 687; II. 3, 311 LAMARCK, II. 678 LANDRY, II. 490, 492 LANGE, A., I. 29, 284 LANGE, G\, II. 443, 449, 455, 457, 460, 462 LANGE, K., II. Ill LANGE, L., on reaction-time, mus cular and sensorial, I. 92 LANGE, N., on muscular element in imagination, I. 444 Language, as a human function, II. 356-8 LAROMIGUEIRE, I. 247 Laughter, II. 480 LAZARUS, I. 624, 626; II. 84, 97, 369, 429 LE CONTE, JOSEPH, II. 228, 252, 265 LEONIE, M. Janet's trance-subject, I. 201, 387 ff LEVY, W. H., II. 204 LEWES, on frog's sp. cord, I. 9, 78, 134; on thought as a sort of alge bra, 270; on ' preperception,' 439, 442; on muscular feeling, II. 199; on begging in pup, 400; on lapsed intelligence, 678 LEWINSKI, II. 192 LIBERATORS, II. 670 LIEBMAN, O. , on brain as a machine, I. 10; II. 34 LTEGEOIS, J., II. 594, 606 Light, effects of, on movement, II. 379 Likeness, I. 528 LINDSAY, T. L. , II. 421 698 INDEX. LIPPS, on ' unconscious ' sensations, I. 175; on theory of ideas, 603; linie-perceptiou, 632; on muscular feeling, II. 200; on distance, 221; on visual illusions, 251, 264; on space-perception, 280; on reality, 297; on effort, 575 LlSSAUER, I. 50 Local signs, II. 155 ff., 167 Localization, in hemispheres, 1.30 ff. Localization, II. 153 ff.; of one sen sible object in another; II. 31 if., 183 ff., I95ff. LOCKE, J., I. 200, 230, 247, 349, 390, 462, 483, 553, 563, 679; II. 210, 306, 644, 662-4 'LocksleyHall/I. 567 Locomotion, instinct of, II. 405 LOEB, I. 33, 44; II. 255, 516, 628 Logic, II. 647 LOMBARD, J. S., I. 99 LOMBARD, W., II. 380 LOTZE, I. 214; on immortality, 349; on personal identity, 350; on at tention, 442-3; on fusion and dis crimination of sensations, 522; on local signs, II. 157, 495; on volition, 523-4 Louis V., I. 388 Love, sexual, II. 437, 543; parental, 439; Bain's explanation of, 5ol LOWELL, J. R., I. 582 LUCIANI, I. 44-5-6-7, 53, 60. McCosn, I. 501 MACH, E., on attention, I. 436; on space-feeling, 449; on time feel ing, 616, 635; on motion-contrast, II. 247; on optical inversion. 255; on probability, 258; on feeling of in nervation, 509, 511 Magnitude of differences, I. 530 ff. MALEBRANCHE, II. 9 MANOUVRIER, II. 496 Mania, transitory. II. 460 Man's intellectual distinction from brutes, II. 348 ff. MANSEL, H. L .. I. 274 MANTEGAZZA, P., II. 447, 479, 481 MARCUS AURELIUS, I. 313. 317; II. 67"> MARILLIER, L.. I. 445; II. 514 MARIQUE, I. 65 MARTIN, II. N., 99; II. 3 MARTINEAU, J., I. 484 ff., 506; II. 9 MAUDSLEY, H., I. 113, 656 MAURY, A., II. 83, 124, 127 Mechanical philosophv, the. II 666 ff . , Mechanism vs. intelligence, I. 8-14 Mediate comparison, I. 489 Mediumship, I. 228, 393 ff. MEHNER, I. 618 Memory, Chapter XVI : it depends on material conditions, I. 2; the essential function of the hemi spheres, 20; lapses of, 373 ff., in hysterics, 384 ff.; favored by at tention, 427; primary, 638, 643; analysis of the phenomenon of Memory, 648; the return of a mental image is not memory. 649; memory's causes, 653 ff . ; the re sult of association, 654; conditions of good memory, 659; brute re- tentiveness, 660; multiple associa tions, 662; improvement of mem ory, 667 ff . ; its usefulness depends on forgetting much, 680; its decay, 683; metaphysical explanations of it, 687 ff. Mentality, the mark of its presence, I. 8 Mental operations, simultaneous, I. 408 MERCIER, C., on inertness of con sciousness, 135; on inhibition, II. 583 MERKEL, I. 542-3-4 Metaphysical principles, II. 669 ff. Metaphysics, I. 137, 401 Meyer's experiment on color-con trast, II. 21 MEYER, G. H., II. 66, 97-8 MEYNERT, T., his brain-scheme, I. 85, 64, 72 MILL, JAMES, I. 277, 355, 470, 476, 485, 499, 597, 651, 653 II. 77 MILL, J. S., I. 189; on unity of self, 356-9; on abstract ideas, 470; methods of inquiry, 590; on in finitude and association, 600; on space, II. 271; on belief, 285, 322; on reasoning, 331; on the order of Nature, 634; on arithmetical propositions. 654 MILLS, C. K., I. 60 Mimicry, its effects on emotion, II. 463-6 Mind, depends on brain-conditions, I. 4, 553; the mark of its pres ence, 8; difficulty of stating its connection with brain, 176; what psychology means by it, 183, 216 Mind-Stuff theory, Chapter VI: a postulate of evolution, I. 146, 176; some proofs of it, 148; author's interpretation of them, 154; feel- INDEX. ings cannot mix, 157 ff. , II. 2, 103 Miser, association ist explanation of the, II. 423 if. MITCHELL, J. K., II. 616 MITCHELL, S. W., I. 381; II. 38-9, 380 Modesty, II. 435 MOLL, A., II. 616 M LYNEUX, II. 210 Monadism, I. 179 Monism, I. 366-7 Monkey's cortical centres, I. 34-5, 46, 59 MONTGOMERY, E., I. 158 M«ral principles, II. 639, 672 Moiutis, G. S.,1. 365 Mosso, on blood-supply to brain, I. 97-9 , plethysmographic researches, II. 378; on fear, 419, 483 Motor centres, I. 31 if. 'Motor circle,' II. 583 Motor 'strands, I. 38; for special muscles, I. 64 Motor type of imagination, II. 61 Movement, perception of, by sen sory surfaces, II. 171 if.; part played by, in vision, 197.203,234-7; the, Production of, Chap. XXII; requires guiding sensations, 490; illusory perception of, during an aesthesia, 489; results from every kind of consciousness, 526 MOZAHT, I. 255 MULLER, G. E., I. 445, 456-8; II. 198, 280, 491, 502. 508 517 MULLER, J., I. 68; II. 640 MULLER, J. J., II. 213 MULLER, MAX, I. 269 MUNK, II., I. 41-3-4-5-6, 57-8-9, 63 MUNSTERBERG, on Meynert's scheme, I. 77; on reaction times with intellectual operation, 432 : on association, 562; on time-per ception, 6^0, 637; on imagination, II. 74; on muscular sensibility, 189; on volition, 505; on feel ing of innervation, 514; on asso ciation, 590 Muscles, how represented in nerve- centres, I. 19 Muscle reading, II. 525 Muscular sense, its cortical centre, I. 61; its existence, II. 189 if., 197 if.; its insignificance in space-per ception. 197-203, 234-7 Music, its accidental genesis, II. 627; 687 MUSSEY II. 543 Mutilations, inherited, II. 627 MYKKN. F. YV JI., I. 400; II. 133 Mysophobia, II. 435, 545 NATUKK, the order of, its incogru ence with that of our thought, J I 634 if. NAUNYN, I. 55. Necessary truths are all truths of comparison, II. 641 if., 651, <;<>:>. See experience, a priori connections, etc. NEIGLICK, I. 543 Neural process, in perception, I. 78 ff. ; in habit, 105 if. ; in association. 566; in memory, 655; in imagin ation, II. 68 if.; in perception, 82 if , 103 if.; in hallucination, 122 if.; in space-perception, 143; in emotion, 474; in volition, 580 if.; in association, 587 if. Nitrous oxide intoxication, II. 284 Nonsense, how it escapes detection, I. 261 Normal position in vision, II. 238 NOTIINAGUL, I. 51, 60-1 Number, II. 653 OBERSTEINER, I. 87, 445 Object, use of the word, I. 275, 471; confusion of, with thought that knows it, 278 Objective world, known before self, I. 273: its primitive unity, 487-8; ditto, II. 8 Objects versus ideas, I. 230, 278 Old-fogyism, II. 110 OUCIIANSKY, I. 95 ' Overtone ' (psychic), I. 258, 281-2 Pain, I. 143, its relations to the will, II. 549 if., 583-4 PANETII, I. 64, 05 Parallelism, theory of, between mental and cerebral phenomena, see Automaton-theory Paresis of external rectus muscle, II. 236, 507 PARINAUD, II. 7 1 Partiality of mind, see interest, tele ology, intelligence, selection, es sences Past time, known in a present feel ing, I. (VJT: the immediate past is a portion of the present dura tion-block, 608 ff. Patellar reilex, II. 380 Paths throuirh cortex, I. 71; their formation, 107-12; II. 584 if.; association depends on them, 56? 700 INDEX. ff.; memory depends on them, 655 ff., 661, 686 PAULHAN, F., I. 250; 408; 670; II. 64; 476 Pedagogic remarks: I. 121-7; II. 110, 401-2, 409, 463, 466 Perception, Chapter XIX ; com pared with sensation, II. 1, 76; involves reproductive processes, 78; is of probable objects, 82 If.; not an unconscious inference, 111 ff. ; rapidity of, 131 Perception-time, II. 131 PEREZ, B., I. 446; II. 416 Personal equation, I. 413 Personality, alterations of, I. 373 ff. PPLUGER, on frog's spinal cord, I. 9, 134 Philosophies, their test, II. 312 Phosphorus and thought, I. 101 Phrenology, I. 27 PICK, E., I. 669 PITRES, I. 206 Planchette-writing, I. 208-9 ; 393 ff. Plasticity, as basis of habit, defined, I. 105 PLATNER, II. 208 PLATO, I. 462 Play, II. 427 Pleasure, as related to will, I. 143; II. 549; 583-4 Points, identical, theory of, II. 222 Possession, Spirit-, I. 393 ff. Post-hypnotic suggestion, II. 613 Practical interests, their effects on discrimination, I. 515 ff. Prayer, I. 316 ' Preperception,' I. 439 Present, the present moment, I. 606 ff. PREYER, II. 403 Probability determines what object shall be perceived, II. 82, 104, 258, 260-3 Problematic conceptions, I. 463 Problems, the process of solution of, I. 584 Projection of sensations, eccentric, II. 31 if. Projection, theory of, II. 228 Psychologist's fallacy, the, see Fal lacy Psycho-physic law, I. 539 Pugnacity, II. 409 Pure Ego, I. 342 PUTNAM, J. J., I. 61 Questioning mania, II. 284 RABIER, I. 470, 604 Rational propositions, II. 644 Rationality is based on apprehension of series, II. 659 Rationality, postulates of, 670, 677 Rationality, sense of, I. 26U-4; II. 647 Reaction-time, I. 87; simple, 88; what it measures is not conscious thought, 90; Lange'g distinction, between muscular and seusorial, 92; its variations, 94-7; influenced by expectant attention, 427 11'.; after intellectual process, 482; after discrimination, 523; after associa tion, 557; after perception, II. 131 Real size and shape of visual ob jects, II. 179, 237 if. Reality, the Perception of, Chapter XXI; not a distinct content of consciousness, 286; various orders of, 287 ff. ; every object has some kind of reality, 291 ff . ; the choice of, 290; practical, 293 ff.; means relation to the self, 295-8; relation of sensations to, 299; of emotions, 306 Reason, I. 551. See Logic Reasoning, Chapter XXII; its defi nition, II. 325; involves the pick, ing out of essences, or sagacity, 329, and abstraction, 332; its utility depends on the peculiar constitution of this world, 337 ff., 651; depends on association by similarity, 345 Recall, I. 578, 654 'Recepts,' II. 827, 349, 351 Recognition, 673 Recollection, voluntary. 585 ff. REDINTEGRATION, I, 569 'Reductives/II 125, 291 Reflex acts, I. 12; reaction-time measures one, 90; concatenated habits are constituted by a chain of, 116 REID, THOMAS, I. 609, 78; II. 214, 216, 218, 240, 309 Relating principle, I. 687-8 Relation, feelings of, I. 243 fl space relations, II. 148 ff. Relations, inward, between ideas, II. 639, 642, 661, 671; the principle of transferred, 646 Relief, II. 254-7. See third dimen sion. RENOUVIER, CH., I. 551; II. 309 Reproduction in memory, I. 574 ff , 654; voluntary. 585 ff. Resemblance, I. 52.8 INDEX. 701 Respiration, effects of sensory stim uli upon, II. 376 Restitution of function, I. 67 ff. Restoration of function, I. 67 ff. Retention in memory, 653 if. Retentiveness, organic, I. 659 ff.; it is unchangeable, 663 ff. Retinal image, II. 92 Retinal sensibility, see vision, space, identical points, third dime?isio?i, projection, etc. Revival in memory, I. 574 ff., 654 REYNOLDS, MARY, I. 381. RIBOT, TH., I. 375; on attention, 444, 446, 680, 682 RICHET, OH., I. 638, 644-6-7 RIEHL, A., II. 32 ROBERTSON, G. C., I. 461; II. 86 ROMANES, G. J. II. 95, 132 327-9 349, 351, 355, 397 Romantic and classic, II. 469 ROSENTHAL, 79 Ross, J., I. 56-7 ROYCE, J., I. 374; II. 316-7 ROYER-COLLARD, I. 609 RUTHERFORD, II. 170 Sagacity, II. 331, 343 Sameness, I. 272, 459, 480, II. 650 SCIIAEFER, W., I. 35, 53, 59, 63 SCHIFF, M., I. 58, 78, 100 SCHMID, I. 683 SCHMIDT, H. D., II. 399-400 SCHNEIDER, G. H., on Habits, I. 112, 118-20; on perception of motion, II. 173; on evolution of movements, 380; on instincts, 387-8, 411, 418, 439 SCHOPENEIAUER, II. 33, 273 SCHRADER, I. 72 ff. Science, the genesis of, II. 665-9 Sea-sickness, susceptibility to, an accident, II. 627 Seat of consciousness, I. 65; of Soul, 214; of sensations, no original, II. 34 Sciences, the natural, the factors of their production, II. 633 ff.; a Turkish cadi upon, 640 ; pos tulate things with unchangeable properties, 656 Sciences, the pure, they express re sults of comparison 'exclusively, II. 641; classifications, 646; logic, 647; mathematics, 653 Secretiveness, II. 432 SEQUTN, I. 48, 75 Selection, a cardinal function of consciousness, 284 ff., 40'J 591; 11 584; of visual reality. II. 177 ff., 237; of reality in general, 290, 294; of essential quality, 333, 370, 634 Self, consciousness of. Chap. X. not primary, I. 273; the empirical self, I. 291; its constituents, 292; the material self, 292; the social self, 293; the spiritual self, 296: resolvable into feelings localized in head, 300 ff.; consciousness ».l personal identity, 330 ff.; its ul terations, 373 ff. Self-feeling, I. 305 ff. Self-love, I. 317; the name for ac tive impulses and emotions to wards certain objects; we do not love our bare principle of iudi viduality, 323 Self-seeking, I. 307 ff. Selves, their rivalry, I. 309 ff. Semi-reflex acts, I. 13 Sensation, does attention increase its strength? I. 425; terminus of thought, 471 Chapter 1XVII; distinguished from perception, II. 1, 76; its cog nitivc function, 3; pure sensation an abstraction, 3; the terminus ol thought, 7 Sensations, are not compounds, I. 158 ff.; II. 2; their supposed com bination by a higher principle 1. 687; II. 27-30; their iutiu ence on each other, II. 28-30- their eccentric projection, 31 ff., 195 ff.; their localization inside of one another, 183 ff. ; their relation to reality, 299 ff.; to emotions. 453; their fusion, see Mirid-stt/J} tlwory Sensationalism, I. 243; criticised by spiritualism, 687 ditto, II. 5: in the field of space-perception, criticised, 216 ff. ; its difficulties, 231-7; defended 237 ff., 517 SERGI, II. 34 Serial increase, I. 490; II. 644 Series, II. 644-51, 659 ff. SETH, A., II. 4 Sexual function, I. 22 Shadows, colored. II. 25 Shame. II. 435 oKMAKKR, Dr., I. 273 Shyness, II. 430 Sight, its cortical centre, f . 41 ff . 66 Sign-making, a differentia cf a;an, Signs, loca1. II. 155 II. 702 INDEX. SIGWART, C., II. 634-6 SIKORSKY, II. 405 Similarity, I. 528 Similarity, association by, I. 578; II. 345, 353 Skin, discrimination of points on, 1.512 Sleep, partial consciousness during, I. 213 Sociability, II. 430 Somnambulism, see hypnotism, hysterics Soul, theory of the, I. 180; inac cessibility of, 187; its essence is to think (according to Descartes), 200; seat of, 214; arguments for its existence, 343 if.; an unneces sary hypothesis for psychology, 350; compared with transcenden tal Ego, 365; a relating principle, 499 Space, the perception of, Chapter XX; primitive extensity in three dimensions, II. 134-9; spatial order, 145; space-relations, 148; localization in, 153 il. ; how real .%pace is mentally constructed, 166 if. ; part played by movement in, 171-6; measurement of exten sions, 177 if.; synthesis of origi nally chaotic sensations of exten sion, 181 ff . ; part played by articular surfaces in, 189 ff. ; by muscles, 197 If.; how the blind perceive space, 203 if.; visual ipace, 211-268; theory of identical points, 222; of projection, 228; difficulties of sensation-theory expounded and replied to, 231- 268; historical sketch of opinion, 270 ff . SPALDING, D. A., II. 396, 398, 400, 406 Span of consciousness, I. 405, 640 Bpeech, the ' centre ' of, I. 55; its misleading influence in psychol ogy, I. 194; thought possible without it, 269. See Aphasia, Phrenology SPENCER, his formula of 'adjust ment/ I. 6; on formation of paths in nerve-centres, 109; on chasm between mind and matter, 147; on origin of consciousness, 148; on 'integration' of nervous shocks, 151-3; on feelings of relation, 247; on unity of self, 354; on con- ceivability, 464; on abstraction, 506; on association, 600; on time perception, 622, 639; on memory, 649; on recognition, 673; on feel ing and perception, II. 113, 180; on space-perception, 272, 282; on genesis of emotions, 47>S ff.; on free-will, 576; on inheritance of acquired peculiarities, 620 ff., 679; on ' equilibration,' 627; on genesis of cognition, 643; on that of so ciality and pity, 685 SPINOZA, II. 288 SPIR, A., II. 665, 677 'Spirit-control/ I. 228 Spiritualist theory 'of the self, I. 342; II. 5 Spiritualists, I. 161 STANLEY, HENRY M., II. 310 STARR, A., I, 54. 56 Statistical method in psychology, 1. 194 STEINER, I. 72-3 STEINTIIAL, I. 604; II. 107-9 STEPANOFF, II. 170 Stereoscope, II. 87 Stereoscopy, II. 223, 252. See third dimension STERNBERG, II. 105, 515 STEVENS, I. 617 STEVENS, E. W., I. 397 STORY, JEAN, I. 263 Stream of Thought, Chapter IX: schematic representations of, I. 279-82 STRICKER, S., II. 62 ff. STRUMPELL, A., I. 376, 445, 489, 491 STRUMPELL, Prof , II. 353 STTJART, D., I. 406, 427 STUMPF. C., on attention, I. 426 s on difference, 493; on fusion of impressions, 522, 530-3; on strong and weak sensations, 547; on re lativity of knowledge, II. 11; on sensations of extent, 219, 221 Subjective sensations, I. 516 ff. Substance, spiritual, I. 345 Substantive states of mind, I. 243 Substitution of parts for wholes iu reasoning, II. 330; of the same for the same, 650 Subsumption, the principle of medi ate. II. 648 Succession, not known by succes sive feelings, I. 628; vs. duration, 609 Suggestion, in hypnotism, II. 598- (501; post-hypnotic, 613 Suicide, I. 317 SULLY, J., I. 191; II. 79, 221, 272, 281, 322, 425 Summation of stimuli, 1. 82; of el^ INDEX. 703 ments of feeling. 151; the lattei is inadmissible, 158 Superposition, in space-measure merits, II. 177, 266 If. Symbols as substitutes for reality, II. 305 Sympathy, II. 410 Synthetic judgments a priori, II 601-2 Systems, philosophic, sentimental and mechanical, II. 665-7 Tactile centre, I. 58 Tactile images, II. 65 Tactile sensibility, its cortical cen tre, I. 34. 61, 6'3 TAINH:, H., on unity of self, I. 355; on alterations of ditto, 376; on recollecting, 658, 670. On projec tion of sensations, II 83; on images, 48, and their 'reduction/ 125-6; on reality, 291 TAKACS, II. 490 TARDE, G., I. 263 TAYLOR, C. F., II. 99 Tedium. I. 626 Teleology, created by consciousness, I. 140-1; essence of intelligence, 482 involved in the fact of essences, II. 335; its barrenness in the natural sciences, 665 Tendency, feelings of, I. 250-4 THACKERAY, W. M. , II. 434 Thermometry, cerebral, I 99 ' Thing,' II. 184, 259 Thinking, the consciousness of, I. 300 ff. Thinking principle, I. 342 Third dimension of space, II. 134 ff., 212 ff., 220 THOMPSON, D. G., I. 354; II. 662 THOMSON, ALLEN, I. 84 Thought, synonym for con scions- ness at large, I. 186; the stream of. Chapter IX: it tends to personal form, 225; same thought never comes twice, 231 ff.; sense in which it is continuous, 237; can be carried on in any terms, 260-8; what constitutes its rational char acter, 269; is cognitive, 271; not made up of parts, 276 ff., JL 79 ff. ; always partial to some of its ob jects, I. 284 ff. ; the consciousness of it as a process, 300 ff . ; the pres ent thought is the thinker, 369, 401; depends on material condi tions. 553 Thought reading,' II. 525 Time, occupied by neural and mental processes, see reaction-time — unconscious registration of, 201 Time, the perception of, Chapter XV; begins with duration, I. 609; compared with perception of space, 610 ff. ; empty time not perceived, 619; its discrete flow, 621, 637; long intervals conceived symbolically. 622 ff. ; variations in our estimate of its length, 628 ff.; cerebral process underlying, TISCHER, I. 524, 527 Touch, cortical centre for, I. 58 Trance, see hypnotism Transcendentalist theory of the Self I. 342, 360 ff . ; criticised, 363 ff. Transitive states of mind, I. 243 ff. TSCHISCH, VON, I. 414, 560 TUKE, D. H.. II. 130, 413 TAYLOR, E. B.. II. 304 Tympanic membrane, its tacti)e sen sibility, II. 140 TYNDALL, I. 147-8 UEBERWEG, I. 187 Unconscious states of Mind, preofs of their existence, I. 164 ff." Ob jections, 164 ff. Unconsciousness, I. 199 ff. ; in hys terics, 202 ff.; of useless sensa tions, 517 ff. Understanding of a sentence, I. 281 Units, psychic, I. 151 Unity of original object, I. 487-8- II. 8; 183 ff. Universal conceptions, I. 473. See Unreality, the feeling of, II. 298 VALENTIN, I. 557 Varying concomitants, law of disso ciation by, I. 506 VENNTJM, LURANCY, I. 397 Ventriloquism, II. 184 VERDON, R., I. 685 Vertigo, II. 89. Mental vertigo, 309; optical, 506 Vicarious function of brain-parts, I 69, 142; II. 592 VIERORDT, I. 616 if.; II. 154, 172 VlNTSCHGAU, I. 95-6 Vision with head upside down, II. Visual centre in brain, I. 41 ff. Visual space, II. 211 ff. Visualizing power, II. 51-60 Vocalization, II. 407 Volition, see Will 704 INDEX. VOLKMANN, A. W., II. 198, 252 ff YOLKMANN, W. VON VoLKMAK, I. 627, 629, 631. II. 276 Voluminousness, primitive, of sensa tions, II. 134 Voluntary thinking, I. 583 Vulgarity of mind, II. 370 VULPIAN, I. 73 WAHLE, I. 493 WAITZ, TH., I. 405, 632; II. 436 Walking, in child, II. 405 WALTER, J. E., I. 214 WARD, J., I. 162, 454, 548, 562, 629, 633; II. 282 WARREN, J. W., 1. 97 WAYLAND, I. 347 WEBER, E. H., his ' law,' I. 537 ff. On space-perception on skin, II. 141-2; on muscular feeling, 198 WEED, T., I. 665 WEISMANN, A., II. 684 if. Wernicke's convolution, I. 89, 54-5 ' WHEATSTONE'S experiment,' II. 226-7 WIGAN, Dr., I. 390, 675; II. 566-7 WlLBRAND, I. 50-1 Will, Chapter XXVI; involves memory of past acts, and nothing else but consent that they shall occur again, II. 487-518; the • memory may involve images of either resident or remote effects of the movement, 518-22; ideo-mo- tor action, 522-8; action after de liberation, 528; decision, 531; effort, 535; the explosive will, 537; the obstructed will, 546; relation of will to pleasure and pain, 549 if. to attention, 561; terminates in an 'idea', 567; the question of its indeterminism, 569; psychology must assume determinism, 576; neural processes concerned in education of the will, 579 if. Will, relations of, to Belief, II. 320 WILLS, JAS., I. 241 Witchcraft, II. 309 WOLFE, H. K., I. 674, 679 WOLFF, CHR., I. 409, 651 World, the peculiar constitution of the, II. 337, 647, 651-2 Writing, automatic, I 393 if. WUNDT, on frontal lobes, I. 64; on reaction-time, 89-94, 96, 427 ff., 525; on introspective method, 189; on self -consciousness, 303; on per ception of strokes of sound, 407; on perception of simultaneous events, 411 ft' ; on Weber's law, 534 if. ; association-time, 557, 560; on time-perception, 608, 612 ff., 620, 634. On local signs, II. 155- 7; on eyeball-muscles, 200; on sensations, 219; on paresis of ext. rectus, 236: on contrast, 250; on certain illusions, 264; on feeling of innervation, 266,493; on space as synthesis, 276; on emotions, 481; on dichotomic form of thought, 654 Zollner's pattern, II. 232 1 5 1929 PLEASE DO NOT REMOVE CARDS OR SLIPS FROM THIS POCKET UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LIBRARY BF 121 J2 1890 v.2 cop. 3 James, William The principles of psychology.